1 Introduction

Despite enormous advances in the prevention, diagnosis and treatment of human illnesses, severe diseases continue to deprive people of health, well-being and independence. Attempts to find cures for these maladies give rise to legal issues. One of the biggest debates involving biotechnology and the law is the regulation of stem cell research and the patentability of such technology.Footnote 1

Research into human developmental biology has led to the discovery and isolation of human stem cells. These are precursor cells that can give rise to multiple tissue types and include human embryonic stem cells (hESCs), embryonic germ cells (EGCs) and adult stem cells (ASCs). Recently, improved techniques have been developed for the in vitro culture and re-programming of stem cells, providing novel opportunities for understanding human embryology and for developing new applications for induced pluripotent stem cell technologies.Footnote 2 Although it seems to be impossible to precisely foresee the results of this research, some exciting applications are already emerging.Footnote 3 In any event, it is evident that scientists will gain immense new knowledge of the biology of human development that presumably will hold extraordinary potential for therapies and cures.Footnote 4

The fact that human stem cell research may involve the use of cloning techniques, such as somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT), raises legal, but also ethical and religious, questions which concern public policy making, the governance of science and society at large. Potential uses of human stem cells to generate human tissues and organs are also the subject of ongoing public debate. Furthermore, the possible sources, risks and potential of different types of human stem cells are fiercely debated.Footnote 5

One of the most discussed issues is whether biotechnologists should be allowed to produce stem cells from human embryos for research and/or clinical use and/or commercialisation and, eventually, to patent the methods and products resulting from the skilful application of modern stem cell technologies. Despite promising advances in induced pluripotent stem cell (iPSC) technology,Footnote 6 which might make the use of human embryos unnecessary in the future, this new technology still faces many limitations and safety issues, such as the risk of tumorigenesis.Footnote 7 For these and other reasons hESC technology unfortunately still appears to be required until iPSC technology has become more advanced.Footnote 8 Until recently, however, the reality was that the embryo was necessarily sacrificed in the process.Footnote 9 The technological potential to help find new treatments for severe illness and the simultaneous need to manipulate and destroy human fertilised ova (or similar) produce a societal and ethical dilemma between the duty of care and the dignity of life.Footnote 10 Moreover, a wide diversity of views and regulatory approaches coexist within the EU.Footnote 11 From an individual point of view, for example, an empirical study shows that with regard to stem cell research, by a small margin European citizens prioritise their right to health (53 %) over protection of dignity (47 %).Footnote 12 However, various individuals and groups have expressed concerns, ranging from religious institutionsFootnote 13 to anti-abortionist groups, animal rights campaigners, bio-ethicists, scientists, governmental officials, members of parliament, patient advocate groups or organisations like Greenpeace.Footnote 14

Against this complex and multifaceted background, this paper will focus on issues related to the patentability of hESC-related technology with respect to the ordre public and morality provisions embedded in European patent legislation. Brief comparisons will be made with recent US patent eligibility developments in the wake of the US Supreme Court judgment in Myriad.Footnote 15 After describing the most recent case law developments regarding the patentability of human embryonic stem cells from the Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU), the European Patent Office (EPO), Germany and the UK, special attention will be given to the CJEU judgment in C-364/13 International Stem Cell Corporation (ISCO) v. Comptroller General of Patents.Footnote 16

To this end, Sect. 2 of this paper will start out by outlining the applicable legal framework in Europe, while Sect. 3 will describe the most seminal recent case-law developments preceding ISCO. Section 4 will then summarise the procedural history and outcome of the CJEU’s ISCO decision. Open questions and other problematic issues will be discussed in Sect. 5. This will provide the basis for a consideration of practical implications in Sect. 6, and a brief comparison with some recent US developments in Sect. 7. Finally, we will conclude the paper with a few general remarks in Sect. 8.

2 The European Legal Framework

The European controversy concerning the patentability of hESC-related inventions is primarily concerned with Art. 53(a) EPC,Footnote 17 which explicitly excludes certain inventions “the commercial exploitation of which would be contrary to ‘ordre public’ or morality” from patentability,Footnote 18 the EU Directive on the Legal Protection of Biotechnological Inventions (Biotech Directive)Footnote 19 and corresponding national stipulations.Footnote 20

In September 1999, the Administrative Council of the EPO introduced several provisions of the Biotech Directive into the Implementing Regulations of the EPC (EPC Rules).Footnote 21 Although the Biotech Directive was merely addressed at the EU Member States and had no direct authority over the EPO, these rules are now binding on the various divisions of the EPO and the Boards of Appeal. The incorporation of the Biotech Directive into the EPC Rules included provisions relevant to the discussion concerning the patentability of hESCs. Article 5 Biotech Directive (Rule 29 EPC) specifies the circumstances under which elements isolated from the human body can constitute a patentable invention. The primary focus of this analysis, however, is on Art. 6(2) Biotech Directive (Rule 28(d) EPC), which resembles the morality clause in Art. 53(a) EPC and goes even further by defining more specifically which processes and uses of technology should be considered to be contrary to public policy or morality, and thereby non-patentable. The patentability exceptions defined in Art. 6(2) Biotech Directive (Rule 28 EPC) have a specific impact on the patentability of hESC technology and the methods that could be associated with it, since they inter alia comprise processes for cloning human beings, for modifying the germ line’s genetic identity, and, in particular, in Art. 6(2)(c) (Rule 28(c)), uses of human embryos for industrial and commercial purposes.

Since the drafters of the Biotech Directive could not foresee the full implications and opportunities of modern stem cell science, the broad wording of the provision and the lack of definitions in particular raise many questions with regard to the patentability of hESC technology and the definition of the human embryo. Totipotent hESCsFootnote 22 can be understood as a stage in the formation and development of the human body and product claims thus fall unequivocally under the patentability prohibition set forth in Art. 5(1) Biotech Directive. However, the questions of patentability raised by pluripotent hESCsFootnote 23 and method claims concerning totipotent hESC uses remained rather unclear.

The situation appears even more complex when taking into account that the member states have introduced differing legislations with regard to the materials and techniques that are allowed in stem cell research, as well as various legal definitions of what constitutes an embryo. Thus, a wide variety of legal frameworks, resting on diverse ethical considerations, can be found within Europe.Footnote 24 Although it is well established that a morality clause cannot exclude an invention from patentability merely because that invention is prohibited by law or regulation, these laws and regulations still have to be considered, in order to define the technologies that are deemed to fall under the morality exclusion. In doing so, the national courts and patent offices would focus on the national legal rules on stem cell research, the EU mandated rules and the international treaties signed by the domestic state. The EPO and the CJEU, however, would have to define a European standard and take this as the basis for their decisions.Footnote 25 In that context it does not seem surprising that the provisions in national patent law and in the EPC which correspond to Arts. 5 and 6 Biotech Directive are equally subject to various interpretations and much debate, which ultimately has to be resolved by case law.

3 Preceding Case Law

The first high profile European case that directly addressed essential questions related to the interpretation of Art. 53(a) EPC (Rule 28(c)) referred to the EPO Enlarged Board of Appeal (EBA) under Art. 112(a) EPC was the WARF case. The patent application referred to primate (including human) embryonic stem cells, which are estimated by the scientific research community to hold potential promise for the treatment of many serious diseases and disabilities.Footnote 26 In November 2008, the EBA considered the above-described European legal framework and the relevant EPC provisions on the non-patentability of inventions using human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes in Europe to reject the patent application.Footnote 27 However, the Board left open the possibility of patenting products and methods using hESCs available in biobanks because these were derived from cell lines. In the aftermath of the WARF decision, the EPO used this loophole to develop a more liberal approach towards patent claims directed to hESCs which were available from certain pre-existing stem cell lines, that is, claims on technical inventions that did not directly require the destruction of an embryo.Footnote 28

This was, of course, good news for patent applicants and patentees. However, things were developing rather differently at the national and EU levels, where questions similar to those addressed by WARF were to be considered by the German Federal Patent Court, the German Federal Supreme CourtFootnote 29 and, ultimately, the CJEU in the Brüstle proceedings. This case concerned a patent granted by the German Patent Office.Footnote 30 The patent basically claimed neuronal precursor cells, a method of their production and their therapeutic use for neuronal disorders. It was subsequently challenged by Greenpeace due to the fact that the claims comprised hESCs. Greenpeace filed for nullity of Brüstle’s patent, asserting that it was against public morality (sittenwidrig) under Sec. 2 of the German Patent Act, which is the German equivalent of Art. 6(2)(c) Biotech Directive. On 5 December 2006, the Federal Patent Court declared major parts of the claims to be invalid insofar as they related to human embryonic stem cells.Footnote 31 While the judgment of the Court had no legal effect on the pending EPO decision and had to be discussed in the light of very specific legal stipulations, such as Germany’s Embryo Protection ActFootnote 32 and the Stem Cell Act,Footnote 33 the Brüstle case nevertheless left room for speculation concerning the potential implications it might have for the interpretation of the fundamental questions raised by the then still ongoing WARF proceedings at the EPO. Such considerations became even more interesting after the Federal Patent Court decision was appealed to the Federal Supreme Court. The Supreme Court recognised that any decision in the case would require further clarification by the CJEU. It therefore stayed the proceedings and referred a number of questions to the CJEU under the preliminary ruling procedure in Art. 267 TFEU.Footnote 34

In October 2011, the CJEU rendered its judgment in Brüstle,Footnote 35 broadly interpreting the patent exclusion of human embryos for commercial or industrial purposes, and adopting a “full history” approach.Footnote 36 The Court held inter alia that Art. 6(2)(c) Biotech Directive excluded from patentability an invention where the technical teaching of the patent application requires the prior destruction of human embryos or their use as base material, whenever such destruction takes place and even if the claims’ description does not refer to the use of human embryos.Footnote 37 Moreover, the CJEU widely defined the notion of human embryo as: “[A]ny human ovum after fertilization, any non-fertilized human ovum into which the cell nucleus from a mature human cell has been transplanted and any non-fertilized human ovum whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis.”Footnote 38

The Court thus explicitly included non-fertilised ova after somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT)Footnote 39 and – most importantly for this case – parthenotes, which are created by the artificial activation of an oocyte by a variety of chemical and electrical techniques so that they are capable of further cell division in the absence of sperm fertilisation.

In the wake of the CJEU’s Brüstle judgment, scientists in the field of hESC research became concerned about the wider impact of this controversial decision and the full-history approach, as it prohibits hESC patents that use publicly available stem cell lines, which thus would not imply de-novo destruction of embryos.Footnote 40 The judgment was also fiercely debated and criticised in the academic literature, inter alia for artificially creating a fictional consensus in Europe on the definition of human embryos, and on the morality of stem cell research and regulation, and also for not complying with international standards and treaties, such as the TRIPS Agreement.Footnote 41

However, when the German Federal Supreme Court ultimately applied the CJEU’s preliminary ruling in Brüstle and delivered a final decision,Footnote 42 it became apparent that, surprisingly, the Court did not apply the prior CJEU considerations in a narrow and strict manner. Interpreting the CJEU’s explanations in a rather patent-friendly way, the Federal Supreme Court decided to only partially revoke Oliver Brüstle’s patent. It determined that the patenting of the process is only excluded, according to Sec. 2(1) No. 3 Patent Act, if the process includes the prior destruction of embryos, or their use as source material. Patenting is possible, however, where the relevant stem cells are extracted without necessitating the destruction of embryos. Also, the use of cell lines extracted from embryos that are no longer able to develop does not – according to the Federal Supreme Court – result in exclusion from patentability. The negotiated patent claim was, in this respect, limited, and the appeal was only partially rejected. Amending this decision with a disclaimer, the Court also appeared to be willing to consider later (post-filing) technological developments that allowed the extraction of stem cells (e.g. through optimised blastomere separation) without necessarily destroying the embryo in the process. While the final Supreme Court decision indicated that a reasonable and relatively broad patent protection of human stem cell-related technology is still possible in Germany, it also raised crucial questions about a potential “misinterpretation” of the CJEU’s preliminary ruling and a potential conflict with the present approach taken at the EPO.

In that context it should be noted that the EPO took a rather different path, which partially confirmed the aforementioned concerns of patentees and scientists. Shortly after the CJEU’s judgment – although not formally bound by it – the EPO decided to directly incorporate the CJEU’s Brüstle principles and the full-history approach into its guidelines for examination.Footnote 43 Accordingly, the EPO began to reject patent claims that would arguably have been accepted under the EPO’s previous more pragmatic approach resulting from the EBA decision in WARF.Footnote 44 On 4 February 2014, this new restrictive approach was rigorously applied in the Technion decision, in which the TBA departed from the EBA’s prior decision in the WARF case, deciding instead to align itself with the CJEU’s decision in Brüstle.Footnote 45 Following a strict interpretation of Art. 53(a) EPC (Rule 28(c)) and the new EPO Guidelines, the TBA decided to exclude from patentability “inventions which make use of HES cells obtained by de-novo destruction of human embryos or of publicly available HES cell lines which were initially derived by a process resulting in the destruction of the human embryo”.Footnote 46 Thereby, the TBA clearly brought the patentability of hESCs at the EPO more into line with the CJEU’s decision in Brüstle. However, it appears less clear how far such a strict interpretation comports with the more permissible approach applied by the German Federal Supreme Court in its 2012 decision in Brüstle. Meanwhile, the UK courts were also struggling with the precise scope and implications of the CJEU’s findings in Brüstle, resulting in a new referral to the CJEU seeking clarification of whether the CJEU ruling in Brüstle applies without distinction to unfertilised human ova stimulated by parthenogenesis. This is an interesting question, since such ova may develop into pluripotent cells that – in the absence of further genetic manipulation – are not capable of developing beyond the blastocyst stage. National courts were obviously confused about the full implications of the CJEU’s Brüstle judgment in the light of these scientific facts. This provided the basis for the second stem cell judgment of the CJEU in C-364/13, International Stem Cell Corporation, which will be described in more detail in the next section.

4 The CJEU in C-364/13 International Stem Cell Corporation

In the following, we will outline the facts and procedural history, and summarise the main arguments and outcome of this case.Footnote 47

4.1 Facts of the Case

The UK Intellectual Property Office (UKIPO) rejected two national patent applications assigned to International Stem Cell Corporation (ISCO), relating to research of a stem cell technology called parthenogenesis.Footnote 48 Objections were raised by the UKIPO on the grounds that the inventions were excluded from patentability due to their constituting uses of human embryos under para. 3(d) of Schedule A of the Patents Act 1977 – the rule that implements Art. 6(2)(c) Biotech Directive.Footnote 49 The applicant argued that the CJEU Brüstle decision should not apply, because the claimed inventions related to parthenogenetically activated oocytes, which are incapable of initiating the process of development of a human being, due to the phenomenon of genomic imprinting. ISCO was then confronted with research suggesting that such obstacles could be overcome by genetic engineering. As a result, an amendment to the claims was submitted, introducing the word “pluripotent” before “human stem cell line” and referring to a lack of paternal imprinting, thereby excluding any such method of genetic manipulation.Footnote 50 The patent applicant arguments were not found completely persuasive, and thus ISCO appealed to the High Court of Justice of England and Wales, Chancery Division (the Patents Court).Footnote 51

4.2 The Referral

During the proceedings, scientific evidence emerged distinguishing parthenotes from fertilised ova and differentiating the factual findings from those presented in Brüstle. The Patents Court relied on technical evidence contained in the expert reports and exhibits referred to in the appealed decision, evidence presented in the German Supreme Court Brüstle case,Footnote 52 and also the findings of the UKIPO. It was accepted by all parties that parthenogenesis refers to a process of activation of an oocyte, in the absence of sperm, conducted through a variety of chemical and electrical techniques. The resultant oocyte or parthenote is capable of division and further development into a blastocyst-like structure. However, without further genetic manipulation, parthenotes are unable to develop to term, due to lacking paternal DNA, which is necessary for the development of extra-embryonic tissue. Unlike fertilised ova and their early-stage descendent cells, parthenogenesis-activated oocyte cells are merely pluripotent and never totipotent. The evidence examined pointed out that, so far, human parthenotes have only been able to develop to the blastocyst stage (around 5 days).Footnote 53

The legal debate revolved around whether biological analogy between a parthenogenetically derived structure and the blastocyst stage of normal embryonic development justified legal analogy, having in consideration that parthenotes had been expressly declared to be non-patentable human embryos.Footnote 54 The Comptroller argued that the test set in Brüstle could be interpreted as being concerned more with the commencement of the process of fertilisation than its outcome, but conceded that Brüstle could also be interpreted as requiring such a process to be capable of leading to a viable human being.Footnote 55 ISCO submitted that a narrow understanding of Brüstle should prevail.Footnote 56

The Patents Court pointed out that the factual matrix in the case differed from the facts in Brüstle, suggesting that the CJEU may have relied on inaccurate or incomplete scientific submissions.Footnote 57 Therefore the following question was referred to the CJEU: “Are unfertilised human ova whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis, and which, in contrast to fertilised ova, contain only pluripotent cells and are incapable of developing into human beings, included in the term ‘human embryos’ in Article 6(2)(c) of Directive 98/44/EC on the Legal Protection of Biotechnological Inventions?”.Footnote 58

4.3 Opinion of Advocate-General Cruz Villalón

The Advocate-General (AG) reasoned that while the wording in Brüstle, interpreted literally, includes parthenotes in the definition of “human embryos”, the operative part of the judgment should be interpreted in the light of the grounds for such a decision.Footnote 59 The criterion used by the CJEU to include an organism in the definition of a human embryo was whether such an organism has the capability of commencing the process of development of a human being, and is thus functionally equivalent to an embryo.Footnote 60 The expression “capable of commencing the process of development of a human being” should therefore be understood as an organism possessing the inherent capability of developing into a human being.Footnote 61 Furthermore, the mere possibility of further genetic manipulation of parthenotes does not change their character before such manipulation.Footnote 62 The AG suggested the following answer to the referred question: “Unfertilised human ova whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis are not included in the term ‘human embryos’ … as long as they are not capable of developing into a human being and have not been genetically manipulated to acquire such a capacity.”Footnote 63

4.4 The Decision of the CJEU

The CJEU ruled that Art. 6(2)(c) Biotech Directive must be interpreted in the sense that an unfertilised human ovum whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis does not constitute a “human embryo” under the proviso that “it does not, in itself, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being”. The decision of whether such a condition was fulfilled was left to the national courts. However, the CJEU established a criterion for such evaluation: “current scientific knowledge”.Footnote 64 Pursuant to this reasoning, parthenotes should not be excluded from patentability provided that, in the light of current scientific knowledge, these are not considered to be capable of developing into a human being and are therefore not considered to be human embryos under the Biotech Directive. In its reasoning, the CJEU began by confirming the court’s decision in Brüstle, and re-stating that human embryo, insofar as the interpretation of the Biotech Directive is concerned, is an autonomous EU law concept to be interpreted uniformly, and that such a concept must be construed in a wide sense.Footnote 65 Concerning the specific interpretation of Brüstle it was observed that the statement that any human ovum must, as soon as it is fertilised, be regarded as an embryo, since fertilisation implies the beginning of the process of the development of a human being,Footnote 66 must be interpreted according to the specification in the subsequent paragraph concerning non-fertilised ova. Clarifying that, it was also stated that non-fertilised ova would only be considered to be human embryos if found “capable of commencing the process of development of a human being just as an embryo created by fertilisation of an ovum can do”.Footnote 67 This critical and controversial expression was interpreted following the opinion of the AG,Footnote 68 which had proposed applying a test of “inherent capacity”.Footnote 69 The CJEU concluded that as far as non-fertilised ova are concerned “the mere fact that an organism commences the process of development is not sufficient for it to be regarded as a ‘human embryo’”Footnote 70 As for the reason why in Brüstle parthenotes were considered human embryos, the CJEU acknowledged that it had based its findings on submitted written observations which considered these to be capable of full development. It was left to the national courts to decide, in accordance with available scientific knowledge, whether an organism is inherently capable of developing into a human being.Footnote 71

5 Discussion: Out of the Smog into the Fog?

The CJEU’s decision to allow the patentability of certain parthenotes and parthenote-related technology, as we will argue below, may open up new venues for the patentability of hESC research and might thus be welcomed by potential patent applicants, irrespective of the practical relevance of patent applications directed to parthenotes in current patent practice. However, when read in conjunction with Brüstle a number of questions remain open for debate.

5.1 Elusive Definitions of “Human Being” and “Human Embryo”

A first controversial issue is the need to rely on a patent law-mandated definition of what constitutes a human being and a human embryo. Previously, in Brüstle, the term “human embryo” was defined as any human ovum as soon as it was fertilised (and its equivalents). The human embryo was automatically considered a stage of human development. In ISCO, this definition has now been complemented with the added criteria that it should, “in itself, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being”.Footnote 72 Consequently, this creates a reasoning that is still unclear and likely to support different interpretations.

The legal argument employed to exclude hESCs from patentability is vested in the legal text of the Biotech Directive in two legal mechanisms, corresponding to different rationales: (1) subject-matter exclusion of the human body at any stage of development due to its occurring naturally and lacking technical characterFootnote 73; and (2) exception from patentability for ethical reasons precluding the patentability of uses of human embryos.Footnote 74 Although subject-matter exclusions and exceptions follow different rationales and should not be confused, these are interconnected. Stages of human development are products of nature and not patentable due to lack of technicality. Furthermore, private entitlements over the human body are considered ethically inadmissible, as they conflict with basic human rights such as dignity and autonomy. The recitals of the Biotech Directive indicate that this piece of legislation was grounded mostly in ethical considerations and intended to prevent the patentability of a human being, at any stage of development, regardless of whether it may be considered a product of nature (discovery) and thus as such non-patentable subject-matter, or a patentable technical creation (invention) that is denied patentability for being the object of an exception to patentability. Article 5(1) Biotech Directive is generally understood as a subject-matter exclusion norm. However, the motivation for its statutory inclusion in the Biotech Directive as a specific example of non-patentable subject-matter is ethical, as the recitals and historic elements clearly indicate (i.e. recital 16).Therefore, arguably, the subject-matter exclusion can also be said to be indirectly linked to ethical considerations. Such connection may help understand why, under US patent law, the issue has been discussed as a matter of patent eligibility (see Sect. 7).

Totipotent stem cells, per se, cannot be patented due to their being considered a stage of human development and thus not an invention.Footnote 75 Furthermore, uses of totipotent stem cells are also barred from patentability due to considerations of respect for human dignity (protection of life)Footnote 76 and autonomy (exploitation, commodification and objectifications of the human body).Footnote 77 In Brüstle the AG considered totipotent cells to be the first stage of the human bodyFootnote 78 and thus an embryo, regardless of the means by which it was obtained.Footnote 79 The CJEU followed a different approach, declaring that whether stem cells themselves are to be considered a human embryo depends on whether these are “capable of commencing the process of development of a human being”, a task left to national courts to ascertain,Footnote 80 and that any human ova after fertilisation (or its equivalents) are considered themselves to constitute a human embryo.Footnote 81

The patentability status of pluripotent cells has been even more unclear. In this case, too, both the subject-matter exclusion and the morality-based exception have to be factored into the analysis. Regarding the subject-matter exclusion, it is relevant to determine what constitutes “the human body, at the various stages of its formation and development”.Footnote 82 In respect of the morality-based exception, it is furthermore relevant to determine whether an invention includes the use of a human embryo for industrial or commercial purposes.Footnote 83 Pursuant to the ruling in Brüstle, inventions involving pluripotent stem cells may be excluded from patentability if their retrieval or the technical teaching of the invention requires the use of an embryo for commercial or industrial purposes. If embryos are destroyed in order to establish stem cell lines, arguably at a previous moment, this would imply the use of embryos, even when the method for obtaining the stem cell lines is not part of the invention as claimed, nor mentioned in the claims.Footnote 84

Clearly, the construction of the Biotech Directive was anchored in the protection of human dignity and the integrity of the person.Footnote 85 However, the CJEU has refrained from referring to both law and jurisprudence concerning the scope of application of such principles. By considering human embryo for patent law purposes as an autonomous concept of EU law, the CJEU did more than what it arguably intended – to establish its jurisdiction. It also created a situation of legislative conflict between competing legal and regulatory definitions or understandings of the human embryo and its legal and moral status, largely because matters of health law and criminal and civil rules concerning the beginning and end of life are not subject to harmonisation at EU level.Footnote 86

On a first reading, the ISCO ruling introduces some clarification and reduces the scope of the doctrine set in Brüstle. However, both these expressions – “inherent capacity of developing” and “human being” – are legally ambiguous. The ISCO requirement of inherent capacity could either be interpreted broadly – in the sense of without need for any further technical steps or technical intervention – or narrowly, as meaning without further need for a qualified intervention, such a genetic manipulation.

In the first case, the mere necessity of implantation in a human womb would imply the need for further technical intervention and the logical conclusion that such an organism is a non-viable entity and thus not an embryo. As far as we know, under the current state of scientific research it is not possible for a fertilised ovum to survive and continue to develop without further human intervention past the blastocyst phase. The embryo will, at least, need to be implanted in a human uterus at some stage. Even if further techniques allowed for in vitro full-term development, such would necessarily consist of further technical intervention in a broad sense, placing the organism outside the scope of the patent exception.

In the second case, an organism would still be considered an embryo, provided that its cells were totipotent. The need to employ assisted reproduction techniques for full-term development would not disqualify the organism from being considered a human embryo. It is possible to establish a parallel with the issue of determining when a process is essentially biological, for the purposes of determining the scope of Art. 53(b) EPC. While the CJEU has not interpreted Art. 4(1)(b) Biotech Directive, the EBA has considered that the mere need for human intervention is not sufficient criterion for a process not to be considered as “essentially biological”.Footnote 87 It has also determined that an additional technical step that introduces or modifies a trait in the genome qualifies the process as non-essentially biological.Footnote 88 Thus, analogic reasoning would suggest that the EPO would take the second approach – not all types of human interventions would suffice to prove that an organism does not, in itself, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being. On the other hand, firstly the EBA has previously departed from a uniform application of the three exceptions in Art. 53 EPC, on the grounds that each exception corresponds to different policy concerns.Footnote 89 Secondly, it is not a given either that the CJEU would follow similar reasoning, since the EU court could have chosen to construct the answer to the referral by resorting to the type of stem cell criterion – that is, whether the cells are or are not totipotent – as implied by the referred question. The option to depart from such solution and instead resort to the concept of human being could logically be read as intentional. Finally, given all of the above, it is difficult to predict which of these solutions (if any) will be adopted by the EPO, national patent offices and courts. It is not completely unrealistic to expect either hybrid solutions or a scenario of case-by-case approaches concerning different stem cell sources and techniques.

Relying on a patent law-specific notion of human being, even if indirectly, constitutes a weak point of the CJEU construction of Art. 6(1)(c) Biotech Directive, opening it to accusations of creating a non-falsifiable circular argument.Footnote 90 On the one hand, the CJEU jurisprudence appears to imply that a fertilised ovum is to be considered a mere stage of human development.Footnote 91 However, as will be mentioned below, by grounding the exception on human dignity, the CJEU implicitly denies any differentiation (for patent law purposes) extending the concept of human being to fertilised ova. Simultaneously, a fertilised ovum will only be an embryo provided that it has the inherent capacity of developing into a human being. The CJEU, perhaps wisely, deferred the opportunity to issue further guidance, leaving the subject for national authorities and thus indirectly declining competence to adjudicate in such a matter. It remains to be seen how national courts and the EPO will ultimately apply the present ruling.

5.2 Parthenotes as Non-Viable Organisms

ISCO introduced a qualifying criterion that arguably resembles a test of viability of life, raising further legal and ethical considerations. By using the criterion of inherent capacity of developing into a human being, the ruling leads to the logical conclusion that any embryo – or organism – that is somehow impaired, inviable, or unable to survive beyond a certain stage of development, is not a human being, nor a stage of human development for patenting purposes. Although it makes sense to distinguish parthenotes from the concept of embryo adopted in Brüstle, the adopted criterion in ISCO raises the question of whether certain disabilities or impairments, whether accidental or engineered, may disqualify an organism from such qualification. The main issue is the inclusion of the qualitative “human being”, arguably purposely, as part of the test to determine whether an organism can be considered to be an embryo.

In Brüstle the CJEU opted for assuming jurisdiction over the uniform interpretation of the concept of human embryo as far as the Biotech Directive is concerned. This already debatable option was accompanied by a decision to define embryo in its broadest possible sense.Footnote 92 However, the concept of human being is not defined in either the Biotech Directive or in international law. In fact, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) has reiterated that determining the concept of human being for the purposes of evaluating the scope of protection conferred under the right to life – Art. 2 Council of Europe Convention for the protection of Human Rights and Fundamental freedoms (ECHR) – lies within the margin of appreciation which each state enjoys.Footnote 93 The EU has not acceded to the ECHR and is unlikely to do so in the immediate future.Footnote 94 Thus, unlike all of its member states, the EU cannot be considered to fall under the scrutiny of the ECtHR. However, the CJEU is not prevented from finding the arguments of the ECtHR persuasive. On the contrary, this may be advisable and sustainable due to both substantive and formal considerations. On the one hand, there is merit in the ECHR reasoning. On the other, it would be reasonable for the CJEU to take such jurisprudence into consideration in the light of a future accession of the EU to the convention and considering that all EU member states are bound by such decisions.

While intending to protect the value of life and human dignity, ISCO may indirectly result in the opposite, entering into conflict with the ethical and legal status of the embryo, foetus and unborn person in Europe. The unborn human organism lacks biological autonomy, being up to a certain stage of development incapable of surviving by itself, and being intrinsically and reciprocally connected with a woman. For this reason, in most European jurisdictions, under specific circumstances, which vary, the law allows the voluntary interruption of the gestational process and is especially permissive in cases of severe malformations. However, an impaired life can never be considered a non-life, or non-human, as opposed to a healthy one, pursuant to the principles of dignity,Footnote 95 equalityFootnote 96 and non-discrimination.Footnote 97 In this sense, it is particularly relevant to consider the prohibition of eugenics practices, a ban that is consecrated as a fundamental principle of EU law.Footnote 98 Article 11 Oviedo Convention also prohibits discrimination based on genetic heritage,Footnote 99 given that it is also possible to argue that the provision precludes discrimination based on genetic identity even in the case of induced genetic modifications such as would be the case for organisms purposely created with some form of genetic impairment by technological means.Footnote 100

If Brüstle was accused of inducing a lack of formal and substantive coherence in Europe between a more permissible regulatory framework and research funding and the strict interpretation of the patentability exception,Footnote 101 the present ISCO decision, while having positive aspects, has not improved matters in this specific regard. The adopted legal construction does not result in a more coherent legal solution, leads to uncertainty and maintains the potential to foster further litigation.

5.3 Parthenotes and Human Ova Subjected to Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer

Another major issue that remains unsettled is whether the differences between parthenotes and human ova that have been subjected to SCNT are sufficient to justify different legal treatment, or whether, on the contrary, the doctrine set in Brüstle concerning ova subjected to SCNT has now implicitly been revoked and/or needs to be re-visited.

In Brüstle the court ruled that any fertilised ovum is a human embryo, and that such classification must also apply to a non-fertilised human ovum subjected to SCNT and a human ovum stimulated by parthenogenesis. The argument used is one of functional equivalence: although those organisms have, strictly speaking, not “been the object of fertilisation”, they are “capable of commencing the process of development of a human being”, just like a fertilised ovum.Footnote 102 In ISCO it was stated that a parthenote is not a human embryo if “it does not, in itself, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being”. This opens the question of whether the test developed in Brüstle (fertilised ova and equivalents) and the test emerging from ISCO (inherent capability) should be considered as two cumulative conditions; or rather understood as two alternative criteria.

ISCO was presented as a clarification of Brüstle, thus it could be argued that ISCO has developed Brüstle by introducing a further cumulative condition, that is, that the finding of a “human embryo” would require: (1) its being a fertilised ovum or equivalent; and (2) its being inherently capable, by itself, of developing into a human being. In this case, it is a logical deduction to argue that any organism at the blastocyst phase (fertilised ovum or equivalent), that inherently or by itself is incapable of further development, is excluded from the concept of embryo. This understanding, which follows a line of reasoning similar to that of the German Federal Supreme Court, would have broader consequences, since it would imply generalising a more permissible approach in Europe. In the German Brüstle decision,Footnote 103 the use of cell lines extracted from embryos that are no longer capable of developing was considered to lie outside the scope of the patentability exception.Footnote 104

Another possible reading is to understand these decisions as setting two alternative tests, the first determining whether the organism is a fertilised ovum (naturally occurring or resulting from in vitro fertilisation). These organisms are by default human embryos, since in Brüstle no bottom limit or moral differentiation has been established depending on the stage of development. The second test, concerning organisms that cannot be considered fertilised ova, would be one of establishing analogy through functional equivalence, that is, inherent capability of development into a human being. In this case, in practice it could be considered that these are two separate alternative tests to be applied to different organisms, resulting from different fertilisation techniques. Under this reading, the second criterion could no longer be applied to a fertilised ovum, even if it does not, “in itself, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being”. This means that the ISCO criteria would not be applicable to the so-called inviable embryos, limiting the scope of the decision to parthenotes and, eventually, human ova subjected to somatic cell nuclear transfer.

In both cases, the concrete legal and factual arguments that might justify differentiation or equal treatment remain undetermined. This might include debating whether functional equivalence is the optimal criterion for establishing similar ethical significance and legal analogy. Scientific evidence will have to be analysed by courts, however arguable it is that, in the light of the ISCO criteria, no major differences can be found between partenothes and human ova subjected to cell nuclear transfer.

It is unlikely that the CJEU intended to allow a broad reading that would disqualify from the exception any organism, including fertilised ova, that, by itself, at the time of use is incapable of further development, such as inviable embryos.Footnote 105 However, the opposite can also be reasonably argued, since the decision of the German Federal Supreme Court in Brüstle was known to the court. Ultimately, the fact that the EU court did not further elaborate on the matter leaves the question open.

5.4 Selection and Use of Legal Sources

The referred question offered an opportunity to re-think the contested jurisprudence set in Brüstle, but the CJEU skilfully avoided re-opening the debate by treating the issues raised as matters of factual determination. The key issue remains: there are biological, ethical and legal differences between a blastocyst, an embryo, a foetus and a person/human being. These differences are generally accepted, both at European and national level. Furthermore, the use of embryos in research, including their destruction, is considered to be morally justified and legally admissible under the regulatory frameworks of several European countries.Footnote 106

The CJEU in Brüstle, facing the lack of European consensus on the matter, has been criticised for ignoring matters of both fact and law while ruling that any fertilised ovum is an embryo and an embryo is a person.Footnote 107 The decision could be, and has been, criticised for choosing to harmonise legislation interpreting the Biotech Directive in the most patent-restrictive manner that the text allowed, even after acknowledging that “the definition of human embryo is a very sensitive social issue in many Member States, marked by their multiple traditions and value systems”.Footnote 108 Given the legislative history of the Directive,Footnote 109 a most plausive interpretation would have been to consider that the legislature did not further elaborate on the concept of embryo due to the lack of consensus on the matter between different EU member states and the omission was thus intentionally made in order to defer the issue to the national legal orders.Footnote 110

The Biotech Directive must necessarily be interpreted according to the EU Treaty and framed within the context of other derivative legislation and relevant jurisprudence of the EU courts. It has been argued that the CJEU cannot extend the protection of human dignity beyond what is permitted under the Treaty on European Union and that such protection begins at birth.Footnote 111 The Brüstle decision is also at odds with the approach followed in EU legislation enacted after the Biotech Directive, namely the EU Directive on Human Tissue and CellsFootnote 112 and the Regulation on Advanced Therapies.Footnote 113 A default permissive approach was enacted for regulatory purposes, deferring to the member states the task of addressing in national law questions relating to moral and legal constraints on uses of human embryos and stem cells. This supports both a narrower interpretation of the Biotech Directive and the thesis of national jurisdiction concerning morality matters.Footnote 114

The concepts of ordre public and morality that the Biotech Directive elaborates upon are open concepts.Footnote 115 As a matter of interpretative technique, because the resort to open concepts conflicts with legal certainty, and in the interest of systematic coherence, interpretation should necessarily include reference to both higher normative sources, such as the EU Treaties, and regulatory sources that may provide for specific contextual meaning.Footnote 116 The CJEU would be expected to be more sensitive to such matters, being a judicature whose competence is limited firstly in functional terms to ensuring harmonised interpretation of EU law,Footnote 117 and secondly, limited as a matter of formal competences by the EU Treaties and the functions of the Union.Footnote 118 It has been argued that, had the CJEU adverted to the primary legal sources which are specifically mentioned in the Directive, and followed its own jurisprudence regarding the interpretation of fundamental rights, it would have reached a different conclusion.Footnote 119 It has also been mentioned that it is of paramount relevance that the construction of the morality exception is consistent with respect for EU principles, and the diversity of views and national autonomy of member states.Footnote 120 Proportionality is among the most important principles of the EU legal order, serving both the purpose of limiting the EU legal competences, thus creating a mechanism of reconciliation between fundamental values, and that of framing the interpretative task regarding application to specific material facts.Footnote 121 A broad construction of the exception overlooks the nature and functions of the patent right and seems inconsistent with the principle of proportionality.Footnote 122 Also mentioned in the literature is the question of the general scope of exceptions. It has been claimed that the CJEU had previously adopted a principle of narrow interpretation of exceptions to fundamental EU Treaty principles.Footnote 123 Against this, it should be mentioned that the Brüstle case can be read either as the broad interpretation of an exception to the right to intellectual property, or as the broad interpretation of the right to human dignity. Thus, in cases involving conflicting fundamental rights applying by default, a principle of narrow interpretation of exceptions would hardly be a useful interpretative technique.Footnote 124 Instead, emphasis should be given to legislative intent and secondary sources of law, which, as mentioned, would point in the direction of a narrow interpretation.Footnote 125

The interface between IP and human rights is complex.Footnote 126 There are advantages,Footnote 127 but also known dangers of deciding patent law cases in the light of a human rights reasoning.Footnote 128 This is a path that the EPO Boards of Appeal have carefully avoided.Footnote 129 One of the main difficulties is that using a human rights reasoning implies the need to evaluate all connected legal sources. In the current context this entails considering rules and jurisprudence concerning the definition and legal status of the human embryo and human tissues as far as the right to life and the dignity of the person are concerned. An overview of the EU and European legal framework concerning the limits of human life and the protection of the right to life vis-à-vis the right to health points in the direction of a lack of European consensus and strengthens the argument for national jurisdiction.

The argument that lack of harmonisation of the concept of embryo and the scope of protection conferred to embryos in relation to patentability would prejudice the realisation of the internal marketFootnote 130 is not very persuasive. This is, first, because Art. 6(1) Biotech Directive leaves open the possibility for the member states to consider whether an invention is in breach of ordre public or morality even outside the specific examples provided in Art. 6(2) Biotech Directive; and, second, due to the nature of patent rights and the lack of a truly uniform EU patent right.Footnote 131 Patent rights remain national administrative concessions that presuppose an act of will – the patent application. Applicants are furthermore not obliged to apply for a patent right in all EU member states. There will always be situations where an invention is patented in some EU member states and in the public domain in others, given that freedom of movement issues are generally addressed under the doctrine of exhaustion.

5.5 The CJEU and Ethical Expertise

The Biotech Directive was enacted with the objective of introducing a balance between competing policy issues: (1) preserving human dignity, the right to life and human autonomy, in the sense of non-commercialisation of parts of the human body; and (2) maintaining an adequate level of incentives to ensure that the research and development of life-saving technologies remains attractive to private investors.Footnote 132 However, consensus between the relative values to be attributed to each of these policy objectives was and is far from being achieved, both at political and cultural level. Evidence that the legislature understood the social and political sensitivity of the subject can be found in Art. 7 Biotech Directive, which determines that provisions of the Directive entailing an element of ethical evaluation of biotechnology inventions should be interpreted according to the decisions of the Commission’s European Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies (EGE).Footnote 133

The EGE has examined ethical issues related to stem cell patenting, expressing the opinion that no ethical reason could be found for a complete ban on the patenting of inventions relating to stem cells or stem cell lines, since this would be contrary both to the public interest – the right to health – and to the EU’s encouragement of research and scientific progress – as expressed in the recitals of the Biotech Directive. Furthermore, the EGE distinguishes between non-modified hESCs, which should not be patentable, and patentable modified hESCs. The EGE does not take a position on what is to be considered an embryo and, most importantly, does not consider embryo destruction to be a determinant ethical consideration.Footnote 134

Even though the merits of the EGE’s reasoning can be questioned, it is apparent that the legislature expressly attributed some legal interpretative value to these opinions. In contrast, the CJEU has ignored the EGE and avoided references to Art. 7 Biotech Directive. Arguably, the CJEU has implicitly made a restrictive interpretation of the mandate conferred on the EGE and the value of its opinions as a secondary source of law, and opted for its own evaluation, framed by the experience of the Court and the submissions of the parties.Footnote 135 Independently of how the role and mandate of the EGE are understood, this case demonstrates that it is important to debate the limits of jurisdictional adjudication concerning matters that transcend the borders of the law and enter the fields of both science and ethics, and whether the CJEU has crossed those boundaries. It has been suggested that the use of ethical expertise, or a pre-exam by an ethics council, could offer courts and patent offices the benefits of ethical expertise.Footnote 136 Comparatively, and despite the debate, no such institutional solution has been created within the framework of the EPO, nor within the new Unified Patent Court system. Formally, it is within the powers of the CJEU to decide whether a measure of inquiry is necessary, since the commissioning of expert reports is expressly allowed by the court statute.Footnote 137 This possibility could help inform future decisions, but is not immune to criticism and practical difficulties.

5.6 The CJEU and Scientific Expertise

In ISCO the CJEU recognised that in Brüstle it had relied on incorrect scientific data concerning parthenotes, but it did so only indirectly, and fell short of actually acknowledging that there had been a technical failure,Footnote 138 or that the CJEU was misdirected or had misunderstood the science at issue. Hence, both decisions revive an old debate concerning the limits of judicial adjudication in scientifically very complex matters. It could be argued that a broad discretion of the Court in deciding on legal and scientific facts is necessary to fulfil the Court’s function in ensuring a harmonious interpretation of EU law. However, the function of general courts of last resort, such as the CJEU, is primarily to rule on matters of law. If the decision on whether parthenotes – or oocytes created by nuclear cell transfer – constitute embryos in accordance with the Biotech Directive is indeed merely a matter of factual determination (as admitted by the CJEU), the Court would have been wise to avoid adjudicating directly on such matters.Footnote 139 Alternatively, and in the absence of any information indicating the contrary,Footnote 140 the CJEU should at least have based such a decision not merely on the submissions of the parties, but also on commissioned independent expert reports on the state of scientific knowledge and technical possibilities.

On a positive note, ISCO nevertheless signifies an important step, since the CJEU appears to at least indirectly recognise the inherent dangers and difficulties of ruling in complex matters concerning sensitive scientific facts. This appears even more important now, since the CJEU will also have limited opportunity to ultimately judge on particular issues arising within the emerging Unitary Patent System.

There is another point to be made: questions are raised by the re-enforcement of “current scientific knowledge”Footnote 141 as a criterion to determine whether a parthenote, or another organism, is inherently capable of developing into a human being. Firstly, the issue of determining the relevant moment in time to consider when defining “current” remains unresolved. In comparison, the EPO post-WARF practice has been to consider the date of filing.Footnote 142 However, in ISCO the CJEU has accepted arguments concerning the nature of parthenotes based on scientific papers published long after the applications’ filing dates.Footnote 143 The CJEU naturally based its findings on the material facts as settled by the referring court. The use by courts of scientific evidence posterior to the filing date may be defendable from a procedural point of view, since the decision is limited to a matter of interpretation of legal concepts. However, considering the functions and nature of the patent rights, this approach creates unwarranted legal uncertainty: at any moment during the life of the patent right new scientific developments may render the claims in total or partially non-patentable.Footnote 144 Likewise, at the filing date, applicants (and similarly potential opponents) will still have difficulty in determining with certainty whether an invention is excluded or patentable, and deciding on the appropriate IP strategy. This was already apparent from the final decision of the German Federal Supreme Court in Brüstle, where the court appeared to be willing to consider post-filing technological developments that allowed the extraction of stem cells without necessarily destroying the embryo. Another related matter is the procedural issue of determining the value to be attributed to the scientific evidence presented, and the level of consensus in the scientific community required, for an expert opinion to be considered reliable by the courts. The CJEU relied on its previous decision in Smits and Peerbooms Footnote 145 and declared the standard to be “knowledge which is sufficiently tried and tested by international medical science”.Footnote 146 The chosen standard is on the one hand unclear because in the context of the present norm it requires proof of a negative factFootnote 147; and on the other hand dependent on non-harmonised national procedural rules.

5.7 TRIPS Compliance

Until Brüstle, most important patentability decisions in Europe were issued either by the EPO or by national patent offices and courts. The EPO is an international organisation, and although all of its member states are simultaneously members of the WTOFootnote 148 and thereby signatory parties to TRIPS,Footnote 149 the EPO in itself is not formally obliged to comply with TRIPS. However, during the revision of the EPC, consistency with TRIPS and EU law was acknowledged as a necessity.Footnote 150 Article 27(2) TRIPS allows signatory parties to include in their domestic patent law “provisions necessary to protect ordre public or morality”.Footnote 151 Article 53(a) EPC and corresponding national norms predate TRIPS and compliance with it has been mostly presumed. However, this norm was rarely invoked until the advent of biotechnology. Moreover, exclusions and exceptions were traditionally interpreted narrowly.Footnote 152 The expansionary evolution of EPO practice,Footnote 153 the posterior enactment of the Biotech Directive and its broad interpretation by the CJEU, have changed the legal landscape, creating a shifting paradigm for the morality exception. This jurisprudential morality standard has to be debated in the light of the international obligations consubstantiated by TRIPS.Footnote 154

The CJEU decision in Brüstle created a historical approach equivalent to an original-sin doctrine that has established a perpetual link between a damaging action – the immoral act of embryo destruction – and a fruit-of-the-poisonous-tree or strict-liability standard. This understanding was subsequently included in the EPO Guidelines, expanding the original scope of the EPC provision, which had been generally held to be necessarily construed narrowly.Footnote 155 Strict adherence to the CJEU’s broad construction of the exception could result in excluding the entire field of technology based on hESC research from patentability.Footnote 156

Compliance with the TRIPS Agreement has to be considered by reference to its Art. 27(2), which allows members to “exclude from patentability inventions, the prevention within their territory of the commercial exploitation of which is necessary to protect ordre public or morality” (emphasis added). As observed by several commentators, the ability of member states to introduce ordre public and morality exceptions is not absolute, but rather conditional on the necessity of the measure.Footnote 157 Joseph Straus mentions that this should entail that “firstly, and most importantly, exclusion from patentability of a specific invention is only allowed, if the commercial exploitation of that invention is prohibited in the territory of the respective Member”.Footnote 158 The letter of the law states that the patentability exclusion cannot be based on mere legal prohibition of commercialisation. This is clearly because it will not always be necessary to deny patent incentive, and on the contrary compelling reasons may dictate that incentive be granted to further research in order to invent non-detrimental (or less detrimental) versions. It may also be the case that regulatory prohibition has been determined for reasons that cannot be subsumed under the concepts of ordre public and morality. Through the use of the word “necessary”, Art. 27(2) TRIPS introduces a two-step test: (1) that the exclusion necessarily contributes in practice to the protection of ordre public and morality values; and (2) that no less restrictive measures are available.Footnote 159 In the light of the current EU regulatory framework, it is at best debatable whether the CJEU’s jurisprudence fulfils these conditions. This is something that the national courts may have realised, which explains to a certain extent the German Supreme Court’s Brüstle decision,Footnote 160 but also the difficulties of the UK court and the later referral in ISCO.Footnote 161

The present decision in ISCO re-introduces a more nuanced approach and indirectly re-establishes some balance in the jurisdictional construction. However, Straus’ compelling arguments remain unblemished and this decision has not altered their validity. In strict legal terms, member states could be brought before the dispute settlement body of the WTO for lack of compliance with Art. 27(2) TRIPS,Footnote 162 naturally depending on political and patent policy considerations, which are beyond the scope of this paper. This more balanced approach may signify that other arguments will be less likely to succeed, since it can no longer be argued that any technology based on hESC research is, per se, necessarily immoral and thus that a field of technology has been banned from patentability.

6 Practical Implications

Considering the legal reasoning and material findings of the referring court, it is expected that it will conclude that, under the current scientific knowledge, parthenotes cannot be considered inherently capable of developing into a human being. As a consequence, the patent will probably be granted as amended. However, given the issues examined above, a high level of uncertainty will persist.

6.1 Implications at the National Level

The CJEU in ISCO deferred to national courts the evaluation of whether parthenotes, and arguably other organisms resulting from genetic manipulation, “have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being” and thus whether these can be subsumed under the definition of human embryo under Art. 6(2)(c) Biotech Directive. No further guidance was offered as to what constitutes a “human being”, nor what point in the biological development process, if any, determines such qualification. Simultaneously, an analysis of human rights law shows that there is no uniform European definition of human being, nor any consensus on its lower and upper limits.

ISCO also introduced the requirement that such evaluation should be made according to “current scientific knowledge”. However, it is left undetermined what point in time should be considered when assessing the state of “current scientific knowledge”. Therefore, applicants may tend to develop strategies guided by the consideration of whether the invention’s patentability is likely to suffer or benefit with time.

The approach currently followed at the EPO, as stated in the EPO Guidelines, is to consider the state of the art at the filing date.Footnote 163 This might be extremely complex in cases where the possibility of obtaining the said base material by a certain method is anticipated in the literature, but there is still uncertainty as to whether such a method would produce the intended results, or in cases where there are still technical problems to be overcome. It was also left undetermined whether the standard in ISCO for determining the current scientific knowledge will translate into a novelty/state-of-the-art standard, or rather an inventive-step standard. It is noteworthy that the test set in ISCO is one of “current scientific knowledge” and not a test of “technical state of the art”, as used in patent examination. This may point in the direction of national courts using a broader concept than the EPO or patent offices, meaning that the mere scientific possibility of obtaining hESCs by methods considered ethical would defeat the original-sin legal presumption set in Brüstle. In theory, linking patentability decisions to the “current scientific knowledge” would make it possible to introduce objectivity and reach a higher level of harmonisation and legal certainty in Europe. However, as explained above, this may not be the case.

Another potential practical concern is that national courts may be bound to different extents by the material facts and scientific evidence presented by the parties in the specific proceedings, depending on each jurisdiction’s procedural rules and stance concerning the court’s powers of discovery and the parties’ legal obligations of disclosure during civil proceedings. This procedural aspect, often overlooked, should also be carefully considered by potential applicants for national patents.

The CJEU has not defined the term “human being”, but the patentability test is based on the ability, or lack thereof, of autonomous development into a human being. The reasoning makes it difficult to apply with certainty the same logic to other technology developments. It can be argued that the test set in ISCO only applies to parthenotes, or on the other hand, that it should also apply to any organisms created by technical means, such as SCNT. It remains an open question whether and how national courts will apply this decision in relation to similar, but not identical, factual situations, and whether national courts will eventually decide that further referrals are necessary.

Taking into consideration the solution found in Brüstle by the referring court – the German Federal Supreme CourtFootnote 164 – it is likely that jurisdictions with a patent-holder-friendly tradition will tend to apply the ISCO ruling in its most permissive reading. There is also a possibility that some national courts may extend the inherency test to other organisms, allowing the patentability of hESCs obtained from other sources. It is likely that any attempt to apply the current ruling to new factual circumstances will generate further referrals. Simultaneously, it appears equally possible that some jurisdictions may follow a stricter approach and even resort to the general ordre public and morality exception. As pointed out by the AG,Footnote 165 the decision to consider parthenotes as not included in the concept of human embryo does not preclude that, at national level, parthenotes and hESCs originating in parthenotes, or other pluripotent cells and their uses, may be considered, either in general or in specific cases, offensive to morality in accordance with the general exclusion in Art. 6(1) Biotech Directive on the basis of other grounds of public order and morality. Furthermore, despite the fact that some parthenote-derived stem cell lines and inventions based on these may be patentable, caution remains advisable concerning applications which do not mention the origin of the hESCs, since these will still cover every stem cell line and thus also the use of embryos, including their destruction, for commercial purposes.

6.2 At the EU Level

The ISCO decision may have a broader implication concerning the patentability of all stem cell research: it has now been established that pluripotent human embryonic stem cells can be obtained without necessarily destroying an embryo. Arguably, this could mean the beginning of the end of the Brüstle historical approach.

Faced with unsurpassable evidence that the Brüstle decision was inconsistent with scientific facts, the court adapted the legal fiction to reality. It is possible that future referrals will provide opportunities for further clarification of the doctrine set in Brüstle and eventually its full replacement. In the long run, provided that technological advances do not render the legal discussion obsolete, it is likely that the Brüstle historical approach may prove to be unsustainable. A generalisation of the Brüstle reasoning to the entire biotechnology field implies the conclusion that if an act or research step at the outset of the process that leads to an invention is found to be immoral, then the invention will not be patentable.Footnote 166 A practical example could be found in the case of data and biological materials obtained previously in serious breach of acceptable ethical norms, for instance using human beings as test subjects without their consent or knowledge. Naturally, the issue relates to a broader ethical dilemma: should information and biological materials obtained unethically be destroyed, or is their use for therapeutic and medical research purposes morally acceptable?Footnote 167 Inventions are based on scientific information created using data and biological materials. If these were obtained in serious breach of ethical standards, under the fruit-of-the-poisoned-tree reasoning in Brüstle, the resulting invention would not be patentable.Footnote 168 It would be irrelevant how much time had passed, or that the claims did not mention the origin and retrieval methods of the source materials, or arguably, that the inventor had no connection with, knowledge of or influence on the methodology used to obtain such data and source material.

It can be argued that ISCO marks the beginning of the end of the historical approach set in Brüstle. The idea that all forthcoming stem cell research is morally tainted by the stain of the original unethical conduct – the previous destruction of a blastocyst to establish stem cell lines – will be easier to circumvent/disclaim, since now at least one morally acceptable source of pluripotent stem cells is available. Indirectly, it is also now established that pluripotent hESCs should not, by themselves, be considered embryos, since they are not capable of originating all types of cells. The uncertainty concerning the legal status of pluripotent cells has thus now been resolved. This is a welcome step, and although it remains to be seen whether these stem cells are as safe and useful as stem cells obtained by other methods, this decision re-opens patent possibilities for stem cell-related inventions.

As soon as they are in force, the European patent with unitary effectFootnote 169 and the Unified Patent CourtFootnote 170 will create an extra route of patent protection in Europe and another layer of jurisdictional adjudication. It is difficult to predict how the new Unified Patent Court will reason. However, it is not completely out of the question to expect that the current CJEU jurisprudence will be observed and applied, including in respect of the European patent with unitary effect.Footnote 171

6.3 Implications at the EPO Level

It remains to be seen how the EPO will incorporate this decision. If previous actions are an indication, the Boards of Appeal will most likely adopt a similar reasoning and follow the CJEU jurisprudence. The EPO is not formally obliged to accept the decisions of the CJEU, since the EPO is not an EU institution. However, it is to be expected that the ISCO decision will also be reflected in the EPO Guidelines and implemented in the practice of the EPO. The current practice has been to take into consideration the entire teaching of the application and the relevant description, in order to establish whether, in the light of the state of the art at the filing date, the stem cells used “are obtained exclusively by the use, involving the destruction, of a human embryo or not”.Footnote 172 As mentioned in the previous section, the EPO will also have to determine whether “in the light of current scientific knowledge”, a parthenote or other organism, “in itself, ha[s] the inherent capacity of developing into a human being”. The dependence on the state of “current scientific knowledge” to determine the scope of an exception to patentability is problematic.Footnote 173

It can be said that, directly, the ISCO decision will only apply to the limited number of patent applications that concern parthenote-related inventions. However, in the silence of the application, the mere technical possibility of obtaining stem cell lines from parthenotes would seem to destroy the legal presumption as to the non-ethical origin of the stem cell lines. Caution is still advised, since the current wording of the EPO Guidelines appears to point to the contrary and, in the sense of a requirement, to at least disclaim the use of stem cell lines obtained involving embryo destruction. Already in WARF,Footnote 174 and even more so now with Technion,Footnote 175 it is the applicant that is required to either disclaim or submit references that establish that the source material used is not immoral. This conflicts with the intention of the drafters of the EPC and with the traditional EPO approach of narrow construction of exceptions to patentability.Footnote 176 Exceptions are not positive requirements, and in this sense can be said to have been intended to be invoked and argued against the applicant. Under the general rule concerning the burden of proof, it is the party that invokes the lack of ethical compliance that should be required to offer evidence of misconduct.Footnote 177 On the other hand, it has been the longstanding practice of the EPO to deny patentability when the claims may encompass excluded subject-matter. Therefore, it has been suggested that repositories of hESCs should contain and make available to researchers information concerning the techniques used for obtaining cell lines.Footnote 178 In the absence of such data, it is advisable that patent applicants should be proactive in securing such information.

ISCO establishes that stem cells derived from parthenotes may be outside the scope of the morality clause. While the doctrine in Brüstle has not been recanted, it does offer new possibilities for applicants. For patent applicants wishing to apply for patents under the PCT-EPC scheme, careful claim drafting is still advisable. In particular, the applicant might consider disclaiming the use of hESCs, or limit the claims to the use of cell lines obtained from parthenotes, or to the use of iPSC lines, and include references that sustain that this is possible in the light of the scientific state of the art. In the light of ISCO, it will also be advisable to disclaim any further genetic manipulation of parthenotes that might allow them to be considered totipotent, or inherently capable of developing into a human being. The use of disclaimers to avoid the prohibited subject-matter should be considered with great care, since merely including a general disclaimer, such as for example “wherein the method does not involve use of a human embryo for industrial or commercial purposes” is likely to affect the clarity of the claims (Art. 84 EPC) and be rejected for not meeting the requirements of Art. 123(2) EPC.Footnote 179

7 A Brief Comparison with the US Situation

Historically US courts have examined patent eligibility questions under US patent statutes with reference to the “Patent Clause”Footnote 180 of the US Constitution. The object of the Patent Clause is to promote the progress of science and the useful arts by bestowing upon inventors a temporary reward in return for the benefit to the public provided by the invention.Footnote 181 While the Patent Clause speaks of securing exclusive rights for inventors without expressly mentioning patents, 35 U.S.C. § 101 of the US Patent Statute provides that “[w]hoever invents or discovers any new and useful process, machine, manufacture, or composition of matter, or any new and useful improvement thereof, may obtain a patent therefor, subject to the conditions and requirements of this title.”

Unlike European patent legislation, however, US patent statutes do not include an explicitly codified morality clause and have generally not defined which types of inventions or discoveries fall outside the scope of patentability.Footnote 182 The generally accepted explanation is that these are Constitutional limitations based upon the framers’ intent in enacting the Patent Clause. It has thus traditionally been the province of the courts and the US Patent and Trademark Office (USPTO) to establish limits for subject-matter that may not be granted patent protection.Footnote 183 In the past, the USPTO has in rare circumstances refused to issue patents for inventions of incredible or specious utility, or for inventions whose utilisation is not adequately disclosed in the application. Additionally, the courts have interpreted the utility requirement to exclude inventions deemed to be “injurious to the well-being, good policy, or good morals of society”.Footnote 184 Although several billsFootnote 185 had attempted to categorically exclude from patent protection certain biological material that had been isolated from its natural environment, such as genes, proteins and stem cells, the US Patent Reform Act of 2011Footnote 186 principally still leaves these fundamental questions to the courts and the USPTO.Footnote 187

Despite rejecting patent applications for gambling machinesFootnote 188 and human chimeraFootnote 189 under the so-called “moral utility doctrine”,Footnote 190 the USPTO has so far pursued a more liberal approach in the stem cell area than its European counterparts and has already granted several patents that directly claim hESCs, including culture methods, differentiated cells derived from hESCs and even hESCs per se.Footnote 191 This approach, in combination with President Obama’s decision to lift the ban on governmental funding for stem cell research,Footnote 192 has led to a very research- and patent-friendly environment for stem cell technology in the US.

However, in the aftermath of the much-debated US Supreme Court decisions in Myriad Footnote 193 and Prometheus,Footnote 194 the patentability of stem cells that have been isolated from their natural environments, and of biological processes and methods that are employed in stem cell technology, now stands on shaky ground in the US. While previous challenges were typically based on prior art and the US standards for novelty and non-obviousness,Footnote 195 Myriad and Prometheus have opened the gates for new challenges based on arguments related to patent eligibility. This has resulted in considerable legal uncertainty.Footnote 196

The elusiveness of the current situation is also illustrated by the new USPTO guidelines.Footnote 197 With regard to stem cell-related technology, these new guidelines and the case examples indicate that their patent eligibility will rely on whether the claimed subject-matter is “significantly different” to the product as it is found in nature. It now remains to be seen how exactly the USPTO will interpret and apply these instructions. One central question will be: how much human involvement and manipulation is required to make such cells “significantly different” to the product as it is found in nature under the Myriad and Prometheus standards of patent eligibility? And: to what extent would such manipulations be acceptable with regard to other laws and regulations?

Be that as it may, it can be expected that these recent US developments will lead to an increased number of proceedings and challenges in US courts and at the USPTO against patent claims directed to technologies that utilise isolated hESCs. This is exemplified by recent challenges against the US equivalentsFootnote 198 to the European WARF patent claims that were rejected by the EPO’s EBA in November 2008. In the same year, that is, prior to the US Supreme Court decisions in Myriad and Prometheus, the USPTO did not follow the EPO’s approach and in a heavily debated decision upheld important claims of the three WARF patents for in vitro cultivation of human embryo-derived cells.Footnote 199 However, after enduring controversy revolving around the prior art and an asserted lack of novelty and non-obviousness, these claims were subsequently limited by another USPTO decision from 2010.Footnote 200 Then, in 2013, Consumer Watchdog challenged the WARF patent in an appeal to the US Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit,Footnote 201 asserting that the claimed cells are “products of nature” and that the patent should thus be invalidated under the new patentability standard established in Myriad.

In June 2014, the challenge was rejected since Consumer Watchdog did not itself work the claimed patents or plan to use hESC-derived technology, thereby lacking legal standing based on the principles established by the US Supreme Court in Lujan Footnote 202 and MedImmune.Footnote 203 It is, however, only a matter of time before parties with legal standing challenge such claims; the patentability of such cells therefore remains uncertain in the wake of Myriad.Footnote 204

8 Concluding Remarks

In our view, ISCO constitutes a first step in the right direction, introducing a more nuanced approach to stem cell patenting. However, difficulties will persist. Considering the combined significance of the Brüstle and ISCO rulings to such important medical areas as regenerative medicine and cellular therapy, the persistent legal uncertainty and the lack of generally applicable clear guidance are very unfortunate and do not serve the goal of a harmonious and effective European legal framework for innovation.

Legal norms should be interpreted inter alia by reference to their purposes and their systematic insertion and by taking into consideration the other norms that are part of the broader legal system. Within an incomplete system, such as EU law, this interpretative precaution is even more important. Legislative and judicial determination of ethical and scientifically uncertain or controversial concepts should be approached carefully and only as far as strictly necessary. The present ruling raises matters of legal interpretation and further difficulties in subsuming the factual reality of scientific development under the normative construction. Relying on a patent law-specific notion of human being, albeit indirectly, constitutes a weak point of the CJEU’s jurisprudence. In our view, such an understanding also creates the legal fiction of an EU consensus concerning the scope of protection of human dignity and the extent to which it applies to unborn humans. This contravenes the history of the provision, the ECHR jurisprudence, and the CJEU’s own admission. It is also an interpretative solution contradicted by the EU regulatory framework. ISCO has done little to reduce the inconsistency between patent law and other fields of EU law and regulation. Stem cell-based therapies provide hope for millions of people suffering from inter alia severe self-immune degenerative diseases, for which currently no cure is available. Meanwhile, myriads of fertilised human ova are discarded in in vitro fertilisation treatments. For this reason, research involving embryo destruction is allowed under specific conditions in several national jurisdictions, considered ethically justified according to EU regulations and even supported by public research grants. However, the results of such therapeutic research are – somewhat paradoxically – declared immoral for patent law purposes.

The introduced criterion of inherent capacity has not improved legal certainty, since it may sustain different interpretations, which indirectly implies that further clarification is required concerning the intended meaning of such distinction. The approach also leaves room to consider the moral status of non-viable embryos. It can be argued that there is a moral differentiation between destroying an embryo and destroying a non-viable embryo or a parthenote. In this sense, the distinction created by ISCO is welcome. However, linking the concept of human embryo to its viability raises the spectre of eugenics, which is inconsistent with humanitarian law and national constitutions. The relationship between the interpretative approach set out in Brüstle and the added criterion introduced by ISCO is also open to interpretation as either cumulative or alternative conditions. Moreover, the present decision leaves unsolved the patentability status of ova subjected to SCNT and related methods and products. In this sense, it is reasonable to expect that this has not been the last word of the CJEU on stem cell patentability.

Despite the more flexible approach now introduced, compliance with TRIPS also remains debatable. Our comparison with the US approach, which does not entail a similar statutory exception from patentability, demonstrates that the issue is equally controversial on both sides of the Atlantic, albeit for different reasons. In the light of the emerging unitary patent system it furthermore became clear that we should perhaps not only worry about the tunnel vision of overly specialised unified patent courts, but also about the occasional involvement of general courts in highly complex and sensitive matters demanding multifaceted expertise and broader debate. It will be important to develop an appropriate infrastructure ensuring that such involvement is not only based on an in-depth understanding and respect for general legal principles, but also on correct fact-finding and scientific expertise.

Seen in an overall context, in its efforts to avoid divergent national interpretations the CJEU jurisprudence has to a certain extent lost track of the purposes and functions of patents and the limits of EU harmonisation. It introduced new layers of complexity and arguably opened further venues for divergent national patentability practices, thus defeating the purpose of the referrals.

Despite all of the problems identified above, ISCO still brings some clarification and re-instates some much-needed balance into CJEU jurisprudence concerning the interpretation of Art. 6(2)(c) Biotech Directive. Although it could be argued that the ISCO decision will have limited practical relevance since it will only apply directly to a minor number of patent applications, it nevertheless offers venues for general legal argumentation regarding patent exceptions, as well as specific arguments in favour of restricting the scope given to the Brüstle decision and corresponding EPO Guidelines.

Finally, the authors fully recognise the importance of promoting induced pluripotent stem cell technology, which 1 day might make the use of hESCs unnecessary. Yet, despite recent advances, this promising technology still faces many significant problems and hESC research is still required to improve it. In the absence of an established alternative to the use of hESCs, it is therefore positive that certain parthenotes are now deemed to be a morally acceptable source of hESCs. ISCO can thus be read as pointing the way forward to a narrower and more consistent interpretation of patentability exceptions and the Biotech Directive. Thus, it might indeed have the “inherent capacity” of developing into a reasonable doctrine on stem cell patenting.

9 Postscript

Some time has elapsed since the present article was submitted for publication; therefore an update is in order. As predicted, after the CJEU decision on ISCO, the High Court of Justice of England and Wales, Chancery Division ordered the decision of the comptroller excluding from patentability ISCO’s patent applications to be set aside and the patent applications to be remitted to the Intellectual Property Office for further consideration.Footnote 205 Both patents were granted as amended in October 2015.Footnote 206

More recently, the EPO has published the 2015 version of its Guidelines.Footnote 207 The CJEU jurisprudence was indirectly incorporated in EPO practice through the inclusion in the EPO Guidelines. In particular, a new paragraph was inserted clearly stating that although the CJEU judgments on the interpretation of the Biotech Directive are not binding on the EPO they may be considered as being persuasive. This understanding follows from the EPO decisions Technion Footnote 208 and Asterias Footnote 209 (see above Sect. 6.3).