When is it morally appropriate to disregard the rights of the individual for the wellbeing of the larger group? A burgeoning literature on peoples’ responses to ethical dilemmas has helped to provide an empirical backdrop on how we approach such issues. Central in this field is the study of trolley-style moral dilemmas in which participants are asked whether they consider it appropriate to actively sacrifice the life of a single individual to ensure that the lives of multiple others are saved. These dilemmas contrast an outcome-focused, consequentialist moral logic (i.e., sacrifice one to save many; Rosen, 2005), with a deontological moral logic that focuses on rights, duties and a disavowal of active harm (Alexander & Moore, 2008). The main theory within the field, a dual-process model (Cushman, 2013; Greene, 2007), suggests that each of these two different perspectives is related to a different psychological process. When confronted with a moral dilemma, two processes compete to determine our judgment: a fast, intuitive, automatic process linked with a preference for deontological moral judgment, and a cognitive, deliberative, reasoning-based process that steers our preference toward a consequentialist logic, which weighs the harms versus the potential benefits of each course of action.

This dual-process model was advanced in seminal work by Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, and Cohen (2001). Using neuroimaging techniques, they uncovered that consequentialist moral judgment was associated with increased activation in “cognitive” areas of the brain such as the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, whereas deontological moral judgment was associated with increased activation in “emotional” areas of the brain such as the medial prefrontal cortex. The association of deontological judgment with emotional reactivity has been widely corroborated. For instance, individual differences in empathic concern are consistently associated with deontological judgment (r = .17, p = .02, N = 194—Kahane, Everett, Earp, Farias, & Savulescu, 2015; r = .28, p < .001, N = 112—Conway & Gawronski, 2013; r = .30, p < .001, N = 296—Reynolds & Conway, 2018; ds = 0.64 and 0.52, p < .001 and p < .001, Ns = 718 and 366—Gleichgerrcht & Young, 2013). Interestingly, these associations are not related to concern for the sacrificial victim, but because people high in empathic concern are more aversive of the sacrificial action (Miller, Hannikainen, & Cushman, 2014).

In contrast, the association of deliberate cognition with consequentialist judgment appears to be more tenuous. Greene, Morelli, Lowenberg, Nystrom, and Cohen (2008) attempted to experimentally decrease participants’ inclination to deliberate and found that a concurrent cognitive load decreased the speed of consequentialist but not of deontological judgments (p = .002, N = 82).Footnote 1 Some studies have failed to replicate this effect (d = 0.10, p = .110, N = 311—Tinghög et al., 2016; p = .273, N = 85—Cova et al., 2018), whereas others have uncovered a load effect not on response time but on participants’ overall inclination toward consequentialist judgment (d = 0.73, p = .009, N = 57—Conway & Gawronski, 2013; \( {\eta}_p^2 \) = .033, p < .015, N = 191—Białek & De Neys, 2017; see also Trémolière, & Bonnefon, 2014).

Relatedly, some studies have attempted to increase participants’ inclination to deliberate—for instance, by administering the Cognitive Reflection Test (CRT; Frederick, 2005). The CRT is a reasoning test that asks participants to solve mathematical riddles. Although the correct answers to these riddles require only elementary calculations, they necessitate the suppression of an intuitively appealing wrong answer. Paxton, Ungar, and Greene (2012) found that administering the CRT increased the likelihood of consequentialist judgment (d = 0.43, p = .05, N = 91), but another study failed to replicate this effect (d = – 0.13, p = .24, N = 297—Cova et al., 2018).

Individual difference studies are similarly mixed. Paxton, Ungar, and Greene (2012) reported a positive association of participants’ CRT scores with consequentialist judgment (r = .39, p = .001, N = 41). Aktas, Yılmaz, and Bahçekapılı (2017) replicated this finding in a first study (r = .15, p < .01, N = 269), but not in a second one (r = .00, p > .05, N = 246), nor did Cova et al. (2018; r = .08, p = .11, N = 316; see also Baron, Scott, Fincher, & Metz, 2015; Royzman, Landy, & Leeman, 2015).

One reason why the literature might be mixed is that deliberative reasoning has two components: a motivational component and an ability component. For a deliberative process to suppress intuitive processing, both the motivation to expend the necessary cognitive resources and the availability of these resources (i.e., cognitive ability) are relevant. The existing literature on the dual-process model for moral cognition has not differentiated between the motivational and ability components of deliberate reasoning. This is peculiar, as Evans and Stanovich (2013) have suggested that the ability component is in fact the “defining” aspect of deliberative reasoning. For most of the measures that have been used to study the association of “deliberate reasoning” with consequentialist judgment, the motivational and ability components are heavily entwined. For instance, the CRT is typically perceived as a measure of participants’ cognitive style (intuitive vs. reasoned), but it also correlates well with general intelligence (approximately r = .42, p < .001, N = 376; Saribay & Yilmaz, 2017). Any association that the CRT might (or might not) have with consequentialist judgment could be caused by either the motivational or the ability component of deliberate reasoning. Similarly, most experimental manipulations impact both motivation and ability simultaneously. A concurrent cognitive load not only hinders participants’ ability to deliberate, but also impacts their motivation to complete a second, demanding task (Roets & Van Hiel, 2011).

Despite the large literature on the association of consequentialist moral judgments with deliberative reasoning, we are not aware of any study that has directly investigated whether cognitive ability itself plays a role in this connection. Perhaps most similar is a series of studies by Moore, Clark, and Kane (2008) that investigated whether working memory capacity is related to consequentialist judgment, and they did not find a consistent effect. Investigating the association between intelligence and consequentialist moral reasoning would help clarify the nature of the inconsistent associations between consequentialist and deliberative reasoning in the literature.

The present manuscript investigates this issue through an internal meta-analysis of three studies. The data for Study 1 were gathered as part of two unrelated projects. We decided to combine the cognitive ability and moral judgment data of both projects and investigate their possible association through an unplanned, exploratory test. The result of this test served as the impetus for gathering additional data. The data for Studies 2 and 3, although not preregistered, were gathered with the explicit intent of testing this association.Footnote 2 No other hypotheses were explored for the latter two studies. We report how we determined our sample size, all data exclusions (none), and all measures in these studies.

Method

Participants and sample size

We conducted a total of three studies. Table 1 describes demographic statistics. For Studies 1 (n = 210) and 2 (n = 211), undergraduate students at a Belgian university completed the relevant measures for course credit. For Study 3 (n = 254), North American participants were recruited from Amazon Mechanical Turk and paid US$1.15. The participants in Studies 1 and 2 were able to choose from multiple time slots but were not informed about the nature of the studies that would be conducted during each time slot. For Studies 1 and 2, we aimed for samples with n > 200 (80% power for r ≥ .20). For Study 3, we aimed for a more powerful study (90% power when assuming a population effect size of r ≥ .20). No specific instructions were given to participants during any of the studies.

Table 1 Sample size and summary demographic statistics

Measures

Cognitive ability

In Studies 1 and 2, cognitive ability was measured with a shortened version of the Wilde Intelligence Test (λ2s = .70 and .75; see Kersting, Althoff, & Jäger, 2008). In this test, participants are presented with 45 logic problems tapping fluid intelligence and are instructed to solve as many problems as possible in 12 min. The number of correct responses constitutes the participant’s ability score.

In Study 3, cognitive ability was measured as the number of correct responses on the ten-item WordSum test (α = .77), a vocabulary subtest from the Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale (Zhu & Weiss, 2005), that is used as a measure of general intelligence in the General Social Survey. In this test, participants are presented with ten target words and have to select for each target word—the word that comes closest to the meaning of the target from a set of five words.

Preference for consequentialist (and for deontological) judgment

We used two different measures for these constructs. In Studies 1 and 3, participants were presented with a battery of ten trolley-style dilemmas (Bostyn, Sevenhant, & Roets, 2019) and were asked, for each of the two possible options within each dilemma, to what extent they considered that option to be morally appropriate, on a scale from 1 (completely inappropriate) to 5 (completely appropriate). This battery includes a mix of personal and impersonal dilemmas.Footnote 3 Participants’ preference for consequentialist judgment was calculated by averaging their appropriateness ratings of the consequentialist options (αs = .87 and .88). A preference for deontological judgment was calculated similarly (αs = .85 and .89). Deontological and consequentialist reasoning are envisioned as being driven by dissociable and independent mental processes (Conway & Gawronski, 2013; Greene et al., 2001). As such, we did not expect to find an association between cognitive ability and deontological reasoning.

In Study 2, moral preferences were measured through a process dissociation approach developed by Conway and Gawronski (2013). This procedure contrasts participants’ responses on congruent dilemmas with their responses on incongruent dilemmas. Both types of dilemmas have the same structure as traditional trolley-style moral dilemmas, but on incongruent dilemmas (similar to traditional trolley-style dilemmas), each moral preference is associated with a different response (e.g., “Torture someone to stop a bomb from exploding”), whereas on congruent dilemmas, participants’ preferences for consequentialist or deontological judgment suggest the same response, because the sacrificial harm does not outweigh the benefit that would be gained (e.g., “Torture someone to stop them from vandalizing a bus stop?”). Participants were confronted with 20 dilemmas, ten of each kind, and were asked to report, in a binary fashion (yes/no), whether the suggested sacrificial harm was morally appropriate. Each moral preference was then calculated through a set of equations (Conway & Gawronski, 2013). Some of the original dilemmas from Conway and Gawronski were interchanged with alternatives that were more culturally appropriate for our sample (see Bostyn, Roets, & Van Hiel, 2016). All dilemmas used in all studies were framed from a first-person perspective and are available at https://osf.io/txvjb/.

Results

The data and statistical code are available at https://osf.io/z7uxe/. In each study, we correlated participants’ preferences for consequentialist or deontological moral judgment with their cognitive ability. We then conducted a random-effect meta-analysis with a Paule–Mandel estimator using the metafor package in R (Viechtbauer, 2010). Figure 1 displays the results of each study. Interestingly, we uncovered no association between cognitive ability and the participants’ propensity for consequentialist judgment, rmeta = – .02, pmeta = .415. A large amount of heterogeneity was present, I2 = 71%, 95% CI = 0%, 99%, τ2 = .10. However, given the small number of studies included in this meta-analysis, we caution against interpretation of these heterogeneity estimates.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Correlations of intelligence with preference for consequentialist moral judgment.

To quantify the strength of the evidence in favor of a null effect as compared to the expected positive association, we calculated a directional meta-analytical Bayes factor with the metaBMA package in R (Heck, Gronau, & Wagenmakers, 2017), using a model-averaging approach that weights the results of fixed- and random-effects meta-analysis. We used a half-Normal prior (μ = 0, σ = 0.3) for the effect size, and a half-Cauchy prior (scale factor = 0.5) for the between-study variance (the default options in the package). This analysis suggested that, on the basis of the present work, a null association between preference for consequentialist moral judgment and intelligence is 7.2 times more credible than the expected positive association. A prior sensitivity analysis (using 36 different prior combinations, reported in the online supplementary materials) found that BFH0 ranged from 2.73 to 199.5 (available at https://osf.io/wfasb/). The smallest Bayes factors were obtained when using priors that assumed a high likelihood of a null effect, and the largest Bayes factors were obtained when using priors that assumed a large positive effect.

Finally, though it was not the focus of the present studies, we also uncovered no evidence for an association between preference for deontological judgment and cognitive ability, rmeta = .04, pmeta = .133, τ2 = 0.02, I2 = 8.78%, 95% CI = 0%, 98%).

Discussion

The dominant theoretical framework for moral cognition, the dual-process model, states that consequentialist judgment is driven by a deliberative cognitive process rather than through automatic processing. Research on this issue has uncovered a mixed set of findings, with some studies reporting positive effects and others reporting null effects (see above). Importantly, the previous research did not distinguish between the motivational and ability components of deliberate cognition. Investigating whether cognitive ability is related to consequentialist reasoning can inform which specific aspects of deliberative processing (if any) are driving the overall association. Based on previous work, one could have expected a positive association, however across a set of three studies we uncover no evidence for an association (rmeta = – .02).

The present results clarify some aspects of the dual process model for moral cognition. To the extent that previous research has uncovered associations of measures for “deliberate cognition” with increased consequentialist responding, our studies suggest that these associations are likely driven by participants’ cognitive motivation and not by their cognitive ability. Accordingly, these results qualify earlier work about the effect of cognitive load manipulations on moral reasoning (such as Greene et al., 2008), and suggest that these load manipulations sort their effect through inhibiting cognitive motivation rather than through ability reduction.

One could argue that the lack of an association of consequentialist reasoning with intelligence is not surprising, given the limited mathematical complexity of the 1-versus-5 comparison. However, reducing consequentialist choice to a game of “pick the higher number” ignores the maze of conflicting moral norms one has to navigate to make this choice. The complexity of this type of moral cognition does not lie in the math of the cost–benefit analysis. It lies in whether the consequentialist benefit outweighs violating several moral norms. Trolley dilemmas are hard not because the underlying math is hard, but because weighing norms is hard. Additionally, consequentialist decisions require participants to assume responsibility for the dilemma situation. This puts them in social jeopardy, as research has uncovered that consequentialists are seen as cold, unempathic, and less trustworthy (Bostyn & Roets, 2017; Everett, Faber, Savulescu, & Crockett, 2018; Everett, Pizarro, & Crockett, 2016; Uhlmann, Zhu, & Tannenbaum, 2013). Given the social and moral complexities involved, cognitive ability could very well have impacted participants’ decision making.

In any case, this null effect raises the question of how measures of cognitive motivation can be associated with consequentialist decision making in the absence of an effect of ability. How can the motivation to deliberate have an impact when the ability to deliberate does not? One potential answer could be that individuals with a high motivation for deliberative thinking simply take more time to respond to dilemmas. Previous research has suggested that deontological judgment is driven by a strong emotionally aversive reaction to the sacrificial harm suggested in a trolley-style moral dilemma (Greene, 2007). If so, then taking longer to respond might lessen the impact of this emotional reaction. Perhaps the association of motivational measures with consequentialist decision making is not due to increased deliberation per se, but rather due to attenuation of the initial emotional response.

The present studies have some limitations. A first limitation is that our studies investigated moral decision making using hypothetical dilemmas. In all dilemmas, participants were confronted with a limited set of potential actions, and the outcome of each action was predetermined. Although such dilemmas are common in psychological research, they might be too simplistic to measure moral decision making in the context of cognitive ability. Real-life moral decisions are fraught with uncertainty, and in contrast to hypothetical judgments, the decisions made are actually consequential. We cannot preclude the possibility that real-life moral decision making might be more cognitively demanding than hypothetical decision making. Similarly, given that the present studies only investigated moral decision making in the context of sacrificial moral dilemmas, we should be careful not to generalize our conclusions beyond such dilemmas. It is possible that other types of consequentialist moral reasoning (cf. impartial beneficence; Kahane et al., 2018) might be associated with cognitive ability. Finally, we restricted our investigation to the effects of cognitive ability in isolation from any measures of cognitive motivation. One could assume that any effect of cognitive ability would be most pronounced for participants who additionally have a high motivation toward reasoning cognition. Although there is merit to a study including such variables, our samples contained participants who were both high and low in motivation. Even if cognitive ability and motivation interact and, even if the effect of cognitive ability emerges only for those who score high on motivation, we should still have uncovered an attenuated main effect of cognitive ability. Since our meta-analytic estimate was negative, we think it unlikely that this could explain our findings.

In any case, Greene (2014) has argued that societal progress relies on assuming the meta-ethical perspective offered by consequentialist morality. At least from that vantage point, it seems encouraging that people’s ability to take a consequentialist perspective is not hindered by limitations of their cognitive ability.

Open practice statement

The data, statistical code, and materials for all studies are available at https://osf.io/z7uxe/.