Skip to main content

Time, Narrative and Causality

  • Chapter
History and Causality
  • 174 Accesses

Abstract

Historians subordinate ‘generalization to narration’, in John Gaddis’s opinion.1 ‘The narrative is the form of representation that most historians use’, he continues, before proceeding to challenge the idea ‘that historians don’t generalize: we do this all the time, but we do it by incorporating our generalizations into our narratives rather than the other way around’.2 Historical practitioners can qualify one detail by another set of details ‘down to and beyond the level of Napoleon’s fleas’, yet they choose not to, making conscious decisions about the adequacy of their simulation or representation.3 The problem is that Gaddis, like many narrative historians, fails to indicate not only when the procedure of qualification should stop (stating how much detail is required), but also where the act of description should start (justifying an object of study). His reply to the objection that ‘there are a potentially infinite number of links in any causal chain’ — for instance, ‘where did each flea come from’ and how did he or she attach himself or herself to the emperor’s underwear, and then to the emperor?’ - consists simply of the assertion that ‘There are some things we can’t know, there are some things we don’t need to know, and fortunately these categories overlap to a considerable degree’.4 From this perspective, generalizations are convenient mechanisms within the narrative form rather than means of answering a question and of explaining why change and continuity occur: ‘We use micro-generalizations to bridge such gaps in the evidence and to move the narrative forward [-] they make it possible to represent reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is a wide variety of definitions of narrative, with some paying little attention, even, to time: for example, M. Bevir and R. A. W. Rhodes, ‘Interpretive Theory’, in D. Marsh and G. Stoker (eds), Theories and Methods in Political Science, 133–4: ‘Although narratives may have a chronological order and contain such elements as setting, character, actions and events, their defining characteristic is that they explain actions using beliefs and preferences’. See also M. Bevir], ‘Historical Explanation, Folk Psychology and Narrative’, Philosophical Explorations, 3 (2000), 152–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. L. Stone, ‘The Revival of Narrative: Reflections on a New Old History’, Past and Present, 85 (1979), 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. F. R. Ankersmit, ‘The Dilemma of Contemporary Anglo-Saxon Philosophy of History’, History and Theory, 25 (1986), 16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., xvi. D. Can, ‘Narrative and the Real World: An Argument for Continuity’, History and Theory, 25 (1986), 117–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. He has been criticized by post-structuralists for emphasizing ‘experience’, as a phenomenologist, rather than language: J. Hillis Miller, ‘But Are Things as We Think They Are?’, Times Literary Supplement, (9 October 1987), 1104–5. Joan Wallach Scott, ‘Comment: Agendas for Radical History’, Radical History Review, 36 (1986), 43

    Google Scholar 

  6. Despite the fact that, in some instances, ‘to say that we build a house is not equivalent to saying that I build a house, and you build a house, and he builds a house’, since ‘not all linguistic uses of we cany this sense of concerted action’: D. Carr, ‘Narrative and the Real World: An Argument for Continuity’, History and Theory, 25 (1986), 127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. D. Carr, ‘Narrative Explanation and Its Malcontents’, History and Theory, 47 (2008), 19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. P. A. Roth, ‘How Narratives Explain’, Social Research, 56 (1989), 470.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid. On the relationship between historical language and reality, see A. C. Danto, ‘Historical Language and Historical Reality’, Review of Metaphysics, 27 (1973), 219–59.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2014 Mark Hewitson

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hewitson, M. (2014). Time, Narrative and Causality. In: History and Causality. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137372406_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137372406_5

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, London

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-349-47611-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-137-37240-6

  • eBook Packages: Palgrave History CollectionHistory (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics