Skip to main content

Recognition, Social Systems and Critical Theory

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory

Part of the book series: Political Philosophy and Public Purpose ((POPHPUPU))

Abstract

This chapter argues that the critical project in social theory can revitalize its critical potential if it aligns with a theory of society and its institutions seen as social systems. The first generation of critical theory repelled the project of normativity as it had been pursued in Hegel’s The Philosophy of Right or in functionalist exponents of classical sociological theory. Yet, the recent turn toward the paradigm of recognition embraces a theory of justice fashioned after the ethical demands of the Hegelian project. This chapter discusses the subsumption of a theory of normative social institutions to the forces of reification and of one-dimensionality in the writings of Horkheimer, Adorno and Marcuse; Habermas’s critical reconstruction of systems theory that salvages the unnoticed normativity of social institutions in modernity and reexamines social systems as value-laden entities; and the project of fortifying the value of freedom in institutional arrangements in the work of Axel Honneth. The chapter concludes with some thoughts on the systemic anomalies that Honneth’s research program for critical theory seems to accommodate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a comprehensive reconstruction of the public sphere that engages systematically with the relevance of sociological explanations of institutions and social systems, see Cohen and Arato (1992).

  2. 2.

    AGIL stands for adaptation (A), goal attainment (G), societal integration (I) and latent pattern maintenance (L). On the level of the social system, they reflect the subsystems of economy (A), of polity (G), of civil society and solidarity (I), and of collective values, which also include trust (L).

  3. 3.

    The pernicious “utopianism” typical of certain strands of socialist thought is succinctly pointed out by Claus Offe (1997: 91, n. 9) and André Gorz (2012: 8).

  4. 4.

    In an uncanny mode Critical Theory still operates within Hegel’s system of logic: the critique of modernity fashioned after Adorno and Horkheimer resembles critique at the level of the doctrine of “being” (i.e. subsuming all facets of a complex reality to the abstract unity of domination), Habermas’s “system”—“life-world” dualism at the level of the logical category of “essence”, (emphasizing the distinction between unity [life-world] and difference [system]), while Honneth’s research program of recognition seems to operate on the level of the doctrine of the concept (i.e. “unity-in-difference” since the “good” is forged within a plural and complex set of differentiated social institutions and social systems). Although schematic, this analogy may prove instructive in disclosing the logical pattern of critique launched by the Frankfurt School.

  5. 5.

    For Adorno (2000: 37) Durkheim’s hypostasized version of the “social” is part of a dualism, the other nonreducible element of which is methodological individualism.

  6. 6.

    Nisbet (1974: 273) thinks that the New Left drew inspiration from Durkheim’s theory of the state in its critique of the bureaucratized Soviet State. I am not in a position to confirm Nisbet’s claim. Marcuse, for instance, in a similar critique does not refer to Durkheim; rather, he resorts to Aristotle, Hegel and Tönnies (sources of Durkheim’s ethical division of labor) to juxtapose to Soviet Marxism a model of a “free and rational organization of social labour” in convergence between ethics and economics (Marcuse 1971: 213). Meštrović (1993: 84–6) for his part attempts a loose affinity between Durkheim’s skeptical provisos against pragmatism and Max Horkheimer’s similar critique.

  7. 7.

    Horkheimer (1972: 192) rescues, momentarily, Durkheim from the empiricist brand of sociology, yet he misses the Kantian dimension of indeterminacy as freedom (Stedman Jones 2001: 107–110) as well as the normatively driven request for a science of society aimed to curb anomie.

  8. 8.

    A sympathetic to the Durkheim–Adorno affinity interpretation by Garde Hagens (2006), reproduced the very irreconcilable elements in their theories and attaches itself to a conservative image of Durkheim’s social theory.

  9. 9.

    For a similar formulation see Durkheim (1974: 38).

  10. 10.

    Interestingly enough, Durkheim’s conception of the organic as a configuration that surpasses its legalistic and contractual entanglements in modern society is raised by the vitalist De Chardin: “We feel that the relation between Society and Social Organism is no longer a matter of symbolism but must be treated in realistic terms. But the question then arises as to how, in this shifting of values, this passage from the legalistic to the organic, we may correctly apply the analogy. How are we to escape from metaphor without falling into the trap of establishing absurd and oversimplified parallels which would make of the human species no more than a kind of composite, living animal? This is the difficulty which modern sociology encounters” (1964: 155–56). Although obviously tethered to irrationalism, such appreciations do expose critical theory’s shortsighted vision of the moral surplus of organic solidarity.

  11. 11.

    Georg Simmel had also refuted the claim that material interests can be decoupled from values: “As the content of the meaning of history, historical materialism has selected material interests—a choice that is, in a certain sense, utterly unidealistic. But historical materialism fails to recognize that even material interests motivate history only as mental values” (Simmel 1977: 200).

  12. 12.

    The distinction, but in a different context, between “system integration” and “social integration” comes from David Lockwood (1964).

  13. 13.

    For a similar strategy against Luhmann from the perspective of civil disobedience, see Frankenberg (1997).

  14. 14.

    The odd absence of sociology is most conspicuous in Horkheimer critical theory of society (1974a, b; 1995).

  15. 15.

    For Luhmann the moral code respect/disrespect (adopted by Honneth) is a form of society’s ethical self-description, yet paradoxical as the code is used simultaneously by both “ego” and “alter”: individuals, groups or collectivities claim “respect” as victims of “disrespect” vis-à-vis an alter (individual or collective). To avoid this moral “war of all against all” ethics becomes a differentiated system (in business, in politics, in the market, in sustainability projects, in journalism among others). This is due to the asymmetrical placement of “ego” and “alter” in differentiated niches that communicate an “amoral coordination of morality” (2012: 149).

  16. 16.

    For systematic affinities between the two, see Gangas (2007).

  17. 17.

    Honneth writes: “Discursive spaces for the reciprocal correction of consumer needs have only emerged where social life-situations have not grown so far apart as to prevent consumers from putting themselves in each other’s position” (2014b: 222). Empirical proof of Honneth’s claim can be found in Wilkinson and Pickett (2009).

  18. 18.

    For a critique of this neo-idealist twist to Critical Theory, see Thompson (2014).

  19. 19.

    For an attempt to reconstruct the category of reification beyond its materialist dent, see Honneth (2008).

  20. 20.

    Habermas (1996) rescues the law as the “third realm” of validity that partakes of both the lifework (justice) and the system (validity of the law). Brunkhorst reactivates the moral ideal of solidarity but pursues its normative reconstruction within the systems theory agenda wrought by Luhmann. Hauke Brunkhorst expounds on Habermas’s mediating function of law (between system and life-world) arguing that: “The social function of law does not, however—as Emile Durkheim had already keenly observed—consist in eliminating the illegal, but rather in generating certainty of expectations through the dependable distinction between legal and illegal, and in increasing opportunities for fighting very many more conflicts with a simultaneously declining willingness to resort to violence. Law makes it possible to live with conflicts instead of dying in them, and permits the expansion of freedom, which stands and falls with the freedom to conflict” (2005: 148 [original emphasis]). Unfortunately, Brunkhorst’s highly interesting argument with its defense of constitutions (as a fusion of system and lifeworld) cannot be taken up further here. His qualified response to Luhmann is roughly this: differentiated systems presuppose variation in order to build internal system complexity and reduce outer complexity. Variation is accomplished by means of productive individuals and their respective social roles. Exclusion of large segments of the population jeopardizes the self-steering capacity for internal complexity, leaving each system in limbo as it can take recourse only to crude binary and less complex distinctions (e.g. educational merit via the pass/failure of tests only). The functionlessness of the system is equivalent to the decline in democracy. For this reasoning see Brunkhorst (2005: 90). In a sense, Luhmann recognizes this problem when he renders democracy a condition for functional differentiation (Luhmann 2004: 304).

  21. 21.

    Sober Marxists like Horkheimer (1978: 233) express their disdain for much of what today is called “radical Left” that abandons all too easily the accomplishments of bourgeois society.

  22. 22.

    For an instructive summary of these two epistemologies see Weber (1975: 66–67).

  23. 23.

    For Horkheimer bourgeois society understands itself through the “disjunctive judgment” (either/or) whereas critical theory unfolds the “existential judgment” (1972: 227), which is similar to Marcuse’s formulations about the a priori values of critical theory. Brunkhorst (1996: 100) sees Foucault and Luhmann as symptoms of what Adorno and Horkheimer (1979: 27) had anticipated and lamented, namely of “the world as a gigantic analytic judgment”.

  24. 24.

    Contrary to what McCarthy (1991: Chap. 6) chides as the overestimated seducement of systems theory, I agree with Kjaer (2006: 77, n. 87) that Luhmann’s concept of “balance” is better suited to alert us to, as well as to explain, the asymmetries between systems, as opposed to Habermas’s imagery of colonization. As Luhmann writes: “In brief, the autonomy of functional systems secured by their own binary codings excluded metaregulation by a moral supercode, and morality itself accepted, indeed remoralized this condition. For now code sabotage becomes a moral problem—for instance, corruption in politics and law or doping in sport or venal love or cheating with data of empirical research. The higher amorality of functional codes was recognized by morality itself; but this also meant renouncing the idea of the moral integration of society” (2013: 281 [original emphasis]).

References

  • Adorno, Theodore. 1976. Introduction. In The positivist dispute in German sociology, ed. Theodore W. Adorno, et al., 1–67. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. “Einleitung zu Emile Durkheim” » Soziologie und Philosophie« In Soziologische Schriften I, 245–279. Frankfurt aM: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Hegel: Three studies. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Introduction to sociology. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. History and freedom: Lectures 1964–1965. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodore, and Max Horkheimer. 1979. Dialectic of enlightenment. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman, Zygmunt. 1976. Towards a critical sociology: An essay on commence and emancipation. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel. 1996. The cultural contradictions of capitalism, 20th Anniversary ed. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boltanski, Luc. 2011. On critique: A sociology of emancipation. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunkhorst, Hauke. 1996. Critical theory and empirical research. In The handbook of critical theory, ed. David M. Rasmussen, 78–118. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Solidarity: From civic friendship to a global legal community. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Jean, and Andrew Arato. 1992. Civil society and political theory. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Berg, Henk. 2013. Unlearning how to hope: Eleven theses in defense of liberal democracy and consumer culture. In The privatization of hope: Ernst Bloch and the future of Utopia, ed. Peter Thompson and Slavoj Žižek, 269–287. Durham/London: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Chardin, Teilhard. 1964. The future of man. London: Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubiel, Helmut. 1987. Theory and politics: Studies in the development of critical theory. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Domination or emancipation? The debate over the heritage of critical theory. In Cultural-political interventions in the unfinished project of enlightenment, ed. Axel Honneth, Thomas McCarthy, Claus Offe, and Albrecht Wellmer, 3–16. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, Émile. 1960. The division of labor in society. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. Sociology and philosophy. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Durkheim on politics and the state, ed. A. Giddens. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elias, Norbert. 1978. What is sociology? New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filloux, Jean-Claude. 1977. Durkheim et le Socialisme. Genève: Droz.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankenberg, Günter. 1997. Disorder is possible: An essay on systems, laws, and disobedience. In Cultural-political interventions in the unfinished project of enlightenment, ed. Axel Honneth, Thomas McCarthy, Claus Offe, and Albrecht Wellmer, 17–37. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gane, Mike. 1992. Institutional socialism and the sociological critique of communism. In The radical sociology of Durkheim and Mauss, ed. Mike Gane, 135–164. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gangas, Spiros. 2007. Social ethics and logic: Rethinking Durkheim through Hegel. Journal of Classical Sociology 7(3): 315–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garde Hagens, Tobias. 2006. Conscience collective or false consciousness? Adorno’s critique of Durkheim’s sociology of morals. Journal of Classical Sociology 6(2): 215–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorz, André. 2012. Capitalism, socialism, ecology. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1976. Legitimation crisis. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. The theory of communicative action, vol. 2: Lifeworld and system: Critique of functionalist reason. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Between facts and norms. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1991. The critique of power: Reflective stages in a critical social theory. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. An interview with Axel Honneth: The role of sociology in the theory of recognition, (interviewed by Anders Petersen and RasmusWillig). European Journal of Social Theory 5(2): 265–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Reification. A new look at an old idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. The pathologies of individual freedom: Hegel’s social theory. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014a. The I in We: Studies in the theory of recognition. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014b. Freedom’s right: The social foundations of democratic life. Cambridge: Polity.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical theory: Selected essays. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974a. Eclipse of reason. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974b. Critique of instrumental reason. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Dawn and decline: Notes 1926–1931 and 1950–1969. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Between philosophy and social science: Selected early writings. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjaer, Poul. 2006. Systems in context. On the outcome of the Habermas/Luhmann-debate. AncillaIuris, 66–77. Available at SSRN: http://ssm.com/abstract=1489908.

  • Laudan, Larry. 1971. Towards a reassessment of Comte’s Méthode positive. Philosophy of Science 38(1): 35–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lechner, Frank J. 1990. Fudamentalism and sociocultural revitalization: On the logic of dedifferentiatiom. In Differentiation theory and social change: Comparative and historical perspectives, ed. Jeffrey C. Alexander and Paul Colomy, 88–118. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, David. 1964. Social integration and system integration. In Explorations in social change, ed. George K. Zollschan and Walter Hirsch, 244–257. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, Niklas. 1988. Familiarity, confidence, trust: Problems and alternatives. In Trust: Making and breaking of corporate relations, ed. Diego Gambetta, 94–107. Oxford: Wiley-Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994a. Politicians, honesty and the higher amorality of politics. Theory, Culture and Society 11: 25–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994b. “What is the case?” and “What lies behind it?” Two sociologies and the theory of society. Sociological Theory 12(2): 126–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Globalization or world society: How to conceive of modern society? International Review of Sociology/Revue Internationale de Sociologie 7(1): 67–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Law as a social system. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Theory of society, vol. 1. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Theory of society, vol. 2. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1968a. One dimensional man. London: Sphere Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1968b. Negations. Essays in critical theory. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1971. Soviet Marxism: A critical analysis. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Reason and revolution. Hegel and the rise of social theory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. The sociological method and the problem of truth. In Knowledge and politics. The sociology of knowledge dispute, ed. Vokler Meja and Nico Stehr, 129–139. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. A revolution in values. In Towards a critical theory of society: Collected papers of Herbert Marcuse, vol. 2, ed. Douglas Kellner. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, Thomas A. 1991. Ideals and illusions: On reconstruction and deconstruction in contemporary critical theory. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meštrović, Stjepan. 1993. Emile Durkheim and the reformation of sociology. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbet, Robert. 1974. The sociology of Emile Durkheim. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Offe, Claus. 1997. Bindings, shackles, brakes: On self-limitation strategies. In Cultural-political interventions in the unfinished project of enlightenment, ed. Axel Honneth, Thomas McCarthy, Claus Offe, and Albrecht Wellmer, 63–94. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Offe, Claus. 2015. Europe entrapped. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, Talcott. 1969. Politics and social structure. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Talcott Parsons on national socialism (Uta Gerhardt, ed.). New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quante, Michael. 2011. Recognition as the social grammar of species-being in Marx. In Recognition and social ontology, ed. Heikki Ikäheimo and Arto Laitinen, 239–267. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renault, Emmanuel. 2010. Taking on the inheritance of critical theory: Saving Marx by recognition?. In The philosophy of recognition: Historical and contemporary perspectives, ed. Hans-Christoph Schmidt am Busch and Christopher F. Zurn, 241–256. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riedel, Manfred. 1984. Between tradition and revolution: The Hegelian transformation of political philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritter, Joachim. 1982. Hegel and the French revolution: Essays on the philosophy of right. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, Georg. 1977. The problems of the philosophy of history: An epistemological essay. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stedman Jones, Susan. 2001. Durkheim reconsidered. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Michael J. 2014. Axel Honneth and the neo-idealist turn in critical theory. Philosophy and Social Criticism 40(8): 779–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tönnies, Ferdinand. 1993. Community and society. New Brunswick/London: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1975. Roscher and Knies: The logical problems of historical economics. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellmer, Albrecht. 1974. Critical theory of society. New York: The Seabury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1995. The Frankfurt School. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, Richard, and Kate Pickett. 2009. The spirit level: Why equality is better for everyone. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yovel, Yirhmiahu. 1980. Kant and the philosophy of history. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gangas, S. (2017). Recognition, Social Systems and Critical Theory. In: Thompson, M. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory. Political Philosophy and Public Purpose. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-55801-5_25

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics