Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 401))

  • 392 Accesses

Abstract

Russell inaugurated analytic philosophy new-style. His initial concern was with rationality. He took its display in science to be best and the clearest. He therefore had two initial aims: to render philosophy scientific and to prove that science is certain (since tradition equates reason with provability). This led him to efforts to improve logic. He argued that whereas every class is a subclass of itself, no class is a member of itself. He wanted to prove this. So he defined “normal” a class is normal if it is not a member of itself: x ε N ↔ ~(x ε x) and tried to prove that all classes are normal: N = V. This made him wonder: is the normal class itself normal? As we saw, the answer is, yes-and-no; which is absurd. Now absurdities were never problematic as everybody always pronounced them false. Russell’s paradox, like any paradox (or antinomy or puzzle), is demonstrably true and false. A language that contains a paradox has all its statements proven. Russell managed to block paradoxes but he allowed contradictions as well-formed. This was the birth of the first fully formal language.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Alam 199 , 135, 155. Landini 2007 describes all this in admirable detail. See also Agassi 2009 . In the 1959 preface of Popper’s magnum opus, he conceded to the analytic school what was Russell’s contribution and rejected the rest as due to misconceptions (alluding to Wittgenstein’s contribution, p. 17). See Glock 2008, 15 and 219. Glock places Popper in the analytic tradition, but while laudably mentioning his protest.

  2. 2.

    The term that Wittgenstein employed systematically is “forms of life”. The reading of this as social institutions is the thesis of Winch 1958 , although the expression “institution” appears there sparingly. See Jarvie 1972 , Ch. 2 and Gellner 1973 , Ch. 4.

  3. 3.

    A string of words is judged a pseudo-sentence in a language if its words are not placed in accord with the rules of the grammar of that language, or else if some of the words in it do not refer but should (TLP, §5.4733).

  4. 4.

    This historical question invites a historical answer. Some writers have offered answers that include streamlined versions of Frege’s work. The streamlining requires of them to overlook the concerns that engaged the historical Frege. This is sad. Here is the place to stress that he worked as a mathematician. Berkeley’s critique of the calculus was conceptual; all effort to answer it were mathematical (Wisdom 1939). Frege and Peano approached the situation differently (Segre 1994) . Kreisel 1978 , 88 reports Wittgenstein’s reference to the “disastrous invasion of mathematics by mathematical logic”. This is strange, considering that Frege was the father of symbolic logic and the very first to perform this “invasion” and considering that Wittgenstein admired his work. This was “an exaggeration”; but since “his public performances which were always tense and often incoherent”, presumably Kreisel found it unsurprising. See also Rodych 2018 .

  5. 5.

    Variance in notation alone need not alter content. This is true by definition. Rewording a problematic differential equation, however, may facilitate its solution. Hence, changing notations may help perform a task. Even the facilitation of reading a formula may help this way, The notations of Oliver Heaviside for both the equations for electric circuits and for electromagnetic equations were every helpful, as was the lovely simplifications that Einstein introduced into tensor calculus.

  6. 6.

    Landini 2012 , Preface. Landini argues that simplifying Frege’s notation has raised many new problems for the reading of his ideas.

  7. 7.

    More precisely, T is the set that contains all and only the true sentences in the language in use.

  8. 8.

    TLP, §3.334: “The rules of logical syntax must go without saying, once we know how each sign signifies.” §5.132: “‘Laws of inference’ … are senseless and would be superfluous”. [Note: they would be superfluous; they are not superfluous tout court.] §6.1264: “(… one cannot express the modus ponens by means of a proposition.)” This is a truism: a rule is not a proposition; since early Wittgenstein limited meaning to propositions, his §6.1264 is trivial.

  9. 9.

    Russell was never clear about the deduction theorem. His “Replies to Critics” (Russell 1944, 969) has a repetition of the theorem and a discussion of the value of any conditional statement. In the case of the dependence of our knowledge of the truth of the conditional on our knowledge of the truth of its antecedent or of the falsity of its consequence, Russell says there, the conditional is useless; it is useful in the case in which our knowledge of its truth is prior to such knowledge. He said this in oversight of conditionals that appear as hypotheticals – in the deduction theorem and in science. They are unknown yet most useful. More obvious is the reductio ad absurdum that here Russell overlooked (as inessential?). This also explains his tern “the contradiction” for his paradox (rather than “the proven contradiction”). See also Whitehead and Russell, 1911, I, 62.

  10. 10.

    The criticism of Frege’s theory of denotation in Russell 1905, 484–5, is that it is hit by the paradox of empty terms (“the present king of France is bald”) and of referential opacity (“the king wanted to know who was the author of Waverley ”). Linsky 1967, 72–3 and Hintikka 1981, 170 have complained that Russell had not cleared the paradox of referential opacity, and that it does not involve definite descriptions. The two complaints may neutralize each other. Yet referential opacity remains an obstacle – not for PMia that is extensional, not for other purposes. Students of intensional logic may do better if the specify them.

  11. 11.

    Martin 1963 ; Salmon 1993 .

  12. 12.

    Quine 1943, conclusion. This is the program for developing a free logic, one with no existential import.

  13. 13.

    Hintikka 1981. (His oversight of Linsky here is baffling.)

  14. 14.

    “Use” is a social term. Modern logic and modern methodology are sociological. Traditional (Locke-style ) conceptual analysis is intentionally psychological: classical philosophy was individualist and demanded the reduction of sociology to psychology. Though Wittgenstein’s “use” is clearly sociological rather than psychological, many members of the analytic school prefer psychology to sociology.

  15. 15.

    Popper 1959 , Preface to the English Translation is devoted to a thorough criticism of this idea.

  16. 16.

    Moore noticed (Schilpp 1944, 214) that that “the Whale” differs from “Man” and “Horse” in its possession of a definite article. Russell dismissed this (op. cit., 690) as a minor irregularity.

  17. 17.

    Hylton 1989 ; Linsky 1967 , xvi, stresses that Russell repeatedly offered variants of that theory.

  18. 18.

    Carnap 1947 , §30; Linsky 1967 , 44n, 46, 48.

  19. 19.

    Limiting this discussion for unique entities leaves open the question, is it necessary to assume that a class is non-empty before naming it? This is a quaint variant of the problem of induction. For, the assumption that atoms exist is a corollary to the statement that atomic theory that describes them is a true explanation.

  20. 20.

    Some comments seem obviously exaggerated, such as the refutation of Russell’s view that definite descriptions are unique. The alleged refutation is with the expression “the men who … .” This is an unintended insult. It stems from understanding Russell’s “On Denoting” as a theory of all the diverse usages of the definite article in familiar English rather than as a solution to a problem within the task of formalizing parts of a natural language into a language adequate for mathematics. Russell expressly referred to the definite article in the singular. (In some languages, singular and plural expressions may differ widely.)

  21. 21.

    Strawson 1959; Russell 1950; Linsky 1967, 99 considers Strawson’s argument exceptionally poor. See also Rorty 1971 .

  22. 22.

    Bunge uses the universe of discourse freely to solve the problem at hand the easy way.

  23. 23.

    This is a disclaimer: the theory is no complete account of the diverse acceptable usages of the definite article. Russell ends his paper by asserting a smaller claim as more general: the problem has no easy solution. All his commentators agree with him, but few pay him the courtesy of saying so explicitly.

  24. 24.

    To render an opaque problematic inference invalid one needs to use a technique similar to the classical fallacy of four terms (quaternio terminorum).

  25. 25.

    Russell 1905, 484: “one would suppose that ‘the King of France is bald’ ought to be nonsense; but it is not nonsense, since it is plainly false.” Here we see the importance of not calling a falsehood “nonsense”.

  26. 26.

    Russell stressed repeatedly that propositions that contain expressions with no meanings may nevertheless possess clear and obvious meanings. Wittgenstein agreed, even though not clearly: TLP, §4.064 says, “Every proposition must already have sense; assertion cannot give it a sense, for what it asserts is the sense itself.” Nevertheless, Wittgenstein often spoke of the meanings of words, not of statements (“and then whenever someone else wanted to say something metaphysical, to demonstrate to him that he had failed to give a meaning to certain signs in his propositions”; TLP, 6.53). This is but a slip of his pen: he proudly presented his atheism as a part of modern logic. Popper 1963 , 373 has corrected Wittgenstein here: the theory of definite description allows describing the deity in many ways, all of them traditional. Putnam 2008 repeated the claim that Wittgenstein’s philosophy supports religion as a practice devoid of any doctrine.

  27. 27.

    Russell 1905, 484–5: “A logical theory may be tested by its capacity for dealing with puzzles, and it is a wholesome plan, in thinking about logic, to stock the mind with as many puzzles as possible, since these serve much the same purpose as is served by experiments in physical science.” This then is a partial success of his plan to render philosophy scientific.

  28. 28.

    Russell 1914, title to Chapter 2: Logic as the Essence of Philosophy.

  29. 29.

    Russell 1956b, 27; Monk 1990, 2012, 64.

  30. 30.

    Monk 1996, 241, 250–2272, 280, 289, 282: “No one except Wittgenstein understood it all”.

  31. 31.

    This may be a mistake of mine: as commentators are reluctant to discuss this, I may be missing a point.

  32. 32.

    Forster 2004 , 230. Engel 2012 , 48 denies that Wittgenstein’s Tractatus relates to the ideal language. “He was attempting, rather, to reveal the essential structure” of any language. As Forster refers to TLP, §§3.325 and 4.0031 here, it is hard to ascribe to Engel ignorance rather than defensiveness. Dummett 1991c , 83–5 argues for the impossibility of the ideal language, as all language is social.

References

  • Agassi, J. (2009). The advantage of theft over honest toil. (Review of Landini, 2007.). Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 29, 507–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Am, N., & Agassi, J. (2014). Meaning: From parmenides to Wittgenstein: Philosophy as ‘footnotes to parmenides’. Conceptus, 41, 188–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W., III. (1982–1983). Wittgenstein and homosexuality. Salmagundi, 58–59, 166–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. (1979). frege’s theory of judgement. Oxford/New York: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. ([1947] 1956). Meaning and necessity: A study in semantics and modal logic. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, J. W. (1994). Wittgenstein’s metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, J. W. (2000). Wittgenstein, empiricism, and language. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991a). Frege: Philosophy of mathematics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991b). Frege and other philosophers. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991c). The logical basis of metaphysics. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, M. N. (2004). Wittgenstein on the arbitrariness of grammar. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1984). Collected Papers (P. Geach & R. H. Stoothoff, Trans.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gellner, E. (1973). Cause and meaning in the social sciences (I. C. Jarvie & J. Agassi, Eds.). London/Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (2008). What is analytic philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1981). On denoting what? Synthese, 46, 167–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hylton, P. (1989). The significance of on denoting. In A. Savage & H. Feigl (Eds.), Rereading Russell (pp. 88–107). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvie, I. C. (1972). Concepts and society. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreisel, G. (1978). Review of Wittgenstein’s lectures on the foundations of mathematics, Cambridge, 1939. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 84, 79–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landini, G. (2007). Wittgenstein’s apprenticeship with Russell. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landini, G. (2012). Frege’s notations: What they are and how they mean. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, L. (1967). Referring. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, L. (1977). Names and descriptions. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, R. M. (1963). On the Frege-Church theory of meaning. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 23, 605–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monk, R. (1990, 2012). Ludwig Wittgenstein: The duty of genius. London: Vintage Digital.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk, R. (1996). Bertrand Russell, 1872–1921: The spirit of solitude. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Notturno, M. A. (1985). Objectivity, rationality, and the third realm: Justification and the grounds of psychologism: A study of Frege and Popper. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. ([1935] 1959). The logic of scientific discovery. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2008). Jewish philosophy as a guide to life: Rosenzweig, Buber, Lévinas, Wittgenstein. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodych, V. (2018). Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1971). Verificationism and transcendental arguments. Noûs, 5, 3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493 reprinted in his 1956a, 39–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). Problems of philosophy. New York: H. Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1914). Our knowledge of the external world: As a field for scientific method in philosophy. London: G. Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1944). My mental development; replies to criticisms. In Schilpp, 1944, pp. 1–20 and 679–741.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1950). Logical positivism, in his Logic and knowledge, 1956a, pp. 367–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1953). The cult of common usage. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 3, 303–307 Reprinted in Russell 1956b, 66–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1956a). Logic and knowledge. London: G. Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1956b). Portraits from memory and other essays. London: G. Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. ([1959a] 1993). My philosophical development. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. ([1959b] 2005). Foreword to Gellner’s words and things

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1993). A problem in the Frege-church theory of sense and denotation. Noûs, 27, 158–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schilpp, P. A. (Ed.). (1944). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell. Evanston: Northwestern University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1958). Russell’s objections to Frege’s theory of sense and reference. Analysis, 18, 137–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segre, M. (1994). Peano’s axioms in their historical context. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 48, 201–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (2009). Frege’s judgement stroke and the conception of logic as the study of inference not consequence. Philosophy Compass, 4, 639–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wettersten, J. R. (1995). Preliminary report on efforts of Psychologism to gain influence in proper epistemological, methodological and psychological societies. In Jarvie & Laor, 1995, pp. 129–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1958). The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. O. (1939). The analyst controversy: Berkeley’s influence on the development of mathematics. Hermathena, 29, 3–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Letters to Russell, Keynes, and Moore. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. ([1969] 1991). Philosophical grammar. Ed. Rush Rhees.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Agassi, J. (2018). Russell. In: Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Synthese Library, vol 401. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00117-9_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics