Skip to main content

Ayer’s Book of Errors and the Crises of Contemporary Western Culture

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic

Part of the book series: History of Analytic Philosophy ((History of Analytic Philosophy))

Abstract

This essay takes the position, consistent with Ayer’s own retrospective judgments, that the philosophical significance of Language, Truth and Logic (LTL) was minimal at best, and that its real significance was socio-historical. LTL stands as one of the most influential expressions of an overzealous and simplistic scientism that swept through Western culture in the first half of the twentieth century. This scientism played a crucial role in problematizing the West’s relationship to truth in ways that contributed to the eventual emergence of “post-truth” culture, with its “post-truth politics.” This in turn made possible the disastrous results of recent votes and elections in Britain and, above all, in the United States. In short, LTL’s real significance resides in the role it played as a sophisticated and successful bit of propaganda for an ideology that played a crucial role in loosing Western culture from its moral and epistemic moorings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I wish to thank Adam Tamas Tuboly and an anonymous reviewer for very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay. All page references to Language, Truth and Logic below are to the second edition of 1946; see Ayer (1936/1946), noted in the text as “LTL.”

  2. 2.

    If one takes philosophical significance to be more about articulating novel ideas that stimulate further philosophical efforts than about getting things right, then LTL could be said to have great philosophical significance. I find such a view unsatisfactory because it confuses means with ends. For most of philosophy’s history, the attainment of knowledge was taken either to be, or at least to be central to, its main objective. Knowledge, in turn, was understood to be the accurate (i.e., true) representation of some fraction—or perhaps the whole—of reality. I take this traditional view to be normative for the discipline. Consequently, I see philosophical significance, in the primary and unqualified sense of the term, as having to do with the attainment, through philosophizing, of more or better knowledge—that is, in getting things substantially right—for only in such attainment is the objective of philosophy achieved. By contrast, stimuli to philosophizing—from the Pythia’s words about Socrates, to Aristotle’s “wonder,” to the puzzling statements of certain British Idealists that drove G.E. Moore to philosophize—are better construed as means to philosophical ends than as attainments of those ends. Clearly, such phenomena bear some significance for philosophy, and one might call this “philosophical significance” in some sense. But not in the primary sense. So at most, LTL could have “philosophical significance” in this secondary sense; however, even this affirmation must be tempered by a sober estimation of LTL’s deficiencies. As we shall see, Ayer’s positivism caught-on not because of its plausibility, but because of its usefulness in challenging certain traditional views and the unnecessarily restrictive or oppressive social practices they supported. In fact, LTL got things so thoroughly wrong that, within a few decades of its publication (after its social usefulness was exhausted), no serious defenders of Ayer’s positivism remained. Such a work can only be seen as seriously philosophically deficient, precisely because the ideas advanced therein were not very plausible candidates for knowledge. The case of LTL is very unlike those of, say, the key works of Plato and Aristotle, whose central ideas in metaphysics and ethics, at least, have proven incredibly resilient despite millennia of criticism.

  3. 3.

    For a compendium of problems , see Joad (1950) and Blanshard (1962).

  4. 4.

    There is a widely shared view among scholars of Logical Positivism that LTL oversimplifies positivism so much that it is really more a distortion than an expression of the positivist position. And, of course, merely speaking of “the positivist position” involves a certain amount of oversimplification, as there was always considerable diversity of opinion among leading positivist thinkers, such as those associated with the Vienna Circle. It should also be said that most of these thinkers had deep moral convictions and did not think their views about the limits of knowledge posed any problem for maintaining and promoting those convictions. Nonetheless, this essay and this book are concerned specifically with the historical and philosophical significance of LTL. Consequently, it is specifically the significance of LTL and its version of positivism that are in focus here. Whether a more sophisticated version of positivism would have had different cultural consequences had it, instead of Ayer’s, captured the popular mind, is an interesting question, but not one we shall pursue here.

  5. 5.

    It was at the 1933 Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association that A.J. Ayer declared to old-guard metaphysicians that “You’re lost! The forces of Cambridge and Vienna are descending upon you!” See Rogers (1999, 104); cf. Nagel (1936, 9).

  6. 6.

    “Confirms” is meant to include both cases in which Ayer makes an assertion and cases in which he affirms an assertion made by Magee.

  7. 7.

    The paper, no longer extant, was read at a meeting of the Jowett Society. Cf. Rogers (1999, 73).

  8. 8.

    Largely forgotten today, in the 1940s Joad was one of Britain’s leading public intellectuals. Head of philosophy and psychology at the University of London’s Birkbeck College, he wrote numerous books for the educated public and was a frequent contributor to the British Broadcasting Corporation (BBC)’s Brains Trust program from 1941 to 1947. Presumably, due to his having spent the 1930s outside of Oxford, Joad seems unaware of the immediate impact LTL had had on student culture there.

  9. 9.

    See Ingarden (1936/2018) and the accompanying discussion in Pelletier and Linsky (2018). Cf. with Hempel (1950, 1951). On the history and status of verificationism, see Uebel (2019).

  10. 10.

    Oxonian was Churchill’s nephew, the journalist Giles Romilly, who had been a student in Oxford in the 1930s before becoming a war correspondent. On the history and context of Joad’s and Romilly’s charges, see Tuboly (2020).

  11. 11.

    For a longer discussion of this background than I can give here, see the first section of Willard (2018, Ch. 4).

  12. 12.

    Specifically, the principle of verification generalized physicist Percy Bridgman’s (1927) “operationalism.” Bridgman himself had doubts about operationalism’s applicability outside of physics, let alone as a general theory of meaning. See Nelson (2009, 63–64). But more generally the positivists presented themselves as promulgating a “scientific world-picture” the rudiments of which had been established by others. See Carnap et al. (1929/1973).

  13. 13.

    Ayer’s biographer notes that, over its first three decades in print, LTL sold three times more copies in America (~300,000 copies) than in Britain (~100,000 copies). See Rogers (1999, 217).

  14. 14.

    Anonymous (2018). “I am part of the resistance inside the Trump administration.” New York Times, Sept. 5, 2018. https://www.nytimes.com/2018/09/05/opinion/trump-white-house-anonymous-resistance.html

  15. 15.

    https://abcnews.go.com/Site/transcript-james-comeys-interview-abc-news-chief-anchor/story?id=54488723

  16. 16.

    https://www.politifact.com/personalities/donald-trump/, accessed 8/13/2019. Trump’s truth scores have actually worsened by about 1% overall since I wrote the first draft of this paper in the summer of 2018.

  17. 17.

    “Post Truth” is defined as “relating to or denoting circumstances in which objective facts are less influential in shaping public opinion than appeals to emotion and personal belief.” As we shall see, it is no mere coincidence that emotion is named as the alternative to fact, for this is precisely the alternative supplied by emotivism. See also Gelfert (2018) and Dahms (2021).

  18. 18.

    https://www.merriam-webster.com/news-trend-watch/vox-america-is-facing-epistemic-crisis-20171102

  19. 19.

    See “The post-truth world: Yes, I’d lie to you.” The Economist, Sept 10, 2016; see also Mallinder (2018). Wikipedia’s entry on “Post-truth politics” includes a useful set of references to allegations of post-truth politics made in the media. <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Post-truth_politics> All of these were accessed on 8/13/19.

  20. 20.

    <https://gfds.de/wort-des-jahres-2016/>

  21. 21.

    In a speech given on Sept. 7, 2018 at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Full transcript available at: https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/politics/elections/2018/09/07/president-barack-obamas-speech-transcript-slamming-trump/1225554002/

  22. 22.

    David Roberts, “Donald Trump and the rise of tribal epistemology,” Vox, May 19, 2017. https://www.vox.com/policy-and-politics/2017/3/22/14762030/donald-trump-tribal-epistemology

  23. 23.

    For a nuanced discussion of relativism, including the varieties Bloom has in focus, see Baghramian and Carter (2018).

  24. 24.

    Again, many experts on logical positivism would insist that, like the “positivism” of LTL, this was a crude oversimplification of the true positivist vision.

  25. 25.

    In this volume, other minds and philosophy of mind are discussed in more details by Gergely Ambrus and Thomas Uebel; analyticity is taken up by Nichole Rathgeb; verification is the subject of Hans-Johann Glock; finally, Ayer’s theory of truth is the topic of László Kocsis.

  26. 26.

    “When the terms are completely neutralized [of emotion], we may say with tranquility that all moralists are propagandists, or that all propagandists are moralists.” See Stevenson (1944, 30, 113, original emphasis).

  27. 27.

    This fact is fundamental to what Stefan Collini has called “the paradox at the heart of Ayer’s career as an intellectual: the authority of his public role rested on his professional identity as a philosopher, but his declared philosophical position was that philosophy could have little to say on the issues that were of public interest” (Collini 2006, 398). More pointedly, Ayer’s status as a public intellectual depended on the notion that, as a member of the professoriate, he could speak with intellectual authority on moral and political matters; however, by his own positivist principles, these were matters of subjective preference relative to which his status as a member of the professoriate gave him no special authority. Thus, Ayer quite self-consciously understood his role as a public intellectual to be that of a propagandist: as a philosopher, he had no special knowledge about how to live, but only “a certain advantage in putting [his opinions] persuasively” (Ayer 1947/1990, 16–17).

References

  • Ayer, Alfred J. 1936/1946. Language, Truth and Logic. 2nd ed. London: Victor Gollancz.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1947/1990. The Claims of Philosophy. In The Meaning of Life and Other Essays, 1–17. London: Weidenfeld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baghramian, Maria, and J. Adam Carter. 2018. Relativism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/relativism/

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 1973. Austin and the Early Beginnings of Oxford Philosophy. In Essays on J.L. Austin, 1–16. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanshard, Brand. 1961. Reason and Goodness. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1962. Reason and Analysis. LaSalle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Alan. 1982. Our Listless Universities. National Review, December 10, 1537–1548.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, Percy W. 1927. The Logic of Modern Physics. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf, Otto Neurath, and Hans Hahn. 1929/1973. The Scientific Conception of the Word: The Vienna Circle. In Empiricism and Sociology, ed. Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen, 299–318. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collini, Stefan. 2006. Absent Minds: Intellectuals in Britain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahms, Hans-Joachim. 2021. Alternative Facts, Fake News, Pseudo-Science: New Challenges for Logical Empiricism. In The Socio-Ethical Dimension of Knowledge: The Mission of Logical Empiricism, ed. Christian Damböck and Adam Tamas Tuboly. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubnov, Arie M. 2012. Isaiah Berlin: The Journey of a Jewish Liberal. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1986/2005. On Bullshit. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, Axel. 2018. Fake News: A Definition. Informal Logic 38 (1): 84–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1950. Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 41 (11): 41–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1951. The Concept of Cognitive Significance: A Reconsideration. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 80 (1): 61–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, James Davison. 2000. The Death of Character: Moral Education in an Age Without Good or Evil. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutten, E.J. 1951. Review of Joad’s The Critique of Logical Positivism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 2 (6): 172–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, Roman. 1936/2018. The Logical Attempt at a New Formulation of Philosophy: A Critical Remark. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (6), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joad, C.E.M. 1948. Logical Positivism, Fascism and Value. The New Statesman and Nation, July 31, 91–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1950. A Critique of Logical Positivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Bandy, ed. 2017. The Dangerous Case of Donald Trump. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter, Brian. 2017. “Realism and Moralism in Political Thought.” Paolo Bozzi Prize Address for the conference on “Post-Truth, New Realism, Democracy,” University of Turin, Italy. Excerpted at the Leiter Reports blog: https://leiterreports.typepad.com/blog/2017/10/the-internet-and-the-crisis-of-epistemic-authority.html. Accessed 8/13/19.

  • Magee, Bryan. 1978. Men of Ideas: Some Creators of Contemporary Philosophy. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Confessions of a Philosopher. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallinder, Lorraine. 2018. Inside Hungary’s Post-truth Laboratory. The New Internationalist, 7/1/18.

    Google Scholar 

  • McBrayer, Justin. 2015. Why Our Children Don’t Think There Are Moral Facts. New York Times, March 2. https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2015/03/02/why-our-children-dont-think-there-are-moral-facts/

  • Midgley, Mary. 2005. The Owl of Minerva. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Ernest. 1936. Impressions and Appraisals of Analytic Philosophy in Europe, I. The Journal of Philosophy 33 (1): 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, James M. 2009. Psychology, Religion, and Spirituality. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1987. Undemocratic Vistas. The New York Review of Books, November 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oxonian. 1948. Visit to Oxford. The New Statesman and Nation, June 26, 518–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, Francis Jeffry, and Bernard Linsky. 2018. Verification: The Hysteron Proteron Argument. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (6), 7–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, Aaron. 2006. Positivism. In The Continuum Encyclopedia of British Philosophy, ed. A.C. Grayling, Andrew Pyle, and Naomi Goulder, vol. 3. London/New York: Thoemmes Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Analytic Philosophy: The History of an Illusion. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purcell, Edward A., Jr. 1973. The Crisis of Democratic Theory: Scientific Naturalism and the Problem of Value. Lexington: University Press of Kentucky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ravitch, Diane. 2000. A Century of Failed School Reforms. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuben, Julie. 1996. The Making of the Modern University: Intellectual Transformation and the Marginalization of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, David. 2017a. America Is Facing an Epistemic Crisis. Vox, November 2. https://www.vox.com/policy-and-politics/2017/11/2/16588964/america-epistemic-crisis

  • ———. 2017b. Donald Trump and the Rise of Tribal Epistemology. Vox, May 19. https://www.vox.com/policy-and-politics/2017/3/22/14762030/donald-trump-tribal-epistemology

  • Schilpp, Paul Arthur. 1959. The Abdication of Philosophy. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 32: 19–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, Laura. 2006. Reforming Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, Charles L. 1944. Ethics and Language. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, Ben. 1999. A.J. Ayer: A Life. New York: Grove Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomlin, E.W.F. 1936. Logical Negativism. Scrutiny, September, 200–2018.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuboly, Adam Tamas. 2020. A Cricket Game, a Train Ticket and a Vacuum to Be Filled: Ayer’s Logical Positivism as a Focal Point for Post-war British Cultural Struggles. British Journal for the History of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2020.1731681.

  • Uebel, Thomas. 2007. Empiricism at the Crossroads: The Vienna Circle’s Protocol-Sentence Debate. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Verificationism and Its Discontents. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 7 (4), 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, Bas C. 2002. The Empirical Stance. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varghese, Roy Abraham, ed. 1998. Great Thinkers on Great Questions. Oxford: Oneworld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, Mary. 1961. Ethics Since 1900. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willard, Dallas. 2018. The Disappearance of Moral Knowledge, ed. and completed by Steven Porter, Aaron Preston, and Gregg TenElshof. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aaron Preston .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Preston, A. (2021). Ayer’s Book of Errors and the Crises of Contemporary Western Culture. In: Tuboly, A.T. (eds) The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic. History of Analytic Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-50884-5_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics