Skip to main content

Epilogue: Neoliberalism and the Crisis of Democratic Theory

  • Chapter
In Search of the Liberal Moment
  • 249 Accesses

Abstract

How might we understand the ostensible renaissance of French liberal thought in the 1970s? Even the most cursory glance into modern French history troubles the waters of a supposed “revival”: Condorcet drafted a constitution in 1793; Benjamin Constant prepared the constitution for Napoleon’s 100 days; Adolphe Thiers and François Guizot governed for the better portion of the July Monarchy from 1830–1848; Tocqueville participated in French colonial strategy as well as the constitutional convention of 1848; the Second Empire ended as the “Liberal Empire” in 1870; writing in the 1860s, Prévost-Paradol penned one the most influential texts on the institutional structure of the Third Republic and Édouard Laboulaye presented an early version of the founding amendment of the Third Republic; some five decades later, the “Colloque Lippmann” in the interwar years established an agenda for an entire generation and beyond, while Élie Halévy maintained an intellectual project that nourished Raymond Aron, François Furet, and others.

If we were satisfied with the idea that Tocqueville never departed from an aristocratic conception of liberty, all research would be vain and the conclusion would be neither new nor fecund. Beyond this, we hope to uncover the signs of indeterminacy in his thought, which was confronted with the enigma of democracy.

—Claude Lefort, “De l’égalité à la liberté”1

The ideas of liberals set forth in the first third of the nineteenth century were potent in criticism and in analysis. They released forces that had been held in check. But analysis is not construction, and release of force does not of itself give direction to the force that is set free.

—John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “Si nous nous satisfaisions de l’idée que Tocqueville ne s’est pas départi d’une conception aristocratique de la liberté, la recherche serait vaine et la conclusion, comme d’avance, ni nouvelle ni féconde. Bien davantage nous import-t-il de relever les signes de l’indétermination d’une pensée à l’épreuve de l’énigme de la démocratie.” Originally published in Libre, 3, 1978. Republished in Claude Lefort, Essais sur le politique XIXe–XXe siècles (Paris: Seuil, 1986), 248.

    Google Scholar 

  2. John Dewey, “Liberalism and Social Action,” in The Papers of John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925–1953, Vol. 11, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University, 1987), 625.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bertrand Jouvenel, On Power (New York: Viking Press, 1962 [1945]), 294.

    Google Scholar 

  4. On the reception of Jouvenel’s On Power, see Olivier Dard, Bertrand de Jouvenel (Paris: Perrin, 2008), who notes that the reception was more extensive and enthusiastic in the English-speaking world than in France.

    Google Scholar 

  5. This claim about Aron may only be understood from the perspective of the renewal of a new liberalism or neoliberalism in the interwar period designed to combat the influence of a state socialism. As François Denord suggests, “Lors de la Libération … le libéralisme passe pour une idéologie surannée,” in Dictionnaire historique des patrons français, ed. Jean-Claude Daumas, Alain Chatriot, Danièle Fraboulet, Patrick Fridenson, and Hervé Joly (Paris: Flammarion, 2010), 1025. For the quotation see Michael C. Behrent, “Justifying Capitalism in an Age of Uncertainty: L’Association pour la Liberté Économique et le Progrès Social, 1969–73,” in France since the 1970s, ed. Emile Chabal (London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2015), 178.

    Google Scholar 

  6. This point has been most forcefully made by Michael Scott Christofferson, French Intellectuals Against the Left: The Antitotalitarian Moment of the 1970s (New York: Berghan, 2004). On the specificity of French neoliberalism, its birth in the 1930s and final triumph at the end of the century, see Serge Audier, Le colloque Lippmann. Aux origines du “neo-libéralisme” (Lormont: Le Bord de l’eau, 2012) and François Denord, Néo-libéralisme version française: Histoire d’une idéologie politique (Paris: Demopolis, 2007).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Christophe Prochasson’s biography of Furet suggests that even his regular critiques of the left did not amount to a betrayal of his contribution to a new leftist politics. See Christophe Prochasson, François Furet. Les chemins de la mélancolie (Paris: Stock, 2013), in particular, the conclusion, “Pour penser à gauche,” where he writes: “Voici pourquoi sa pensée politique, si nourrie d’histoire, est en mesure de fournir à la gauche contemporaine les éléments d’une doctrine renouvelée.” For arguments that Furet was clearly on the right, see Michael Scott Christofferson’s chapter in this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Gauchet’s response to the question “Are you a liberal?” highlights precisely this point. “Tout ce que j’ai écrit sur Constant ou Tocqueville,” he stated, “avait pour but de circonscrire l’erreur de perspective qui les a trompés sur le monde dans lequel ils évoluaient.” Marchel Gauchet, La Condition historique (Paris: Stock, 2003), 267.

    Google Scholar 

  9. John Dewey, “Liberalism and Social Action,” in John Dewey, The Later Works, vol. II (1935–1937), ed. Jo Ann Bodyston (Normal: Southern Illinois University, 1987), 1–66, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  10. On Hayek’s Tocqueville as opposed to that of Lefort, see Serge Audier, Tocqueville retrouvé. Genèse et enjeux du renouveau du tocquevillien français (Paris: Vrin/EHESS, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Claude Lefort, “La question de la démocratie,” in Essais sur le politique XIXe–XXe siècles, ed. Claude Lefort (Paris: Seuil, 1986), 21.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Andrew Jainchill and Samuel Moyn, “French Democracy between Totalitarianism and Solidarity: Pierre Rosanvallon and Revisionist Historiography,” Journal of Modern History 76(1) (2004): 107–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. “Il y a donc les ainés du groupe Socialisme ou barbarie, principalement Castoriadis et Lefort, il y a parmi nous des tocquevilliens de droite et des tocquevilliens de gauche, mais nous nous retrouvons autour de ce thème: le totalitarisme comme révélateur de problèmes les plus énigmatique et les plus profonds de la démocratie. Ainsi, le totalitarisme, avec la menace qu’il signifiait encore à cette époque, nous conduit vers une interrogation radicale sur la démocratie.” Pierre Manent, Le regard politique (Paris: Flammarion, 2010), 111.

    Google Scholar 

  14. I define “critical” to capture a moral and political position that recognizes both the flaws and causes for dissatisfaction in “democratic” states while understanding democracy as a historical process with liberatory potential. In this sense, it builds on the critical theory of the Frankfurt School as well as Michel Foucault’s notion of “la critique” at the same time that it embraces the indeterminacy of democratic politics as a potentially liberatory power in our contemporary societies that can never be the property of any one nation or people. However, the indeterminacy that was central to this Paris School of political thinkers, prevented the uncritical adoption even of the notion of critique as Gauchet explicitly pointed out when suggested that in 1971–1973 it was necessary to formulate a “critique of the ‘critique critique’” (Marcel Gauchet, La condition historique, 46). For a different, but influential, perspective on new uses of the notion “critical” in history, see Manu Goswami, Moishe Postone, Andrew Sartori, and William H. Sewell Jr., “Introducing Critical Historical Studies,” Critical Historical Studies 1(1) (Spring 2014): 1–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. See, for example, Louis Dumont, Essais sur l’individualisme (Paris: Seuil, 1983); Pierre Rosanvallon, Le Moment Guizot (Paris: Gallimard, 1985); Marcel Gauchet, La révolution des droits de l’homme (Paris: Gallimard, 1989); Pierre Manent, Histoire intellectuelle du libéralisme: dix leçons (Paris: Calman-Levy, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  16. On the influence of Louis Dumont on certain figures of the 1970s, including Gauchet and others, see Serge Audier, La pensée anti-68 (Paris: La découverte, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Marcel Gauchet, L’Avènement de la démocratie: La revolution moderne, Vol. 1 (2007); La crise du libéralisme, Vol. 2 (2007); A l’épreuve des totalitarismes, 1914–1974, Vol. 3 (2010) (Paris: NRF Gallimard); Pierre Rosanvallon, L’âge de l’autogestion: ou la politique du commandement (Paris: Seuil, 1976); Gauchet, La révolution des droits de l’homme; Pierre Manent, The City of Man (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  18. On Castoriadis and Lefort, see Philippe Gottraux, Socialisme ou Barbarie. Un engagement politique et intellectuel dans la France de l’après-guerre (Lausanne: Payot, 1997) and Nicolas Poirier, ed., Cornelius Castariadis et Claude Lefort: l’expérience démocratique (Lormont: Bord de l’eau, 2015).

    Google Scholar 

  19. It is worth noting that this revolt against totalitarianism and generalized pessimism was stated differently, but was also shared in the late writings of the firstgeneration Frankfurt school. It was stated perhaps most clearly in Friedrich Pollock’s “State Capitalism: Its Possibilities and Limitations,” in The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, ed. Andrew Arato and Eike Gebhardt (New York: Continuum, 1982), 71–94. In this essay, Pollack argues “The totalitarian form of state capitalism is a deadly menace to all values of western civilization. Those who want to maintain these values must fully understand the possibilities and limitations of the aggressor if their resistance is to meet with success. Furthermore, they must be able to show in what way the democratic values can be maintained under the changing conditions” (72). The attempt to revitalize a critical democratic project in response to this pessimism is another ambition that Lefort shared with his contemporaries such as Jurgen Habermas, who also confronted the Marxian legacy across the divide of the crisis of the welfare state. One could argue that the attempt to move beyond this pessimism was a central strut in this Paris School of political thought that participated largely in this liberal moment.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Furet, for example, completely avoids the question in his history of the nineteenth century La Révolution de Turgot à Jules Ferry, 1770–1880 (Paris: Hachette, 1989). Rosanvallon speaks very briefly in Le sacre du citoyen (Paris: Gallimard, 1992), but otherwise, does not treat this issue in his work on the nineteenth-century democracy, like Gauchet and others.

    Google Scholar 

  21. On Tocqueville in Algeria, for example, see Margaret Kohn, “Empire’s Law: Alexis De Tocqueville on Colonialism and the State of Exception,” Canadian Journal of Political Science/Revue canadienne de science politique 41(2) (2008): 255–278; Jennifer Pitts, A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005) and Alexis de Tocqueville, Writings on Empire and Slavery, ed. Jennifer Pitts (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001); Melvin Richter, “Tocqueville on Algeria,” Review of Politics 25 (1963): 362–398; Tzvetan Todorov, De la colonieen Algérie (Brussels: Éditions Complexe, 1988). For the later part of the nineteenth century, see Stephen W. Sawyer, “An American Model for French Liberalism: The State of Exception in Édouard Laboulaye’s Constitutional Thought,” The Journal of Modern History 85 (December 2013): 739–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Pierre Nora, Les Français d’Algérie (Paris: Christian Bourgois, 2012 [1961]).

    Google Scholar 

  23. On Jacques Julliard and decolonization, see Robert Chapuis, “Le combat anticolonialiste à l’UNEF,” Pour une histoire de la deuxième gauche: Hommage à Jacques Julliard (Paris: Bnf, 2008), 25–31.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Pour un capitalisme intelligent (Paris: Grasset, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  25. François Furet, “Les juifs et le commissaire,” Le Nouvel Observateur 17, September 1979, repris dans François Furet, Penser le XXe siècle (Paris: Lafont, 2007), 279.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Daniel Lindenberg, Le rappel à l’ordre: enquête sur les nouveaux réactionnaires (Paris: Seuil, 2002). On the paradoxes of the promotion of democracy since the 1990s, see Florent Guenard, “La promotion de la démocratie: une impasse théorique?” La vie des idées, 2007. http://www.laviedesidees.fr/La-promotion-de-la-democratie-une-impasse-theorique.html

    Google Scholar 

  27. Edward A. Purcell Jr., The Crisis of Democratic Theory: Scientific Naturalism and the Problem of Value (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1973), 269.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Marcel Gauchet and Alain Badiou, Que faire? (Paris: Philo, 2014), 85.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lilla writes, “However great the variety and contention we find within the history of our political thought, the fact remains that coherent antiliberal traditions never developed within it. On the Continent they did. Indeed, the history of Continental political thought since the French Revolution is largely the history of different national species of illiberalism opposed to the fundamental principles listed above.” Mark Lilla, “Introduction: The Legitimacy of the Liberal Age,” in New French Thought: Political Philosophy, ed. Mark Lilla (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004), 4.

    Google Scholar 

  30. François Furet, Jacques Julliard, Pierre Rosanvallon, La République du centre: la fin de l’exception française (Paris: Calman-Lévy, 1988), 58.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Pierre Rosanvallon, La democratie inachevée (Paris: Gallimard, 2000), 390–391.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Pierre Rosanvallon, L’Etat en France, 1789 à nos jours (Paris: Seuil, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Pierre Rosanvallon, Le peuple introuvable (Paris: Gallimard, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  34. Pierre Rosanvallon, Le Modèle politique français. La société civile contre le jacobinisme de 1789 à nos jours (Paris: Seuil, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  35. It is worth noting that one of the most important works on inequality of the last decade, Thomas Piketty’s Le capital au XXI siècle (Paris: Seuil, 2013), also appeared in Rosanvallon’s book series with Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Stephen W. Sawyer Iain Stewart

Copyright information

© 2016 Stephen W. Sawyer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sawyer, S.W. (2016). Epilogue: Neoliberalism and the Crisis of Democratic Theory. In: Sawyer, S.W., Stewart, I. (eds) In Search of the Liberal Moment. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137581266_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137581266_10

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, New York

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-349-72072-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-137-58126-6

  • eBook Packages: HistoryHistory (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics