Skip to main content

Abstract

The last chapter assumed that the objects of knowledge are propositions. This assumption requires defence and part of this chapter will be devoted to this. In addition, we must discuss the nature of knowledge in order to be clear about the requirements of omniscience, and therefore this chapter will investigate the nature of knowledge and its objects. This statement of purpose is, of course, a little overstated; for certainly a complete epistemology cannot be presented in one chapter. Rather, I shall investigate the nature of knowledge in so far as it bears on the doctrine of omniscience. First, I shall discuss the nature of knowledge in sufficient detail to develop a preliminary understanding of the claim that there is an omniscient being, and I shall also distinguish that claim from the claim that there is a being who has the property of being omniscient essentially.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

eBook
USD 24.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. Peter Geach, Providence and Evil (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977) p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. David Armstrong, Belief, Truth and Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. Alvin Goldman, ‘What Is Justified Belief?’, in George Pappas (ed.) Justification and Knowledge (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1979) pp. 1–25

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  4. Fred Dretske, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Boston: MIT Press, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Edmund Gettier, ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’, Analysis, 23 (1963) pp. 121–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Patrick Grim, ‘Some Neglected Problems of Omniscience’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 20 (1983) p. 266.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Willard Van Orman Quine, ‘Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes’, in his The Ways of Paradox (New York: Random House, 1966) pp. 185–96.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bertrand Russell, ‘The Philosophy of Logical Atomism’, in R. C. Marsh (ed.) Logic and Knowledge (New York: Capricorn Books, 1956) pp. 175–282.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Bertrand Russell, ‘On the Nature of Acquaintance’, in Logic and Knowledge, p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  10. David Kaplan, ‘Quantifying In’, in D. Davidson and J. Hintikka (eds) Words and Objections (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1969) pp. 206–42.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  11. Ernest Sosa, ‘Propositional Attitudes De Dicto and De Re’, The Journal of Philosophy, 67, (1970) pp. 883–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., p. 892.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Roderick Chisholm, Person and Object (La Salle: Open Court, 1976)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Tyler Burge, ‘Belief De Re’, The Journal of Philosophy, 74 (1977) pp. 338–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Myles Brand, ‘Intending and Believing’, in James Tomberlin (ed.) Agent, Language, and the Structure of the World (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983) pp. 181–2.

    Google Scholar 

  20. John Perry, ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical’, Nous, 13 (1979) p. 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Chisholm defends this view in Person and Object.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., pp. 33–6.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  26. G. E. M. Anscombe, ‘The First Person’, in Samuel Guttenplan (ed.) Mind and Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975) p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  27. ‘The First Person’, p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Hector Castaneda, Thinking and Doing (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1975) p. 159.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. ‘On the Phenomeno-Logic of the I’, Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses fur Philosphie, III (Vienna: University of Vienna, 1969) pp. 260–9.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ernest Sosa, ‘Consciousness of the Self and of the Present’, in Tomberlin (ed.) Agent, Language, and the Structure of the World, p. 140.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Sosa, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. Roderick Chisholm, The First Person; John Perry, ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical’; David Lewis, ‘Attitudes de dicto and de se’, The Philosophical Review, 88, (1979) pp. 513–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Anscombe, ‘The First Person’, p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Peter J. Markie develops this criticism of Chisholm’s property theory in detail in ‘De Dicto and De Se’, Philosophical Studies, 45, (1984) pp. 231–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Chisholm most clearly affirms this view in correspondence with Peter J. Markie on issues surrounding Markie’s criticism of Chisholm’s property view.

    Google Scholar 

  40. This definition is one suggested to me by Edward Wierenga in correspondence.

    Google Scholar 

  41. I owe awareness of both the arguments to discussions with Peter J. Markie.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Chisholm suggests this view in Person and Object, pp. 31–7.

    Google Scholar 

  43. For a discussion and bibliography concerning the issues surrounding a triadic theory of belief which takes the meaning of the sentence to be one component of belief, cf. Mark Richard, ‘Direct Reference and Ascriptions of Belief’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 12, (1983) pp. 425–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Reliabilist theories of justification are especially guilty of confusing epistemic ideality with justification. They claim that a justified belief is a belief produced by a reliable mechanism. Yet, what mechanisms are reliable is sometimes a matter of what epistemic dispositions a person has to form beliefs, and thus reliabilists claim that unless a person has proper dispositions to form beliefs, many of his beliefs will be unjustified. This seems to me to confuse what we want an epistemically ideal agent to be like (we want him not only to justifiably believe all and only what is true, but to be disposed to form beliefs conforming to this requirement as well) with whether a person has a justified belief at present. Justified beliefs can be obtained in the process of forming our intellectual characters (even in the midst of, and as a result of, intellectual deficiencies) just as morally proper behaviour can occur even in the morally tainted. For more discussion on this matter, see Keith Lehrer’s gypsy lawyer example in Knowledge, pp. 124–5 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974), and my own ‘How to Be a Reliabilist’, forthcoming, American Philosophical Quarterly, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1986 Jonathan L. Kvanvig

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kvanvig, J.L. (1986). Knowledge and its Objects. In: The Possibility of an All-Knowing God. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-18437-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics