A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?,Physical Review, 47, 777–780 (1935).

2.1 Reprint of the Paper

Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, Physical Review, Volume 47, Page 777–780, published in 1935 by the American Physical Society. Reprinted with permission https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRev.47.777

2.2 Critical Summary

The paper by Einstein, Rosen and Podolsky, that we shall call the EPR paper in the following , is not long. It is a little less than four pages long and does not contain any references to other publications. It was submitted to Physical Review on March 25, 1935, and published on May 15, 1935.

Besides an introduction, the EPR paper consists of two chapters without heading. In the first part, the authors claim that there is a difference between an assumed objective reality and its description through a physical theory:

Any serious consideration of a physical theory must take into account the distinction between the objective reality, which is independent of any theory, and the physical concepts with which the theory operates.

They continue to stress that the success of a theory should be determined by asking the following questions. First: Is the theory correct? Second: Is the description given by the theory complete? To answer the first question, the authors refer to the agreement with measurement outcomes; this question is not going to be the subject of their paper. The EPR paper focusses on the question of completeness, as implied in the paper’s title.

What is completeness supposed to mean? Quantum mechanical states are described through wave functions (more generally: vectors in Hilbert space). If this description is complete, i.e., if no further (‘hidden’) variables exist that would allow for a simultaneous determination of, e.g., position and momentum, then, the theory shall be called complete.

EPR propose the following, necessary criterion for completeness, which according to them seems unavoidable:

[…] every element of the physical reality must have a counterpart in the physical theory.

In a letter to Schrödinger on June 19, 1935, Einstein wrote more specifically:

In quantum mechanics, one describes a real state of affairs of a system by means of a normed function Ψ of the coordinates (of configuration space). The temporal evolution is uniquely determined by the Schrödinger equation. One would now very much like to say the following: Ψ stands in a one-to-one correspondence with the real state of the real system. The statistical character of measurement outcomes is exclusively due to the measurement apparatus, or the process of measurement. If this works, I talk about a complete description of reality by the theory. However, if such an interpretation doesn’t work out, then I call the theoretical description ‘incomplete’.Footnote 1

In order to apply this criterion one needs to know what elements of physical reality are. Then, according to the authors, the question of completeness can be easily answered. On these grounds they present a criterion that they consider sufficient for their purpose. It is this criterion of reality that would cause much concern and many misunderstandings later on. It goes like this (italics by EPR):

If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity.

The key passage here is “without in any way disturbing a system”. We will get back to this.

The first part of the EPR paper focuses on the quantum mechanical description of a particle in a single space dimension. The authors highlight the fundamental importance of the notion of a state, “which is supposed to be completely characterised by the wave function Ψ.” According to quantum mechanics, Ψ renders a complete description. Further, the authors assume the validity of the probability interpretation . It states that the probabilities of measuring certain values of classical quantities can be obtained from the square of Ψ’s absolute value.

Now, if Ψ is the eigenfunction of an operator A with eigenvalue a, the probability interpretation holds that the physical quantity given by the operator A (such a physical quantity is called an observable in quantum theory) will in this state have the value a with certainty. EPR apply their reality criterion to this situation and infer from it that in this eigenstate an element of physical reality exists which corresponds to the physical quantity A. They take a momentum eigenstate with eigenvalue p 0 as an exampleFootnote 2 and conclude that it is thus reasonable to say that momentum of the particle in this state is real.

If the state is not an eigenstate of the operator A, one cannot deduce this anymore: There is no longer a certain value ascribed to the physical quantity described by A. Take the case where you ask for coordinate values of a particle (corresponding to its position) that currently is in a momentum eigenstate. As a matter of fact, in this case all coordinate values have the same probability! According to EPR, the only way to obtain a specific value for the coordinate is through a direct measurement, which, however, disturbs the particle and its state; the particle then no longer is in the momentum eigenstate. Interestingly, EPR assume a collapse (or reduction) of the wave function , i.e., a violation of Schrödinger’s equation, cf. Sect. 1.4; as was common back then, they do not describe this collapse dynamically but insert it by hand. EPR go on to generalise their conclusions and emphasise that, according to quantum mechanics (where the description through a wave function is considered complete), when the operators corresponding to two physical quantities do not commute, the two quantities cannot have simultaneous reality.

The conclusion of the first part of the EPR paper can thus be summarised as follows. Consider the two propositions:

  1. P1

    The description of reality with wave functions is complete.

  2. P2

    When the operators corresponding to two physical quantities do not commute, the two physical quantities have simultaneous reality.

EPR’s conclusion then is that either P 1 or P 2 is false. That is, either the description of reality with wave functions is incomplete, or non-commuting quantities cannot be simultaneously real. It is important to note that the phrasing is “not simultaneously real” instead of “not simultaneously measured”: the authors do not doubt that non-commuting quantities cannot be measured simultaneously. Up to this point, the paper contains a mostly non-controversial application of the quantum formalism as would be expected in 1935. The second part ist the controversial one. Herein, EPR find that the result of the first part leads to a contradiction.

They demonstrate this with the help of a thought experiment (remember Einstein’s fondness for thought experiments). In it, they consider two systems I and II that interact for a certain time, but are disconnected ever after. Think, e.g., of a decay of a particle resulting in two new particles that fly away in opposite directions and that, in principle, can be separated by arbitrarily large distances. EPR assume that at the beginning both systems are described by states on their own (each by its own wave function), and that these states are known. Following the interaction, there is only one (today we call it entangled) wave function Ψ for the combined system I plus II. The two subsystems do not have a state (a wave function) on their own anymore.

EPR now assume that a measurement is taken on one of the two systems (system I), leading to a collapse (or reduction) of the wave function. As they put it in the first paragraph of part 2.:

We cannot, however, calculate the state in which either one of the two systems is left after the interaction. This, according to quantum mechanics, can be done only with the help of further measurements, by a process known as the reduction of the wave packet. Let us consider the essentials of this process.

EPR now consider (as part of the thought experiment) measurements that are conducted on system I alone. To this end, they consider two different physical quantities (observables) A and B in I. The combined wave functionFootnote 3 Ψ(x 1, x 2) can then be expanded either in terms of the eigenfunctions of the operator A (EPR’s equation (7)) or in terms of the eigenfunctions of the operator B (EPR’s equation (8)). If one now measures in system I the quantity A, one finds a certain value a k and the corresponding eigenfunction u k(x 1). According to the postulate of the reduction of a wave function, the wave function in EPR’s equation (7) is thus reduced to a product Ψ(x 1, x 2) = ψ k(x 2)u k(x 1). But that means that the system II, on which no measurements can be taken (and that by consequence was not ‘disturbed’), now is in a concrete state, namely the one given by ψ k(x 2). The entanglement of the two systems is broken; the new state of the system is a product and therefore no longer describes a correlation between systems I and II.

But instead of A one can also measure quantity B in I, yielding a value b r and an eigenfunction v r(x 1). The combined wave function thus reduces to a different product, namely Ψ(x 1, x 2) = φ s(x 2)v s(x 1). EPR conclude from this:

We see therefore that, as a consequence of two different measurements performed upon the first system, the second system may be left in states with two different wave functions.

According to EPR, one can therefore assign two different wave functions to the same reality. They consider especially important the case where the alternative wave functions ψ k and φ s of system II are eigenfunctions of non-commuting operators P and Q. EPR’s example for this case is so important that we shall discuss it explicitly. This means that our discussion will become somewhat formal now. However, the conclusions drawn from it can be understood without a detailed knowledge of the formalism.

In their example, systems I and II are two particles I and II that have a common wave function Ψ(x 1, x 2). EPR choose the following form of the wave function:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \varPsi(x_1,x_2)=h\delta(x_1-x_2+x_0) \equiv \int_{-\infty}^{\infty}\mathrm{d}p\ \mathrm{e}^{2\pi\mathrm{i}(x_1-x_2+x_0)p/h}, \end{aligned} $$
(2.1)

where x 0 is a constant and h is Planck’s constant. Due to the delta function the difference of x 2 and x 1 is virtually fixed to x 0.

Now A is the momentum operator Footnote 4 of particle I, whose eigenfunctions read:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} u_p(x_1)=\mathrm{e}^{2\pi\mathrm{i}px_1/h}, \end{aligned} $$
(2.2)

where the usual normalisation constant is missing and where the number p is the eigenvalue. The combined state (2.1) can now be expanded in terms of these momentum eigenfunctions:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \varPsi(x_1,x_2)=\int_{-\infty}^{\infty}\mathrm{d}p\ \psi_p(x_2)u_p(x_1), \end{aligned} $$
(2.3)

where

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \psi_p(x_2):=\mathrm{e}^{-2\pi\mathrm{i}(x_2-x_0)p/h} \end{aligned} $$
(2.4)

is the eigenfunction of the momentum operator of particle II, itself given by

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} P:=\frac{h}{2\pi \mathrm{i}}\frac{\partial}{\partial x_2}. \end{aligned}$$

P’s eigenvalue is − p, which is of course a direct consequence of momentum conservation: The total momentum of the initial state is zero and retains that value (as long as no measurement of position is taken on any of the particles).

Now EPR consider an alternative where B is the position operator of particle I, whose (improper) eigenfunction v x is the delta function:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} v_x(x_1)=\delta(x_1-x). \end{aligned} $$
(2.5)

Then one can expand the combined state (2.1) in terms of these position eigenfunctions instead of the momentum eigenfunctions:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \varPsi(x_1,x_2)=\int_{-\infty}^{\infty}\mathrm{d}x\ \varphi_x(x_2)v_x(x_1), \end{aligned} $$
(2.6)

where

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \varphi_x(x_2):= \int_{-\infty}^{\infty}\mathrm{d}p\ \mathrm{e}^{2\pi\mathrm{i}(x-x_2+x_0)p/h}=h\delta(x-x_2+x_0) \end{aligned} $$
(2.7)

is the eigenfunction of the position operator Q = x 2 of particle II. Its eigenvalue is x + x 0, this being the coordinate value of particle II.Footnote 5 Because

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}{}[P,Q]\equiv PQ-QP=\frac{h}{2\pi\mathrm{i}}, \end{aligned}$$

Ψ p(x 2) and φ x(x 2) are indeed eigenfunctions of non-commuting operators, namely of position and momentum of particle II. Non-commuting operators correspond to physical quantities that cannot be measured simultaneously and are therefore subject to an uncertainty relation.

This is EPR’s example, a special case of the general situation they had presented in the beginning of their second part. EPR now get back to their general discussion and reach a conclusion. They assume that the wave functions Ψ k and φ r of system II are eigenfunctions of non-commuting operators P and Q with eigenvalues p k and q r, respectively. The (thought of) experimenter now has a free choice to take on system I a measurement of A or B. If he chooses to measure A, system II will be described by the wave function Ψ k(x 2) (in the above example this is Ψ p(x 2) in (2.4)) with eigenvalue p k (above: p). If he chooses to measure B in I, the wave function of II will be φ r(x 2) (above: φ x(x 2)) with eigenvalue q r. But in neither case system II is being disturbed! EPR now bring forward their reality criterion a second time:

In accordance with our criterion of reality, in the first case we must consider the quantity P as being an element of reality, in the second case the quantity Q is an element of reality. But, as we have seen, both wave functions Ψ k and φ r belong to the same reality.

The EPR paper now concludes as follows. In the first part, EPR found that of the two propositions P 1 and P 2 either P 1 or P 2 is false, i.e., either the description with wave functions is incomplete or non-commuting quantities do not have simultaneous reality. In the second part, they found P 1 ⇒ P 2, i.e., that the simultaneous reality of physical quantities corresponding to non-commuting operators follows from the assumption of completeness. According to the rules of elementary logic the findings of both parts of the paper are both true only if either P 1 and P 2 are both false or if P 1 is false and P 2 is true. Since EPR’s thought experiment showed P 2 to be true (under the assumption of separability), P 1 must be false; i.e., the description of reality with wave functions is incomplete. This is the essential conclusion of the EPR paper.

As a matter of fact, the trueness of proposition P 2 follows directly from the locality criterion or from separability (although these notionsFootnote 6 are not mentioned directly in the paper): events in system I cannot affect the spatially separated system II (it is too far out). In their second part, EPR only show P 2 to be true if one assumes locality: P 1 is not really involved. One can deduce directly from the result of part I (either P 1 or P 2 false) that P 1 must be false, i.e., that i.e., that the description with wave functions is incomplete. These are EPR’s closing remarks:

While we have thus shown that the wave function does not provide a complete description of the physical reality, we left open the question of whether or not such a description exists. We believe, however, that such a theory is possible.

However, they did not conclude their paper without having presented a possible loop-hole through which one could avoid the conclusion of quantum theory’s incompleteness (second last paragraph):

Indeed, one would not arrive at our conclusion if one insisted that two or more physical quantities can be regarded as simultaneous elements of reality only when they can be simultaneously measured or predicted.

Since the simultaneous measurement of non-commuting quantities A and B in system I is not possible, P and Q could not have simultaneous reality in system II, although system II is arbitrarily far out. Here is what EPR have to say about this:

This makes the reality of P and Q depend upon the process of measurement carried out on the first system, which does not disturb the second system in any way.

EPR do not expect this to be a reasonable definition of reality. Bohr, however, clearly thought differently (cf. further below).

2.3 Bohm’s Version of the Thought Experiment

The combined state (2.1) that EPR used in their thought experiment shows some disadvantageous traits. For example, it is not only mathematically quite intricate to include the delta function in the formalism of quantum mechanics (it is not a state in Hilbert space that can be normalised), it is also dynamically unstable. By this we mean that a state described by this function widens with time – a strongly localised wave packet delocalises rapidly. An easier version of EPR’s thought experiment, mathematically and conceptually, was introduced by David Bohm (1917–1992) in his textbook on quantum mechanics [21, p. 610–623], written under strong influence of the Copenhagen interpretation. It uses the particle’s spin and has since its appearance replaced EPR’s original thought experiment in most discussions of their arguments. Interestingly, it is also the version that is more accessible to an experimental realisation. However, the experiments could only be realised decades after Bohm’s introduction of the thought experiment. Yet, also EPR’s original state (2.1) can be realised experimentally as a two-mode squeezed state Footnote 7 (see, e.g., Leonhardt [111, p. 74]). The realisation was reported in a paper by Ou et al. [121]. In fact, this state plays an important role in cosmology and the physics of black holes (see discussion in chap. 6). It exhibits, in a well-defined way, maximal correlation [8].

Now, Bohm in his thought experiment considers a molecule consisting of two atoms, each of spin ħ∕2. The total spin of the combined system is assumed to be zero. So there is an anticorrelation for the orientation of the atoms’ spins with respect to a given but arbitrary direction.

Now the molecule is thought to be fragmented into the two atoms by some dissociation process, and the atoms then separated to an arbitrarily large distance (in principle, their distance can be of astronomical magnitude). ‘Arbitrarily large distance’ means that an interaction between the two atoms is made impossible, in complete analogy to the two particles in EPR’s original thought experiment. Note that the value of the total spin of the combined system is conserved.

The argument then continues as in the EPR paper. If one takes a measurement on the z-component of the first atom’s spin, then one can deduce from it the z-component of the second atom’s spin due to their anticorrelation; if one finds + ħ∕2 for atom 1, atom 2 must have −ħ∕2. Now the point is that one can of course take a measurement on atom 1’s spin with respect to any other direction, for example the x-direction. If one finds + ħ∕2 for atom 1, atom 2’s spin component in x-direction must be −ħ∕2. So just like EPR one can conclude that all spin orientations of atom 2 have simultaneous reality. The atom’s spin orientations play the role of the conjugated quantities position and momentum. Just like those, the spins in different orientations do not commute and can therefore not be measured simultaneously, according to the laws of quantum mechanics. Thus, one can conclude the incompleteness of quantum mechanics from this version, too.

What does the mathematical description look like (for the formalism, also cf. appendix A)? Following the rules of quantum mechanics, one has the following four basic states at one’s disposal when constructing the combined state of a system consisting of two spin-1/2-systems:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \begin{array}{rcl} \vert\varPsi_a\rangle =\vert\uparrow\rangle_1 \vert\uparrow\rangle_2, & &\displaystyle \quad \vert\varPsi_b\rangle =\vert\downarrow\rangle_1 \vert\downarrow\rangle_2, \\ \vert\varPsi_c\rangle =\vert\uparrow\rangle_1 \vert\downarrow\rangle_2, & &\displaystyle \quad \vert\varPsi_d\rangle =\vert\downarrow\rangle_1 \vert\uparrow\rangle_2. \end{array} \end{aligned} $$
(2.8)

The last two of these basic states,|Ψ c〉 and |Ψ d〉, describe situations in which each of the two atoms has a certain spin value in z-direction and the two spins are antiparallel. But neither of those two states corresponds to a well defined total spin value. In other words: Those states are no eigenfunctions of the total spin operator. The state with zero total spin is only obtained through an interference of |Ψ c〉 and |Ψ d〉 with a very specific phase relationship; this is the ‘singlet-state’:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \vert\varPsi\rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}\left(\vert\varPsi_c\rangle - \vert\varPsi_d\rangle \right).\end{aligned} $$
(2.9)

This is the state that takes over the role of EPR’s state (2.1) in Bohm’s version of the thought experiment. If one chose a minus sign instead of a plus sign in (2.9), one would obtain a state with total spin 1; so the phase relationshipFootnote 8 between the two components is essential.

Whereas the state (2.9) corresponds to a definite total spin (of zero value), the individual spins of the atoms are undetermined. In a measurement of atom 1’s spin, this state with definite total spin but undetermined individual spins turns into a state with undetermined total spin but definite individual spins. Namely, it turns into the state |Ψ c〉 or |Ψ d〉 (this is the wave function collapse as discussed above).

The form of the state (2.9) can be generalised to all spin orientations. For two antiparallel spins in x-direction and total spin zero, the same state (2.9) can be decomposed into spin eigenfunctions with respect to the x-direction:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \vert\varPsi\rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}\left(\vert\rightarrow\rangle_1 \vert\leftarrow\rangle_2 - \vert\leftarrow\rangle_1\vert\rightarrow\rangle_2\right). \end{aligned} $$
(2.10)

An equal expression holds for any direction; the quantum state is independent of direction.

If a measurement shows that atom 1’s spin points to the right, so atom 2’s spin must point to the left after following that measurement, and vice versa. The argument continues as shown above. Since you can measure atom 1’s spin either in z- or in x-direction without disturbing atom 2, both spin directions must have a physical reality. Because the state is independent of direction, this argument holds for all spin directions. The description with a wave function that doesn’t allow that must thus be incomplete.

Remember that in the measurement it is not possible to send signals from atom 1 to atom 2.Footnote 9 For atom 2, both state decompositions (2.9) and (2.10) yield the same reduced density matrix (cf. appendix). Whatever the direction, this matrix has always the form

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \rho_{\mathrm{red}}=\frac 12 \left( \begin{array}{cc} 1 & 0 \\ 0 & 1 \end{array} \right). \end{aligned} $$
(2.11)

For the z-direction, this reduced density matrix corresponds to an ensemble of 50% atoms with spin in the positive and 50% atoms with spin in the negative direction. The same is true for all directions. So a measurement on atom 2 cannot help to decide whether a measurement on atom 1 has taken place or not.

How did Bohm interpret EPR’s thought experiment? He questions EPR’s local reality criterion and states that only on a classical level there is a unique correspondence between a mathematical theory and “elements of reality”. In contrast to this, all there is in quantum theory is a statistical relation between the wave function and the system (Bohm uses the term potentiality). Because of this purely statistical trait of nature, one just cannot talk about a precisely defined element of reality for, e.g., the position of an electron. And because EPR’s assumption does not apply to quantum theory, one cannot deduce from it this theory’s incompleteness. In Bohm’s own words [21, p. 622]:

[…] the present form of quantum theory implies that the world cannot be put into a one-to-one correspondence with any conceivable kind of precisely defined mathematical quantities, and that a complete theory will always require concepts that are more general than that of analysis into precisely defined elements.

It should, however, be stressed once again that for EPR it is precisely this statistical character of quantum theory that embodies its incompleteness.

Bohm’s discomfort with the quantum theory led him to his own interpretation in the following year, that is known today as de Broglie-Bohm or Bohm-interpretation. In it, the election is described by a wave function and an additional position variable; we are going to get back to this further below.

Bohm concludes this chapter of his textbook with a short argument to prove that the concept of local reality (represented by hidden local variables) is incompatible with quantum theory. A convincing mathematical expression of this incompatibility are the Bell inequalities that shall be discussed further below (Sect. 5.2). With them, it can be decided experimentally if the concept of local reality is correct or not.

2.4 The Contributions of Einstein’s Co-Authors

We have already briefly discussed the life journey of Einstein’s co-authors up to their meeting in Princeton in the first chapter. How did their journey continue?

There are indications that Podolsky was the one who did the actual writing of the paper. Einstein was not really happy with it on a linguistic level.Footnote 10

For example, he wrote to Schrödinger on June 19, 1935:

For reasons of language it was written by Podolsky, after several discussions. It did not become clear what I actually intended, though; rather, the essential thing was, so to speak, smothered in learnedness. The true difficulty lies in the fact that physics is a kind of metaphysics; physics describes ‘reality’. But we do not know what ‘reality’ is; we only know it through the physical description!Footnote 11

That Podolsky was the one responsible for languageFootnote 12 can also be guessed from the missing definite article in the title of the article. In “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?” there is a the missing after can. An omission that would not be atypical for a scientist of Russian origin. While Bohr in his answer chose to quote the title as it is, the American physicist Arthur E. Ruark inserted the definite article in his commentary [139]. In his biography of Einstein, Abraham Pais furthermore noted that Einstein would have used the term Ψ-function instead of wave function [122, p. 499].

After the EPR paper was finished, it seems Einstein had no further contact with Podolsky. This however was not so much due to the fact that the “essential thing was […] smothered in learnedness”, but was rather provoked by a capricious act of Podolsky’s that left Einstein in anger. The New York Times in its Saturday issue on May 4, 1935 (ten days before the EPR paper was published in Physical Review!) published an article entitled “Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory”, reporting to quite some extent on EPR’s work.Footnote 13 The article was supplemented by a résumé of the paper, written by Podolsky. Podolsky was the one to initiate this article, without having talked about it to Einstein or Rosen. Einstein’s unease with this can be read off his following statement, published in the New York Times on May 7, 1935 [quote taken from Jammer [98, p. 190]]:

Any information upon which the article ‘Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory’ in your issue of May 4 is based was given to you without authority. It is my invariable practice to discuss scientific matters only in the appropriate forum and I deprecate advance publication of any announcement in regard to such matters in the secular press.

Boris Podolsky was appointed professor at the University of Cincinnati, United States, in 1935 and went on to the Xavier University, also in Cincinnati, in 1961. He died in 1966. His scientific work focused on generalisations of electrodynamics. His later statements on EPR’s work emphasised its main point, namely the incompleteness of quantum theory, cf. especially his contributions to a conference at the Xavier University from October 1–5 in 1962 that he had helped organise and that was devoted to the foundations of quantum theory. Among the conference participants were Rosen, Dirac and Wigner. The talks and discussions contributions are available online and offer plenty of interesting thoughts [172].Footnote 14

Fig. 2.1
figure 1

Group photograph taken at the conference at Xavier University in October 1962. Bottom row (from left to right): Eugene Wigner, Nathan Rosen, Paul Dirac, Boris Podolsky, Yakir Aharonov and Wendell Furry. (Photograph by Babst Photographic Services found in University Archives and Special Collections, Xavier University Library, Cincinnati, Ohio)

Nathan Rosen’s contribution to the EPR paper seems to have been to propose the entangled state (2.1) and to have worked out the details of the actual calculation. In view of Rosen’s preliminary experiences this should not come as a surprise. In 1931, he had published a paper on the hydrogen molecule [135], related to his dissertation at MIT, wherein he had used the wave function

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \varPsi=\varPsi(a1)\varPsi(b2)+\varPsi(b1)\varPsi(a2), \end{aligned} $$
(2.12)

where a and b refer to the two nuclei and 1 and 2 refer to the two electrons (this is equation (10) of Rosen’s paper).

At first sight, (2.12) looks like an entangled state similar to the state (2.1) that was later used in the EPR paper. But in fact, it is only the result of a formal symmetrisation that becomes necessary if one is working with the classical construct of ascribing numbers to particles (cf., i.e., Zeh [180, p. 10]). A true entanglement involves the entanglement of relative coordinates, in the general case (where the spin-orbit coupling cannot be neglected) also the spin. In 1931, Rosen probably had not yet recognised this difference. An entangled state for the hydrogen molecule was used by Hylleraas [94], who had already in 1929 formulated an entangled state for the helium atom, see equation (11) in Hylleraas [93].Footnote 15 Only when taking into account this entanglement, one obtains the correct energy levels for the ground state. This important remark was already made by Heisenberg in 1935:

Furthermore, one can point to the fact that the natural character of quantum mechanics is very tightly bound to the formal circumstance that its mathematical frame-work of wave functions operates in multi-dimensional configuration space, not in ordinary space, and that precisely this feature of quantum mechanics has been exactly confirmed through the correct reproduction of the more complicated atomic spectra. Footnote 16

In contrast to Podolsky, Einstein did not cut off contact to Rosen. As a matter of fact, from 1935 on, a fruitful collaboration developed between the two on the subject of problems related to general relativity. While working on the EPR paper, they had worked on the perhaps most important publication on this subject. This article, entitled “The Particle Problem in the General Theory of Relativity” was submitted to Physical Review on May 8, 1935 (one week before the publication of the EPR paper) and was published on July 1 of the same year [64]. In it, the authors present what would later be called the ‘Einstein-Rosen bridge’ or the ‘Einstein wormhole’.

What is this about? According to general relativity, the exterior geometry of a spherical mass distribution is described by a solution of the field equations that had been found by the astronomer Karl Schwarzschild in 1916 and is known as the Schwarzschild solution. In its originally adopted form this solution features an irritating trait: at a certain distance from the centre, it becomes singular and therefore meaningless.Footnote 17 While trying to eliminate this singularity, Einstein and Rosen found a solution that connects two copies of the exterior geometry by a small bridge (a ‘wormhole’) (see Fig. 2.2).

Fig. 2.2
figure 2

Einstein-Rosen bridge. (Figure drawn by Allen McC.; redistribution permitted under a Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0 Unported license)

Because such a solution also exists in the presence of an electromagnetic field, Einstein and Rosen interpreted it as a possible model for describing elementary particles (such as protons and electrons). This would offer a way to infer the existence of matter directly from the field equations, i.e., without having to insert it into the equations by hand. Towards the end of their paper, Einstein and Rosen write:

…one does not see a priori whether the theory contains the quantum phenomena. Nevertheless one should not exclude a priori the possibility that the theory may contain them.

And in his letter to Schrödinger on June 7, 1935, Einstein wrote [158, vol. 2, p. 536]:

I have found that in general relativity neutral and charged particles can be described as singularity-free fields, with no need of additional terms. From the point of view of principles, I absolutely do not believe in a statistical basis for physics in the sense of quantum mechanics, despite the singular success of the formalism of which I am well aware. I do not believe such a theory can be made general relativistic.Footnote 18

And that is where their work is related to the EPR paper! With the help of concepts like the Einstein-Rosen bridge Einstein sought to complete the quantum theory. We will get back to this. It was found later that Einstein’s and Rosen’s solution from 1935 is not suited for this purpose, because it is unstable and therefore not able to describe (stable) elementary particles. Also, being a classical concept it could not explain the EPR situation.Footnote 19

Einstein and Rosen cooperated on two further papers. One dealt with the two-body problem in general relativity [65], the other one with cylindric gravitational waves [66].

Following the year 1936, Rosen was initially appointed professor at the University of Kiev, Ukraine (back then USSR), and from 1941 on at the University of North Carolina in Chapel Hill, United States. From 1953 until his death in 1995, he was a professor at the Israel Institute of Technology (Technion) in Haifa, Israel. Just like Einstein and Podolsky, throughout the rest of his career, Rosen kept emphasising the main point of the EPR paper: the incompleteness of quantum mechanics (see, e.g., Rosen [137]). One of his students was Asher Peres (1934–2005) , who contributed to the foundations of quantum theory, especially to the comparatively young field of quantum information.

2.5 Critical Evaluation

In their paper, EPR concluded the incompleteness of quantum theory. We have discussed the details of this conclusion in the preceding section. Now, we shall discuss the implicit and explicit assumptions on which EPR based their conclusion and will, to this end, deviate from the historic course of events in favour of a more systematic approach. We will rejoin the chronological path of events in the following chapter on the reception and impact of the EPR paper.

First, there is the reality criterion , according to which there is an element of reality corresponding to a physical quantity, if we can predict with certainty the value of this quantity without disturbing the system, cf. the beginning of Sect. 2.2. As Beller and Fine [18] have pointed out, EPR use this criterion merely once in their paper, and only indirectly. Following their equation (1), EPR mention the undisputed quantum mechanical fact that a physical quantity A has with certainty the value a, whenever the wave function of the system is the eigenfunction with associated eigenvalue a of the operator A that corresponds to the physical quantity (‘eigenfunction-eigenvalue link’). Then, EPR continue, “in accordance with our criterion of reality […] there is an element of physical reality corresponding to the physical quantity A.” When EPR mention the reality criterion in part 2 of their paper, they really only talk about this eigenfunction-eigenvalue link. They do not show that P and Q have simultaneous reality in system II; in order to show this through the reality criterion, A and B would need to be simultaneously measurable in system I, but quantum mechanics prohibits that; and EPR do not doubt the validity of quantum mechanics. They only do show that system II has a reality that can be described by a momentum eigenfunction as well as by a position eigenfunction. This fact will be essential when evaluating Bohr’s response in Sect. 4.2.

According to Fine [73, p. 5], Einstein never again mentioned EPR’s reality criterion. It appears that – at least to Einstein – the criterion did not much matter for EPR’s line of argument. As he put it in the letter to Schrödinger quoted above, for him “the essential thing was […] smothered in learnedness.” However, what happens if the learnedness were pushed aside and the core of EPR’s argument laid bare? What was Einstein’s key assumption of their work? He repeatedly commented on this, initially in his letters to Schrödinger, later in his essay on “Physik und Realität” (“Physics and reality”) [57], and in the article published in the journal Dialectica [58] included in this book, as well as in his contributions to the anthology edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp [59, 60] and the Born Festschrift [61]. All these texts make it quite clear that Einstein’s point was based on the locality or separability of physical systems; in EPR’s case, of systems I and II. It is worth taking another, detailed look at Einstein’s letter to Schrödinger on June 19, 1935 – i.e., one month after the publication of the EPR paper–, in which Einstein highlights the important points giving a simple example. Einstein wrote:

I have in front of me two boxes, with lids that can be opened. I can look into the boxes, when the lids are open; this is called ‘to make an observation’. There is also a ball that is always either in one or the other box when making an observation. I will describe the situation as follows: ‘The probability to find the ball in the first box is 1/2.’ Is this a complete description?Footnote 20

Einstein then goes on to discuss the two possible answers. If one considers the statement that the ball is either in the first box or it is not, a complete description, then according to Einstein the answer must be no. But if one assumes (as most of the quantum theorists did at the time) that the ball is in neither of the boxes before the lid is opened, then according to Einstein the answer must be yes. The state then is completely described by the probability 1/2, and there is no reality beyond the statistical character of the world of experience. Einstein then establishes the analogy with quantum theory:

We face similar alternatives when we want to explain the relation of quantum mechanics to reality. With regard to the ball-system, naturally, the second, ‘spiritualist’ or Schrödinger interpretation is hackneyed, and the man on the street would only take the first, ‘Bornian’ interpretation seriously. But the Talmudic philosopher dismisses ‘reality’ as a bogy of naiveté and declares the two conceptions differing only in their terminology.Footnote 21

Now, Einstein lets the cat out of the bag and presents his separation principle, from which in the EPR paper followed – though smothered in learnedness – the incompleteness of quantum theory:

Now my mode of thought is thus: One cannot get by the Talmudic philosopher without the help of an additional principle: the ‘separation principle’. Namely: ‘The second box including everything concerning its content is independent of what is happening with the second box’ (separated subsystems). If we hold fast to this separation principle, then the second (the ‘Schrödinger’) interpretation is excluded and only the Bornian one remains according to which, however, the above given description of the state is an incomplete description of reality or of the real states, respectively.Footnote 22

Einstein then, by using the mathematical formalism and explicitly applying his separation principle, once again summarises the essential line of thought of the EPR paper.

So the locality or separability criterion is of pivotal importance to Einstein; when you dispose of it, says Einstein, you lose the basis for a reasonable description of nature. In his later essays on the topic, he elevated the thoughts he had formulated in the letter to Schrödinger on a philosophical level of general significance. For example, in his Dialectica contribution [58, p. 321] he writes:

Without assuming such an independence of the existence (of the ‘being-thus’) of spatially distant objects, which first originates from everyday thinking, physical reasoning would not be possible in the manner familiar to us.Footnote 23

From this, Einstein concludes the incompleteness of quantum theory because different wave functions can be attributed to the same local reality. Assuming the completeness would correspond to implying “the hypothesis of action-at-a-distance, an hypothesis which is hardly acceptable”Footnote 24, which for Einstein is incompatible with the theory of relativity. Only later, in connection with the formulation of the Bell inequalities some years after Einstein’s death, it became completely clear that the assumption of local reality not only contradicts the completeness of quantum theory, but more than that also contradicts its consistency and feasible experiments. It seems pointless to retrospectively try to imagine Einstein’s reaction to this finding, had he still lived.

It also follows from Einstein’s general remarks that it is indeed sufficient to consider only one variable (e.g., the position coordinate). To consider two non-commuting and therefore not simultaneously measurable variables sharpens the argument, but is rooted mostly in the historical tide of events, namely that it was preceded by the discussion about the uncertainty relations. When we consider an entangled wave function Ψ(x 1, x 2), we can conclude as follows. Because of the entanglement , x 1 and x 2 do not have a reality on their own. Only when the state is reduced to a product by taking a measurement on, e.g., x 1, and when one also applies Einstein’s separation principle, a reality can be ascribed to x 2. Edward Teller (1908–2003) was one to very early highlight this fact, as we can see in a letter he wrote to Schrödinger in June 1935 [158, p. 530]. For this reason, Teller did not even want to speak of a reality.

Einstein expressed his ‘epistemological credo’ in his contributions to Schilpp’s Festschrift. Therein, he wrote [59, p. 31]:

Physics is an attempt conceptually to grasp reality as it is thought independently of its being observed. In this sense one speaks of ‘physical reality’.Footnote 25

In his remarks to the essays appearing in this collective volume, Einstein pointed out [60, p. 236]:

‘Being’ is always something which is mentally constructed by us, that is, something which we freely posit (in the logical sense).Footnote 26

Here, Einstein essentially turned against classical positivism and its motto esse est percipi (‘to be is to be perceived’), according to which being results from being perceived. The thinking conveyed in these quotes differs remarkably from the first part of the EPR paper. Whereas in that paper, reality is an objective quantity and the terms and definitions one applies serve the only purpose of corresponding to the elements of this reality, Einstein now promotes the freedom of choice when selecting the terms and definition in an attempt to approach the reality that is somewhere beyond its being observed. He wrote [59, p. 12]:

Although the conceptual systems are logically entirely arbitrary, they are bound by the aim to permit the most nearly possible certain (intuitive) and complete co-ordination with the totality of sense-experiences; […]Footnote 27

A whole lot of these remarks resemble the Philosophical Investigations (‘Philosophische Untersuchungen’), published years later, in 1953, by the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951, cf. Wittgenstein [171]) who to some extent was influenced by the Vienna Circle chaired by Moritz Schlick. In some ways, Einstein’s notion of a free posit of terms and definitions corresponds to Wittgenstein’s notion of language-games. The main difference between the two is of course that the terms and definitions one chooses in physics are subject to empirical testing.

Since Einstein was convinced to have discovered the incompleteness of the quantum theory, he tried to complete it. But he did not attempt a completion from within: “I believe, however, that this theory offers no useful point of departure for future development.”Footnote 28

Instead, Einstein saw remedy in his search for a unified field theory. Since the 1920s, Einstein had tried to unify gravitation and electromagnetism following the example of his general relativity. He expected particles – that is, the behaviour of atoms and electrons, usually the realm of quantum theory – to turn out to be singularity-free solutions of his fundamental field equations. The above mentioned paper he wrote with Rosen was supposed to be the first brick of this beautiful building: “Look at the small paper on a possible relativistic interpretation of matter that I recently published with Mr. Rosen in the Physical Review. If the mathematical difficulties can be overcome, this might lead to something.”Footnote 29

In his contribution to the de Broglie Festschrift, Einstein once again made the point:

We partly owe my efforts to complete the theory of general relativity by generalising the gravitational equations to the surmise that a reasonable general relativistic field theory might offer the key to complete the quantum theory. This is but a modest hope, not a conviction.Footnote 30

We will discuss further below why ultimately Einstein’s hope was in vain.

Quite early, Einstein felt appalled by the statistical character of quantum theory. There is a passage in a letter he wrote to Born on December 4, 1926 (i.e., ten years before the EPR paper), that has gained fame:

Quantum mechanics is certainly imposing. But an inner voice tells me that it is not yet the real thing. The theory says a lot, but does not really bring us any closer to the secret of the ‘old one’. I, at any rate, am convinced that He is not playing at dice.Footnote 31

As early as in May 1927, i.e., one month after having studied Heisenberg’s paper on the uncertainty relations, Einstein gave a talk at the Prussian Academy of Sciences in Berlin where he discussed the question whether Schrödinger’s wave mechanics describes the dynamics of a system completely or only in a statistical sense. Einstein withdrew the submitted manuscript before publication, but today it is available online [56].Footnote 32 In it, Einstein introduces an interpretation that shows some similarities to de Broglie’s theory of pilot waves. But what is important for our purpose here is the fact that, already in 1927, Einstein was bothered by the question of the completeness of the quantum theory; also cf. Brown [32]. The EPR paper and his later writings clearly show that Einstein had accepted the statistical nature of quantum theory. But to him, it was only an expression of the theory’s incompleteness. Determinism is not a presupposition of EPR’s analysis (see the quote by John Bell towards the end of Sect. 5.2).

In his contribution to the Born Festschrift, Einstein later highlighted the importance of the classical limit [61]. He takes as an example a wave function that in the macroscopic realm corresponds to a superposition of macroscopically different momenta. So it does not describe a classical behaviour. (Schrödinger got to the heart of this situation in his famous cat argument, see further below.) As a consequence, according to Einstein, quantum mechanics can only tell the probability of finding a certain macroscopic state when measuring. This is what he wrote:

The result of our consideration is this: The only acceptable interpretation of the Schrödinger equation is the statistical interpretation given by Born. However, this does not provide a real description of an individual system, but only statistical statements about ensembles of systems.Footnote 33

It still took a long time to truly understand how to obtain the classical limit from quantum theory (see Sect. 5.4). Macroscopic wave functions necessarily become entangled with their environment’s degrees of freedom, yielding a combined state that emulates classical behaviour for the variables of the macroscopic system. So Einstein’s argument from 1953 is ineffective, because it assumes a strictly isolated state.

For the rest of his life, Einstein considered the quantum theory to be a statistical description of nature, similar to the statistical mechanics of the nineteenth century, that was to be replaced by a microscopic theory without such a fundamentally probabilistic character. Amongst other things, it was this belief that motivated his search for a unified field theory based on classical principles – an endeavour that was ultimately in vain.