1 Introduction

Nietzsche makes liberal use of the language of virtue and vice, and he often appears to be praising and exhorting, condemning and encouraging his readers in just such language. He reflects thoughtfully and at length on issues of character, habit and motivation. And his critical enterprise is explicitly framed by a concern with human flourishing (GM P:3).Footnote 1 But is Nietzsche a virtue theorist? Notwithstanding a number of strenuous efforts to read him as one, the answer to this question has to be ‘no’.

In the first two sections of this paper, I present two serious obstacles to the development of a virtue-theoretic reading of Nietzsche. In the face of such obstacles, determined commentators have been forced, or at least tempted, to read selectively, to dismiss textual counterevidence as hyperbole or irony, or to otherwise modify or outright deny what Nietzsche says in the interest of supplying him with views compatible with the contemporary virtue tradition in ethical thought. Ultimately, I think, no such interpretation can be sustained without doing unacceptable violence to the texts. And it need not be done, since, as I argue in the third section, efforts to read Nietzsche as a virtue theorist have so far been predicated on a false dilemma. Once we reject it, we will see that there is nothing to motivate the virtue-theoretic reading.Footnote 2 In fact, it is neither necessary nor desirable to force upon Nietzsche any affirmative morality, since the challenge that his critical philosophy imposes on us is more provocative and philosophically interesting than any virtue-theoretic reading on offer.

2 The First Obstacle: What Is Missing

In an early essay outlining what she thinks a Nietzschean virtue theory might look like, Christine Swanton begins by saying, “Any virtue ethic needs to address at least the following two basic issues: (A) What makes an action right? (B) What makes a trait of character a virtue?”Footnote 3 But since there is nothing in Nietzsche’s corpus to suggest that he intended to offer answers to either question, she is forced to carry out her discussion in terms of how she thinks Nietzsche would have answered them. This concession illustrates the first obstacle facing any virtue-theoretic reading of Nietzsche: namely, the absence of any explicit attempt to give a systematic account of any of the concepts that most contemporary proponents of virtue ethics regard as indispensable to a coherent and normatively successful theory (even taking into account that virtue ethicists can disagree about theoretical requirements). Nietzsche makes no clear effort to define ‘virtue’, for instance, or to tell us what virtue in general consists in; nor do we find in his works any clear account of the virtuous individual or the nature of virtuous action.

In Swanton’s attempt to supply Nietzsche with an answer to her first question, she goes well beyond the texts, even attributing to Nietzsche theses that are plainly incompatible with them. Consider, for instance, how the account of “right action” she claims to be able to extract from Nietzsche’s work introduces the concept of ‘virtue’. On Swanton’s reading, Nietzsche thinks that “the virtuousness of the motive is both a necessary and sufficient condition of rightness of the action that flows from it.”Footnote 4 Nietzsche nowhere says anything of this sort, and the only appropriate response to this interpretive claim, it seems to me, is an incredulity that should not be mitigated by the textual support she offers for it. Swanton appeals to two passages (BGE 32 and GM I:13), both of which do more to undermine than to bolster her case.

To demonstrate that Nietzsche espouses her criterion of right action, for instance, Swanton says, “For Nietzsche, in short, it is the ‘origin’ of an action that ‘decides its value’ (BGE 32).”Footnote 5 But in this passage of Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche attributes this misbegotten claim to deontologists, who have managed to overcome one egregious error—that of supposing that the value of an action is determined by its consequences—only to install a “disastrous new superstition” in its place: namely, that behind every action is an “intention” to which we should look to determine the value of an action. By contrast, Nietzsche says, “we immoralists, at least, suspect that the decisive value is conferred by what is specifically unintentional about an action […] and that all its intentionality […] only belongs to its surface or skin” (BGE 32). The “morality of intentions” to which Swanton makes reference he derides as “a prejudice, a precipitousness, perhaps a preliminary, a thing on about the same level as astrology and alchemy, but in any case something that must be overcome” (ibid.). The Genealogy passage makes a related point, about the misconceptions we harbor about agents and how those errors are ossified in moral theory. “For just as common people separate the lightning from its flash and take the latter as a doing, as an effect of a subject called lighting,” Nietzsche says, “so popular morality also separates strength from the expressions of strength as if there were behind the strong an indifferent substratum that is free to express its strength—or not to. But there is no such substratum […]” (GM I:13). Swanton appeals to this idea, too, in her attempt to ground the claim that what makes an action virtuous is what is “within” the agent. But her explanation requires her to maintain the very conceptual separation between “agent” and “motive” that Nietzsche is rejecting in this important passage—and thereby to commit the very mistake he describes.

In short, Swanton’s account of “Nietzschean” right action would commit Nietzsche to a theory of action he thinks is untenable. In a number of passages, he raises serious worries about the nature of conscious willing (i.e., about “motives” and “intentions”), its transparency, its regularity, and its causal efficacy. No matter how one reads these passages, it is clear that Nietzsche’s view of the relationship between willing and deliberating, on the one hand, and acting, on the other hand, cannot support reliable explanations of our behavior in the way it would have to in order to serve as Swanton’s evaluative criterion of action. Furthermore, although Swanton recognizes that Nietzsche’s moral psychology—according to which motives and intentions are not transparent to agents—complicates the picture she wants to paint,Footnote 6 she fails to appreciate to what extent. Nietzsche takes us to be largely “unknown to ourselves” (GM P:1). In Daybreak, he ridicules the “unknown world of the ‘subject’,” where “actions are never what they appear to us to be! […] and all actions are essentially unknown” (D 116, emphasis added). And “that as one observes or recollects any action, it is and remains impenetrable; that our opinions about ‘good’ and ‘noble’ and ‘great’ can never be proven true by our actions because every act is unknowable” (GS 335, emphasis added). Unfortunately, the more inscrutable our motives and desires become, and the more we recognize that they probably belong to the unconscious, the worse things get for Swanton’s account.Footnote 7 A necessary and sufficient criterion of the rightness of action that is wholly inscrutable to agents themselves—and there is excellent reason to think Nietzsche takes us to be so opaque—is not a very helpful criterion, if it counts as a criterion at all.

Finally, we should also bear in mind Nietzsche’s own observation that the very idea of a causal connection between motives and actions becomes significant only in a context in which we’re interested in getting moral guidance or making attributions of moral responsibility and evaluating actions for the sake of assigning praise and blame. It is those attributions that the notion of “intentions” arises to support, and the only ones who have a vested interest in supporting the connection at all are those committed to the values characteristic of slave morality. Swanton’s attribution of this theory of “right action” to Nietzsche not only outstrips the textual support to fashion him into a moral philosopher—something he seems otherwise Hell-bent on not being, as we shall see in the next section—but it puts him in league with the ascetic ones.

To supply Nietzsche with an answer to her second question, what counts as a virtuous trait of character, Swanton goes further still, and with equally unacceptable results. She openly admits this will be a difficult question to answer on Nietzsche’s behalf, not for the obvious reasons that Nietzsche does not seem to give the concept of a ‘virtue’ any sustained treatment, or that he is deeply suspicious that we have sufficient psychological stability to support identifiable traits of character at all, but rather for the reason that Nietzsche, “it turns out… apparently admires traits which are arguably sick, such as narcissistic grandiosity.”Footnote 8 The remainder of her theory, which she develops but does not substantially revise in later works, is essentially constructed as an answer to the question she asks next, namely, “How can this be?”

Swanton is right to worry that if there is a virtue ethic to which Nietzsche can be committed, the list of virtues it is likely to generate will include several that sit uncomfortably with our civilized modern sensibilities, and that the portrait it develops of the ideal or virtuous type may not be one we are eager to recognize as “flourishing”:

Inasmuch as a determinate picture of the, or an, ideal type is discernible in Nietzsche, an exemplar of that type is depicted as a sad figure, for whom “marriage is a calamity,” who follows in most cases “the path to unhappiness” (GM III:7), who leaves society so far behind that he “comes to grief” and “can’t go back to the pity of men” (BGE 29). This does not look like a picture of eudaimonia […].Footnote 9

Bizarrely, in Swanton’s criticism of Nietzsche’s “higher type” in this passage—inasmuch as it is discernible, as she says—she employs as criteria of evaluation many aspects of “the good” that Nietzsche’s philosophy calls into question, here including even the bourgeois contentment of marriage as a measure of the goodness or success of a life! Setting aside for the moment the issue of the defensibility of such criteria, once employed, they will militate against our accepting as virtues many of the things Nietzsche seems in fact to applaud.

For instance, in her most recent work,Footnote 10 Swanton is determined to argue that Nietzsche condemns cruelty as a vice, lest it get included on the list of “arguably sick” traits of character he apparently supports. This interpretation is deeply problematic against the background of Nietzsche’s Genealogy, in which he argues that cruelty is a fundamental human instinct.Footnote 11 Swanton acknowledges this point, but she says we ought just to read Nietzsche instead as having thought that aggressiveness, not cruelty, is a fundamental human instinct; and aggressiveness, she contends, “constitutes part of the field of a virtue of proper assertiveness.”Footnote 12 Problem solved. Unfortunately, however, there is no clear textual support in Nietzsche for the claim that by ‘cruelty’ [Grausamkeit] he always means merely “aggressiveness” of the sort that Freud reckoned to be part of the basic package of drives common to all human animals. Moreover, when he does discuss cruelty, he does not obviously condemn it.Footnote 13

Rather than taking any of this to indicate that Nietzsche may not be a good candidate for a virtue theorist, Swanton posits what may be most aptly described as a “Bizarro World” virtue theory.Footnote 14 On this reading, Bizarro-Nietzsche is a Schopenhauerian pessimist who finds the world irredeemably bad and its inhabitants incurably sick;Footnote 15 but he is deeply concerned for them and their comfort, which apparently motivates him to develop an affirmative ethic that encourages them toward life-affirmation—the measure of a good life—and is intended to get them to love themselves.Footnote 16 Bad or otherwise undesirable character traits turn out to be good traits, then, in a sufficiently bad world.Footnote 17 In later work, Swanton responds to the problem of cruelty with a slightly modified but equally elaborate reading according to which, although Nietzsche appears to valorize the “noble morality” that condones cruelty and its zealous expressions, he does not do so in absolute terms, but only relative to slave morality, and then only with the qualification that the cruelty nobles express is an expression of their “immaturity” (or, more precisely, an “immature egoism”), which, Nietzsche advises, everyone ought to avoid.Footnote 18

To say there is no strong textual support for these tortured interpretations is an understatement. Most troubling about them is that they invariably make Nietzsche precisely the sort of moralist and “improver of mankind” he constantly criticizes; we find him dispensing advice to the herd about how they “ought” to be and what they ought to do, and endorsing the very moral opposites he was supposed to be getting “beyond.” On the topic of cruelty specifically, consider his exasperated lament in Beyond Good and Evil: “People should rethink their ideas about cruelty and open up their eyes; they should finally learn impatience, so that big, fat, presumptuous mistakes like this [i.e., the denial that human beings are by nature cruel and that all we call “higher culture” would not be possible without it] will stop wandering virtuously and audaciously about” (BGE 229).Footnote 19 If we find Nietzsche issuing a condemnation of anything in this passage, it is not cruelty, but rather the reaction of those who squeamishly recoil from it and cannot see in it anything but vice or “immaturity.”

In his book-length treatment of Nietzsche and virtue,Footnote 20 Lester Hunt is similarly forced to go beyond the texts to fill out his portrait of Nietzsche as a virtue theorist. Like Swanton, Hunt claims to find what Nietzsche never straightforwardly supplies, beginning with an account of virtue. According to Hunt, Nietzsche’s “most general discussion of the nature of virtue” is to be found in Part I of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, in the chapter, “On Enjoying and Suffering the Passions [Von den Freuden- und Leidenschaften],” and so he focuses his efforts on this cryptic stretch of text.Footnote 21 Here, he argues, Nietzsche offers a definition of virtue clear and robust enough to serve as the cornerstone of a theory that will allow us “even [to] give lists of the virtues that are the most important,” lest we think “Nietzsche is unable to supply us with procedures for distinguishing virtues from non-virtues.”Footnote 22

In Zarathustra, Hunt says, we find Nietzsche engaged in advancing a theory according to which what begin as passions, which one might take to be “to some extent incompatible with human power and freedom,” undergo a “liberating transformation” to become virtues “that may be instruments of freedom and power.”Footnote 23 Passions, it seems to me, occupy a different conceptual category from virtues, and it is never made quite clear what sort of alchemy it takes to magic one into the other.Footnote 24 According to Hunt, though, “Passions become virtues,” or perhaps the having of certain regular or lasting or defining passions ought to be considered “virtuous,” “when they contribute to the pursuit of one’s highest goal.”Footnote 25 The appeal to our activity as goal-directed then suggests to Hunt that “we can most easily achieve lucidity about what this connection is [between “overcoming,” destruction and creation in Zarathustra] by going directly to a discussion of Nietzsche’s doctrine of the will to power. “As we shall soon see,” he promises, “the ‘overcoming’ that [Nietzsche] says is involved in the creation of virtue is the same thing as the will to power.”Footnote 26

Here, we must remember that unless we help ourselves liberally to material Nietzsche chose not to publish, there is no sense to be made of the “will to power” beyond a psychological principle that helps to explain animal behavior, and human behavior insofar as we are, after all, animals. Thus I am skeptical about the extent to which “we can most easily achieve lucidity” about the still-nebulous concepts of virtue, passion and overcoming in Part I of Zarathustra by appeal to the even more nebulous “doctrine” of the will to power. In addition, in order to accept Hunt’s definition of Nietzschean “virtue,” we must also be open to taking the character Zarathustra’s oracular pronouncements as claims the propositional content of which can be fairly straightforwardly represented and attributed to Nietzsche as his views, for which he uses the text, Zarathustra, to argue. This is a contentious position, which at the very least stands in need of further defense.

Other commentators have been tempted to similarly extreme measures in their efforts to grow an affirmative morality out of Nietzsche’s unsystematic and scattershot remarks on virtue and vice. Although it is scarcely noticed in the relevant literature, I believe the first of these many attempts to find in Nietzsche an ethic of virtue—or, failing to find it, to furnish him with one—is Robert Solomon’s 1985 essay, “A More Severe Morality: Nietzsche’s Affirmative Ethics.”Footnote 27 Juxtaposing Kant’s ethics of rules and categorical principles with Aristotle’s “ethics of practice,” drawing our attention (quite rightly) to a number of similarities between Nietzsche’s and Aristotle’s outlook on things, and reminding us of Nietzsche’s concern for the creation of new values, Solomon says:

What I want to argue here should be, in part at least, transparent. Nietzsche may talk about “creating new values,” but—as he himself often says, it is something of a return to an old and neglected set of values—the values of masterly virtue—that most concerns him. There are complications. We do not have the ethos of The Illiad, nor even the tamer ethe of Homer or Aristotle…. There is no context, in other words, within which the new virtues we are to “create” are to be virtues, for a virtue without a practice is of no more value than a word without a language, a gesture without a context.Footnote 28

In the rest of his essay, Solomon turns his attention to solving the problem of context, but what I find striking about this passage is the way Nietzsche’s demand for the creation of new values, which we find everywhere in his work, is casually rephrased as a demand for the creation of new virtues. Values and virtues may, naturally enough, be connected, but in this passage the connection is presupposed rather than drawn. And unfortunately, if we reject the substitution of one term for another, on which the remainder of Solomon’s essay appears to be predicated, then there is little support for his version of the virtue-theoretic reading.

Solomon’s reading also conflates a stronger and a weaker statement of Nietzsche’s attitude toward the Greeks and toward the “master morality” of the first essay of the Genealogy, which is supposed to provide whatever content Nietzsche’s “aretaic ethics” will have, in order to fill in in some significant gaps. Nietzsche admires the Greeks. But we will not find any support for the claim that Nietzsche thinks admiration warrants emulation. Quite the contrary, like his German Romantic predecessors, Nietzsche takes our recognition of the greatness of Hellenic culture to leave us in a precarious situation precisely because he recognizes that nostalgia is an unhealthy condition to live in, and because he sees that we cannot go back: their values would just as soon kill us all as make us any stronger. Solomon appreciates this to some extent, of course, which is why he reads Nietzsche as encouraging the creation of new values (virtues) appropriate to our time and place. Ultimately, though, his formulation of the ethics he takes Nietzsche to be developing would commit us to something much stronger: “Aristotle and Achilles versus Kant and Christianity.”Footnote 29 But this slogan would situate Nietzsche squarely in the black-and-white, comic-strip world of ‘good’ and ‘evil’ that he so clearly aimed to oppose.

Finally, in Thomas Brobjer’s 2003 article, “Nietzsche’s Affirmative Morality: An Ethics of Virtue,”Footnote 30 we find the same contradiction and a similar substitution of stronger for weaker—and more plausible (but not less interesting)—theses in Nietzsche’s work. Since he apparently takes himself to be the only one to have had the idea that Nietzsche offers a positive ethics best articulated as a virtue theory,Footnote 31 Brobjer dooms himself to repeating many of the mistakes of the past. In the service of inflating Nietzsche’s affirmative attitude toward Hellenic culture into a full-blown moral theory, he is willing to equivocate: “It is well known that Nietzsche rejects the idea of philosophical systems as being in any sense true or valuable per se. Hence he rejects all attempts at systematization. I will not dispute this claim as such, but Nietzsche does nonetheless, in a sense, believe in the existence of ‘systems’.”Footnote 32 Furthermore, Brobjer acknowledges initially (and rightly) that Nietzsche “rejects the belief in moral opposites,” but he nevertheless says that on Nietzsche’s view, “acts will not so much be regarded as good or evil, or right or wrong, but will be judged rather as worthy or unworthy, or sometimes more directly related to character traits (virtues), for example, as brave, dishonest, or unjust.”Footnote 33 And, more consistently and even more visibly than in some other cases, his reading conflates stronger and weaker formulations of Nietzsche’s views: Brobjer gets basically right, for instance, that “the fundamental aspect of Nietzsche’s moral judgment and thinking is his concern and emphasis of personality and character,” but then he simply says, “I call this aspect an ethics of character, but it could also be called an ethics of virtue.”Footnote 34 Similarly, his claim that “Nietzsche, like the Greeks, wanted to set up personality, character, or ‘the most successful exemplars’ as ideals” is a stronger version of the more accurate view that both Nietzsche and many Greek thinkers he admired were more interested in character and personality than in principles and propositions.Footnote 35

3 The Second Obstacle: Nietzsche’s “Immoralism”

Not only does Nietzsche refuse to aid and abet virtue-theoretic readers of his texts; he works aggressively, it seems, to confound them. By declaring himself, without qualification, an opponent of morality and by adopting the moniker “immoralist,” Nietzsche signals his refusal to contribute yet another “majestic moral structure” to the long history of failed attempts to erect them (D P:3). Rather, he describes his project in Daybreak in quite sweeping terms; his aim, which he describes as “immoral,” is “to criticize morality itself, to regard morality as a problem, as problematic” (D P:3). And in the preface to the Genealogy, he claims that, where he asks questions, “the belief in morality, all morality, totters” (GM P:6). Lester Hunt concedes early on in his analysis that “the exact nature of [Nietzsche’s] immoralism is quite problematic.”Footnote 36 At times, he says, Nietzsche’s claims to be an immoralist sound “extreme,” as if Nietzsche means to provide “an alternative to the moral way of thinking as such.”Footnote 37 That, of course, would render moot the strenuous efforts to read Nietzsche as endorsing a moral theory.

Some readers simply ignore this problem. Interpreting Nietzsche as a virtue-minded philosopher “who has something to offer substantive moral theory,”Footnote 38 Christine Swanton effectively denies (primarily by omission) that Nietzsche’s “immoralism,” his campaign against morality in general, troubles her interpretative approach. Nowhere does she appear to recognize it as a serious obstacle to reading him as a substantive moralist,Footnote 39 and so she never genuinely doubts that there is an affirmative ethic to be wrung from Nietzsche’s texts. By reading quite selectively, and by treating the texts in piecemeal fashion, she altogether avoids the question of why her reading of Nietzsche is so at odds with the various self-descriptions and “mission statements” we find in, say, Nietzsche’s (1886) prefaces, where he characterizes his project as an attack on all morality. Swanton does not accord these passages due consideration, and although she mentions she does not quote or discuss at any length Nietzsche’s self-attributions of “immoralism.”

Lester Hunt acknowledges more appropriately the depth of the problem. His solution turns on the claim that Nietzsche uses the term ‘immoralism’ sometimes in a more and sometimes in a less restrictive way, which is surely true.Footnote 40 But he does not subject the less restrictive passages to close scrutiny. Instead, he suggests we begin altogether elsewhere. Reasoning that the opposite of “immoralism” is “moralism,” or “morality,” he begins by examining what Nietzsche says about the latter (morality), and then attempts to develop an understanding of immoralism via negativa. After rehearsing Nietzsche’s critiques of the concept of responsibility, of morality’s ambition to make prescriptions about the way things “ought” to be, independently of how they are, of the belief in “opposite values,” and of the mutually dependent concepts of disinterestedness and universality, Hunt says: “Taken together, these ideas constitute an elaborate definition of a familiar sense of the word ‘morality’. More specifically, anyone who knows the history of philosophy should immediately recognize that they represent Immanuel Kant’s conception of ‘morality’.”Footnote 41 Hunt therefore posits a distinction, between little-‘m’ “morality” and big-‘M’ “Morality,” and argues that Nietzsche rejects only the latter, which turns out to be Kantian morality. Thus he concludes, “we can see now that there is no inconsistency in admiring some moralities while attacking Morality as such. Morality, in the capitalized sense, is a very distinctive sort of code […].”Footnote 42

There are at least two serious problems with this reading. For one thing, we should be deeply suspicious of a reading that allows “morality” to be so easily specified; Nietzsche does not have so monolithic an image of morality. He is interested in it as a powerful social force and cultural phenomenon, and his later works especially concern themselves with the many guises and manifestations of morality in human culture—in science, in the arts, in a wide variety of secular and not obviously philosophical enterprises. Consider how very odd it would be if the author of the Genealogy and the innovator of the method of investigation employed there, the man who writes that “only that which has no history is definable” (GM II:13), were here to abandon his rich conception of human practices and their metamorphosis over time, and adopt an uncomplicated conception of the phenomenon that remains the focal point of his interests—namely, Kantian morality, neatly axiomatized. Among other things, Hunt’s interpretation would reduce Nietzsche to a critic of moral philosophy quite narrowly circumscribed, rather than a critic of morality, as he describes himself. This reading requires us to deny to Nietzsche the complexity he finds in the very phenomena in which he is most interested.

The second problem is one Hunt sees and attempts to forestall; namely, that his conclusion will “trivialize Nietzsche’s immoralism into an attack on Kant.”Footnote 43 He replies, in effect, that while many thinkers reject this or that feature of Kantian morality, Nietzsche stands apart by rejecting all its central tenets, which is a position radically critical of the philosophical orthodoxy: since most ethical philosophers today accept various of these tenets, “what Nietzsche attacks is what these philosophers believe in.”Footnote 44 But even this is a serious understatement, impossible to reconcile with Nietzsche’s dramatic characterizations of his project and its ramifications: “I know my lot,” Nietzsche says, “One day my name will be connected with the memory of something tremendous,—a crisis such as the earth has never seen, […] a decision made against everything that has been believed, demanded, held sacred so far. I am not a human being, I am dynamite” (EH “Destiny” 1). Be one ever so sharply critical of Immanuel Kant and his theory of morality, it is hard to believe that one’s stance would make one candidate for “the most terrible human being who has ever existed,” or “the destroyer par excellence” (EH “Destiny” 2). And yet, Nietzsche declares that he is “a world-historical monster”: “I am, in Greek, and not just in Greek, the Anti-Christ…” (EH “Books” 2). In the face of declarations like these, Hunt demurs, and straightforwardly denies: “There is likely to be at least one instance in which he is simply not choosing his words as carefully as he usually does.”Footnote 45 Hunt’s reading thus requires that we deny that Nietzsche means what he says in any of these (many) passages.

The same reading is advanced by Robert Solomon. In his original essay, he commits himself almost a priori, and for reasons I shall examine below, to the notion that there is an affirmative morality in Nietzsche. Thus, he is all but forced to say that Nietzsche’s “immoralist” critique is “misinterpreted as a broad-based rejection of all morality (for example, by Philippa Foot, who is one of Nietzsche’s more sensitive Anglo-American readers).”Footnote 46 But, we might ask incredulously, how can this claim—that the scope of Nietzsche’s intended critique is “all” morality—be a misinterpretation of what Nietzsche says if it is what Nietzsche says? Solomon’s answer is that we ought not take Nietzsche at his word; simply put, “to write about Nietzsche as a literal ‘immoralist’ and the destroyer of morality is to read him badly, or it is to confuse the appearance with the personality. Or, [Nietzsche] would say, it is to be a ‘dolt’.”Footnote 47 What of Nietzsche’s well-documented ambition to undertake the transvaluation of all values? “Over-reaching nonsense,” says Solomon!Footnote 48 “And as for ‘the tradition’, as it has come to be called, Nietzsche as philosopher can be understood only within it, despite his unself-critical megalomania about his own ‘untimely’ and wholly novel importance.”Footnote 49 Apparently, Nietzsche’s problem is “that he sees himself as a destroyer, not a reformer or revisionist.”Footnote 50 So, although Solomon starts off bristling at the “rather systematic whitewashing of Nietzsche” to which he says we have been treated in recent years,Footnote 51 it is curiously difficult to see the radical—not to say, “rabid”—firebrand Nietzsche behind the now toothless immoralism of this “good old enlightenment critic.”Footnote 52 Indeed, according to Solomon, “it would not be wrong…to see Nietzsche as an old-fashioned moralist, disgusted with the world around him but unable to provide a satisfactory account of an alternative and unable to find a context in which an alternative could be properly cultivated.”Footnote 53 “Nietzsche’s nihilism,” as he calls it, is basically just a reaction against the “hollowness” of modern moral philosophy generally; more specifically, it is “a reaction against a quite particular conception of morality, summarized in modern times in the ethics of Kant.”Footnote 54

Again, then, we see that in order to make Nietzsche’s immoralism compatible with any serious commitment to an affirmative ethical theory, we must either dismiss or liberally rewrite a good deal of what he actually says, or else we must ignore whatever sounds to our ears implausible, or untoward or grandiose, or that stands in the way of our unearthing, or even fabricating, Nietzsche’s “ethical teachings.” At this point, one must surely begin to suspect that, philologically speaking, things have taken a calamitous turn. How did this happen? I think Solomon’s essay is suggestive of an answer. His attribution of an ethic of virtue to Nietzsche is framed as a response to the dilemma that he says Alasdair MacIntyre’s book, After Virtue, forced upon us: “Nietzsche or Aristotle?”Footnote 55

There is, [MacIntyre] explicitly warns us, no third alternative. MacIntyre sees Nietzsche’s philosophy as purely destructive, despite the fact that he praises the arch-destroyer for his insight into the collapse of morals that had been increasingly evident since the Enlightenment. MacIntryre chooses Aristotle as the positive alternative. Aristotle had an ethos; Nietzsche leaves us with nothing. [But] MacIntyre, by opposing Nietzsche and Aristotle, closes off to us the basis upon which we could best reconceive morality: a reconsideration of Aristotle through Nietzschean eyes.Footnote 56

It is that reconsideration that Solomon undertakes in his essay. His conclusion, contra MacIntyre, is that not only is there “in Nietzsche, unmistakably, an ethics,” but it is “an ethics that is very much part of ‘the tradition’.”Footnote 57 I applaud Solomon’s (under-appreciated) efforts to rescue Nietzsche from MacIntyre’s rather ham-fisted treatment of him, but I want to suggest that we need not go as far as Solomon does to accomplish it.

Essentially, I believe Solomon goes wrong in accepting MacIntyre’s terms of debate. MacIntyre identifies immoralism, the heading under which Nietzsche opposes “all morality, morality as such,” as a kind of nihilism. Solomon wants, quite sensibly, to deny that Nietzsche is a nihilist. But he accepts MacIntyre’s presupposition that to demolish morality without installing something in its place is to be a nihilist; the only alternatives are to embrace (affirmative) moralism or succumb to (dangerous) nihilism. Thus, it looks like we will have to deny that “immoralism” means what Nietzsche says it does and be willing to go well beyond his texts to supply him with a moral theory, if we are to avoid the dour assessment that Nietzsche’s thought leads us “to nothing substantial at all.”Footnote 58 Fortunately for Nietzsche’s readers, I think, this dilemma is a false one.Footnote 59

4 Good Philology

The obstacles to a virtue theoretic reading discussed in the preceding sections have compelled virtue theorists to adopt creative interpretive tactics. At the outset, Lester Hunt, in his book, warns us that: “The process by which we come to understand Nietzsche includes, as a part of it, one in which we subject him to a test. Thus it may also represent the beginning of a process which results in our denying him and going beyond him.”Footnote 60 And we have found instances of both denial and excess in the literature.

The pitfalls in these interpretations can be avoided, however, if only we strive to be the “good readers” of his works that Nietzsche demands: “the sort of reader I deserve,” he says, “reads me as good old philologists read their Horace” (EH “Books” 5),Footnote 61 which is to say creatively, but also with patience, subtlety and caution. Instead of the twin principles of denial and excess, we should cultivate what we might call the philological virtues. For instance, we should at least begin by assuming that Nietzsche says what he means to say. Here, I am proposing that we do precisely what Solomon says we ought not to do—that is, that we read him literally and that we abandon the literal reading only when the text cannot be made sense of any other way. Obviously, we can’t take him literally all the time; that would both distort the texts and take a good deal of the pleasure out of reading Nietzsche. But judicious application of this principle ought to keep Nietzsche’s puns and jokes, his ironies and allusions, that is, his style, perfectly well intact; we have to be sensitive to his use of those literary devices or we stand to miss a good deal of what makes Nietzsche’s works valuable. To the extent that we care what Nietzsche thought, however, I think we are obliged (i) to read what he says (especially in those texts that he intended for publication), (ii) to take it seriously, and (iii) to try to understand what it means, on its own terms.

By that last qualification, I mean to suggest that we should assume the texts are complete unless we have clear reasons to suppose otherwise and, by all means, refrain from “supplying” Nietzsche with theories he does not himself make any attempt to develop.Footnote 62 The virtue-theoretic readings of Nietzsche are all reconstructions, but it is well worth pausing to ask why a reconstruction is called for. Reconstruction is something we must do in cases where a text is obviously incomplete or for some other reason fails to make sense on its own; the fragmentary nature of the extant texts of the pre-Platonic philosophers, for instance, makes anything but a reconstructive approach to interpretation impossible. But I am far from convinced that such an approach is licensed, much less required in the case of Nietzsche, whose published works are anything but fragmentary.

My skepticism about what warrants the radically reconstructive approach commentators have taken, in fact, leads me to wonder whether another aspect of what motivates it—one that may explain the widespread acceptance of what I have described as a false dilemma—is something like an a priori determination to find, perhaps for idiosyncratic psychological reasons, a set of Nietzschean “ethical teachings.” That is to say, even scholars of Nietzsche’s thought seem to have yielded to the powerful desire for moral guidance, though I believe what Nietzsche asks us to imagine is the possibility of overcoming that very desire. Thus, he does not tell us—nor is there any reason to think he takes it to be his job to tell us—how to think about cruelty or immorality or virtue or value or anything else. His task is difficult enough; namely, to get us to “rethink” it and to stop taking for granted that its meaning and value are obvious, and to undermine our “faith” in morality, but without putting something in its place.

Two objections will surely be made at this point. One is that it is not possible psychologically to live without moral commitments of some description or other. The other is that even if it is possible, Nietzsche certainly does not do it. How, one might ask, are we to make sense of the evaluative remarks he makes with such violent emphasis if he has no such commitments? When commentators ask this question, they seem to me to presuppose the necessary existence of a background theory in light of which his strong evaluative expressions are to be explained and justified, lest they be mere “opinions” or “preferences,” or expressions of “taste.” But this is just how Nietzsche himself so often describes them (e.g., GM P:2; BGE 186, 267). The presupposition is that there must be a thread that pulls them all together; otherwise they exert no pressure on our own views. Here, it is interesting to consider an analogy: when faced with the fact of tremendous suffering in the world, the religious believer is faced with two tasks—the explanation and the justification of that suffering in light of the fact of God’s existence. These are the twin tasks of any theodicy. What we find in the literature on Nietzsche and virtue is a number of commentators laboring away at the construction of a theodicy for (i.e., an explanation for the rationality of) Nietzsche’s evaluations of us and our situation. That behavior is entirely predictable on Nietzsche’s own psychological account, but its persistence in the scholarship on Nietzsche demonstrates nothing so clearly as that we have failed to grasp the ramifications of that account and, indeed, that the landscape he so desired to alter has remained unchanged.

Of course there are many things Nietzsche clearly prefers and values, and there are many more things for which he expresses disdain or contempt; many traits he praises as “virtues” and many other traditional vices that he provocatively champions. And he is well aware that we, too, will always have our evaluations of things; it is a natural psychological fact about human beings that we are the “evaluating animals par excellence.” But a great deal of this valuing and disvaluing can go on without our having an overarching theory that either generates the value judgments or justifies them. Nietzsche seems to think (perhaps correctly) that the need for moral guidance or a procedure for generating value judgments—or rules for action, or lists of virtues, or criteria for identifying the virtuous individual—arises only where humans have utterly lost their way and are incapable of making value judgments and prioritizing values on their own. In other words, on Nietzsche’s view, the need for a justificatory principle arises only where humans either do not know or cannot trust themselves to issue judgments otherwise. That hopeless condition is nihilism: it is humanity’s loss of faith in itself, and it is very often just staved off by our placing that faith in someone or something else. Thus, one of the chief symptoms of this nihilistic condition is what Nietzsche variously calls the old, familiar “metaphysical need”Footnote 63 or our “need to believe.”

What Nietzsche is suggesting is that our own reluctance to value and disvalue in the absence of a theory to which to appeal is itself symptomatic of an illness. In light of this, I find it difficult not to read Gay Science 347 as a kind of statement on the scholarship dedicated to uncovering and codifying Nietzsche’s own “severe morality”:

How much one needs a faith in order to flourish, how much that is “firm” and that one does not wish to be shaken because one clings to it, that is a measure of the degree of one’s strength (or, to put the point more clearly, of one’s weakness). […] For this is how man is: An article of faith could be refuted before him a thousand times—if he needed it, he would consider it “true” again and again […]. Metaphysics is still needed by some; but so is that impetuous demand for certainty that today discharges itself among large numbers of people in a scientific-positivistic form. The demand that one wants by all means that something should be firm (while on account of the ardor of this demand one is easier and more negligent about the demonstration of this certainty)—this, too, is still the demand for a support, a prop, in short, that instinct of weakness which, to be sure, does not create religious, metaphysical systems, and convictions of all kinds but—conserves them. […] Faith is always coveted most and needed most urgently where will is lacking; for will, as the affect of command, is the decisive sign of sovereignty and strength. In other words, the less one knows how to command, the more urgently one covets someone who commands severely—a god, prince, class, physician, father confessor, dogma or party conscience. (GS 347)Footnote 64

Nietzsche’s appeal to the “ardor” of the demand for something firm, certain, principled—for a theory—suggests an argument to the best explanation for the easy negligence of some of the interpretations we have examined.

If we return to the false dilemma, “Nietzsche or Aristotle,” we should be able to see better that taking Nietzsche’s side seriously need not mean transmogrifying Nietzsche into Aristotle’s modern cousin. In my view, Nietzsche’s critical work does, in the end, “leave us with nothing,” just as Solomon says MacIntyre charged, but that does not make him a nihilist in the pernicious sense. Human beings have long wondered what is the best kind of life for man, what it means to live a flourishing or valuable life, what we ought to do. But Nietzsche points out that for over two millennia we’ve been producing theories no one of which is clearly superior to the others. Perhaps—just perhaps—there has been something wrong with the attempt. Nietzsche’s immoralism expresses what is perhaps an ambitious hope for himself and a challenge to us to imagine that one may at the same time reject morality as such, all morality, and yet not be a nihilist. This is to read Nietzsche as Hunt suggests we might, though he ultimately thinks we ought not, as intending to provide “an alternative to the moral way of thinking as such.” This challenge follows upon what is perhaps Nietzsche’s most important discovery: that the entire enterprise of philosophizing about morality is itself an irreducibly moral enterprise.

The necessary components of a virtue theory are missing from Nietzsche’s work, and their absence is no oversight. Nietzsche’s “immoralism,” his stated opposition to morality as such, all morality (GM P:6), cannot be reconciled with the attribution to him of a normatively successful moral theory. Since he approaches morality from a position outside theory altogether, since he finds joy in “that free, fearless hovering over men, customs, laws and the traditional evaluations of things” (HH 34), his position is far more aptly characterized as “anti-theory.”Footnote 65 Nietzsche’s novel critical project, to promote suspicion, on a grand scale, about the kinds of prior commitments and presuppositions without which there could be no morality at all, leaves the important questions unresolved and very much open-ended. He surely does not close off the possibility that something may one day answer to the name of ‘morality’ and nevertheless escape the hammer blow of his criticism. But to be open to a possibility and to develop it oneself (or to recommend or demand that we develop it) are two very different things. Scholars unsatisfied with the open-ended reading seem to neglect this, however, and leap to realize that possibility on Nietzsche’s behalf.

There have been a number of valiant efforts to make Nietzsche, quite against his will, a staid and respectable member of a continuous moral philosophical tradition from Aristotle to Anscombe. But the insistence on ascribing to Nietzsche an affirmative ethical theory, I think, does him and his texts an injustice and impedes our understanding of his thought and what makes it genuinely distinctive. It represents not only an unwillingness to confront the textual evidence for Nietzsche’s “immoralism,” but also to appreciate the peculiar challenge that it is meant to issue. On a robust understanding of what Nietzsche asks us to imagine—namely, the possibility that one could live without value commitments of the sort “morality” has required and could nevertheless not be a nihilist—he is precisely what he says he is: not an immoralist, but the first immoralist. Not a critic; but the destroyer par excellence, who is, in so being, also “a bearer of glad tidings as no one ever was before” (EH “Destiny” 1).