Skip to main content

Information and Pluralism. Consequences for Scientific Representation and Methods

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Methodological Prospects for Scientific Research

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 430))

Abstract

Both logic and philosophy of science have developed independent pluralistic views. Nevertheless, a general notion of pluralism is quite elusive. This paper will draw on the theory of information, including Shannon’s version and its fundamental concept of coding, to set up a notion of pluralism that may contribute to an updated idea of the scientific method, such as to interact with computational models. I will discuss Patrick Allo’s notion of “informational pluralism” and connect it with Wesley Salmon’s treatment of “statistical relevance” and James Woodward’s analysis of the “data-phenomena” relationship. Based on the concept of information, I will argue that there is a possible convergence of the three views.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Beall and Restall’s formal account of logical pluralism provides the best opportunities for an information-theoretic approach, directed to support scientific methodology. Consequently, this paper will focus on semantic and model-theoretic issues and will be less concerned with modal topics such as necessity, possibility, and consistency. In this line of thought, modal logic will be reduced to a few mentions, mostly concerning the accessibility relation. For an alternative view and a more intense connection between pluralism and modal logic, see Bueno and Shalkowski (2009).

  2. 2.

    If objective information consists of potential data, they plausibly become actual when encoded in the formulae of a language. See Sect. 6.4, below.

  3. 3.

    Russell distinguishes (1) a substitutional account of LC, where non-logical expressions are uniformly substituted throughout the argument by “syntactically appropriate alternative expressions”; (2) an interpretational account, where different meanings replace the meanings of certain non-logical expressions; (3) a representational account, where non-logical expressions are represented by various situations or states of the world; (4) a universal account, where the non-logical vocabulary is uniformly substituted by different assignments of values to non-logical variables. See Russell (2019), 337–339.

  4. 4.

    The concept of informational content has been used by Dretske in his classical analysis. He distinguishes between meaning and information and defines information as “a commodity capable of yielding knowledge” (Dretske 1981, 44). Allo accepts this distinction (Allo 2007, 687), which involves the problem of defining “information.” I am not going to pursue such a thorny question in this paper.

  5. 5.

    Allo shares Floridi’s conception of information as “declarative, objective and semantic information” (See Floridi 2011). But he is also well aware of Dretske’s classical analysis (cf. Dretske 1981).

  6. 6.

    Any theory of channel cannot but be connected to the information theory that Claude Shannon established in 1948.

  7. 7.

    In the second part of this paper, I intend to show that informational pluralism may also impact the philosophy of science.

  8. 8.

    See also Mares’ relation of “accessibility” in Mares (2010), 117, and 125.

  9. 9.

    Restall (1995), 465. See a few more details about the connection between the R&M ternary relation, the concepts of channel and code, in Sect. 6.4, below.

  10. 10.

    Oron Shagrir has written that “Computation is information processing.”

  11. 11.

    Data are recorded (and I think encoded!) observations. Phenomena are defined this way: “facts about phenomena are natural candidates for systematic scientific explanations in a way in which facts about data are not.” (Bogen and Woodward 1988, 326)

  12. 12.

    Bogen and Woodward do not consider models and simulations.

  13. 13.

    More than this, I maintain that the pluralistic features of DPR also lead to the autonomy of computational models. I may even suggest that models, insofar as consisting of interpretive patterns applied to data collections, may be equated to the structures that connect and organize what Woodward calls “phenomena”.

  14. 14.

    For an epistemic synthesis of Woodward’s ideas about causality, see Gonzalez 2018.

  15. 15.

    This is based on the well-known equivalence – asserted by Claude Shannon (1998, 40) – between a discrete information source and a stochastic process.

  16. 16.

    Besides the equivalence between situations and classes, we may recall other important computational equivalences, such as that between propositions and types, which is the basis of the fundamental Curry-Howard Isomorphism.

  17. 17.

    See Salmon (1967), 58–62 and 108–131; see also Salmon (1970).

  18. 18.

    I am slightly departing from Salmon’s account at this point.

  19. 19.

    Salmon was aware that computability theory was needed for the crucial problem of the construction of objectively homogeneous reference classes (see Salmon 1984, 58–60, 67–68, 81). As for information theory, see Salmon 1984, in particular, 97–101, 125–126, 139–154. S-R approach has been recently updated in informational terms, especially via the notion of “causal power”. This represents the degree to which changes in a cause C produce changes in an effect E. Causal power uses relevance logic to cover not only conditional probabilities and statistical datasets but also Bayesian Networks used in Artificial Intelligence. Causal power is measured using Shannon’s entropy concept (Korb et al. 2009).

  20. 20.

    The completeness of partitions provides to Salmon’s S-R models the character of objectivity that distinguishes them from Hempel’s I-S models (Salmon 1984, 41). Completeness is granted by the maximal homogeneity of both explanans and explanandum partitions (Salmon 1984, 37). It is also to be mentioned that Salmon’s objective homogeneity is the same thing as Shannon’s “ergodicity,” roughly defined as “statistical homogeneity” (Shannon 1998, 45), and reputed to be essential for the final Theorem 11 of Information theory (cf. Kinchin 1957).

  21. 21.

    Salmon’s and Greeno’s visible source is Kullback’s classical treatise Information Theory and Statistics. Kullback supplements Shannon’s concepts with the works of Fisher on information (cf. Kullback 1968). However, apart from Salmon’s theory, it is crucial to shift from Fisher’s to Shannon’s view. In doing so, we gain an intensional perspective on statistical types that is the premise for being able to build computational models. Sayre also misses this point.

References

  • Abramson, N. (1963). Information theory and coding. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allo, P. (2007). Logical pluralism and semantic information. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 36, 659–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allo, P., & Mares, E. (2012). Informational semantics as a third alternative? Erkenntnis, 77, 167–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. (1993). Constraints, channels, and the flow of information. In P. Aczel, D. Israel, S. Peters, & Y. Katagiri (Eds.), Situation theory and its applications (pp. 3–27). Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Seligman, J. (1997). Information flow: The logic of distributed systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Restall, G. (2000). Logical pluralism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 475–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berstel, J., & Perrin, D. (2010). Codes and automata. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, R. (2012). Fluid convection, constraint and causation. Interface Focus, 2, 4–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J., & Woodward, J. (1988). Saving the phenomena. The Philosophical Review, 97, 303–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J., & Woodward, J. (2003). Evading the IRS. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Science and Humanities, 20, 223–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2009). Modalism and logical pluralism. Mind, 118, 295–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camardi, G. (2012). Computational models and information theory. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 24, 401–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caret, C. (2019). Why logical pluralism? Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02132-w. Accessed on 06 Sept 2019.

  • Cook, R. (2019). Pluralism about pluralisms. In J. Wyatt, N. J. L. L. Pedersen, & N. Kellen (Eds.), Pluralism in truth and logic (pp. 365–386). Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cover, T., & Thomas, J. (2006). Elements of information theory. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flux of information. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2002). Fixpoint semantics for logic programming. Theoretical Computer Science, 278, 25–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2011). The philosophy of information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2010). Causal pluralism. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 326–337). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W. J. (2018). Configuration of causality and philosophy of psychology: An analysis of causality as intervention and its repercussion for psychology. In W. J. Gonzalez (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology: Causality and psychological subject. New reflections on James Woodward’s contribution (pp. 21–70). Boston/Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, E. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In L. Paul, E. Hall, & J. Collins (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamming, R. W. (1986). Coding and information theory. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankerson, D., Harris, G., & Johnson, P. (2003). Introduction to information theory and data compression. Boca Raton: Chapman and Hall/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. (2011). Why theories of causality need production: An information transmission account. Philosophy and Technology, 24, 95–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kinchin. (1957). Mathematical foundations of information theory. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korb, K., Hope, L., & Nyberg, E. (2009). Information-theoretic causal power. In F. Emmert-Streiss & M. Dehmer (Eds.), Information theory and statistical learning. Berlin/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kullback, S. (1968). Information theory and statistics. Mineola: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli, S. (2008). Performing abstraction. Two ways of modeling Arabidopsis Thaliana. Biology and Philosophy, 23, 509–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80, 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. (1997). Relevant logics and the theory of information. Synthese, 109, 345–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. (2006). Relevant logics, probabilistic information and conditionals. Logique et Analyse, 196, 399–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. (2010). The nature of information: A relevant approach. Synthese, 175, 111–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E., & Meyer, R. K. (2001). Relevant logics. In L. Goble (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic (pp. 280–308). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality: Models, mathematics, and simulations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’ Donnell, M. (1998). Introduction: Logic and logic programming languages. In D. Gabbay, C. Hogger, & J. Robinson (Eds.), Handbook of logic in artificial intelligence and logic programming (pp. 1–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Padmanabhan, K., et al. (2013). In situ exploratory data analysis for scientific discovery. In T. Critchlow & K. K. van Dam (Eds.), Data intensive science (pp. 301–350). Boca Raton: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. (1995). Information flow and relevant logic. In J. Seligman & D. Westerstähl (Eds.), Logic, language and computation: The 1994 Moraga proceedings (pp. 463–477). Stanford: CSLI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, G. (2019). Varieties of logical consequence by their resistance to logical nihilism. In J. Wyatt, N. J. L. L. Pedersen, & N. Kellen (Eds.), Pluralism in truth and logic (pp. 331–361). Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1967). Foundations of scientific inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1970). Bayes’s theorem and the history of science. In R. Stuewer (Ed.), Historical and philosophical perspectives of science (pp. 68–86). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1977). An “at-at” theory of causal influence. Philosophy of Science, 44, 215–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1994). Causality without counterfactual. Philosophy of Science, 61, 297–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sayre, K. (1977). Statistical models of causal relations. Philosophy of Science, 44, 203–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1998). The mathematical theory of communication [1948]. Repr. In C. Shannon & W. Weaver (eds) The mathematical theory of communication (pp. 29–125). Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapere, D. (1982). The concept of observation in science and in philosophy. Philosophy of Science, 49, 485–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth. An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, R. (2009). Computable models. London: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Emden, M., & Kowalski, R. (1976). The semantics of predicate logic programming language. Journal of the ACM, 23, 733–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Mises, R. (1981). Probability, statistics and truth. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. In A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2011). Data and phenomena. A restatement and defense. Synthese, 182, 165–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Camardi, G. (2020). Information and Pluralism. Consequences for Scientific Representation and Methods. In: Gonzalez, W.J. (eds) Methodological Prospects for Scientific Research. Synthese Library, vol 430. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-52500-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics