Here are two prima facie plausible theses about propositional knowledge:

  • Fallibilism: Possibly, a belief constitutes knowledge even though the belief is justified in a way that’s compatible with its being either false or accidentally true.

  • Attributabilism: Each instance of knowledge is related to its subject in a way similar to that in which each intentional action is related to its agent.

Baron Reed (2007, 2009) develops and defends a novel argument for the incompatibility of fallibilism and attributabilism.Footnote 1 In this paper, I clarify and critically assess Reed’s incompatibility argument. Against the backdrop of an example in which an action is non-intentional due to the role that an accidentally true belief plays in the action’s etiology, I argue that Reed’s incompatibility argument defeats itself: two of its premises are themselves jointly incompatible.

1 I

First, I need to justify my clarificatory statement of the thesis that Reed labels “attributabilism.” I’ve explicitly stated attributabilism in terms of intentional action. While Reed does not so state attributabilism, such a statement constitutes the most charitable interpretation of Reed’s (somewhat less clear) formulations of the thesis.Footnote 2

Here is Reed’s initial statement of Attributabilism:

For any state of knowledge k that a person S possesses, the possession of k is attributable to S. (2007: 238)

As Reed immediately acknowledges, if the material after the comma is equivalent to (something like) “knowledge of k’s propositional content can be accurately ascribed to S,” then attributabilism is a truism. But if attributabilism is a truism, then Reed’s incompatibility argument is tantamount to an attempt to establish that fallibilism is self-contradictory—an extremely implausible thesis which Reed clearly does not endorse (cf. 2002; 2007: 236–7; 2009: 94, 102).

In order to forestall such a misinterpretation of attributabilism specifically and his incompatibility argument more generally, Reed provides the following commentary on his initial statement of attributabilism:

But what is meant by “attributable” is something stronger [than ‘can be accurately ascribed to’]. A comparison with the attributability of actions is instructive here.

There are different ways of explaining the special relationship an agent bears to her action. According to simple versions of compatibilism, …the action must be caused by the agent’s will. For more sophisticated versions of compatibilism, the action must come from… the “Real Self,” where some philosophers take this to be an appropriately structured will while others argue it is the agent’s faculty of reason. Among libertarians, …we find similar variety: some of them require only that the action be indeterministically produced by the agent (perhaps on the basis of reasons the agent has), while others hold the agent to be a special sort of cause. But what is common to all of these philosophers, compatibilists and libertarians alike, is the attempt to show how the action came from the person in question. It is not enough for the person to be merely the locus of a causal process terminating in something like an action. A reflexive leg-kicking, for example, is not something that one does—it fails to belong, in the relevant sense, to the person who kicks.

Many epistemologists have made a similar point about knowledge and its relation to the person who has it. (2007: 238-9)

According to the attributabilist, then, propositional knowledge is similar to a certain practical relation—that is, a certain relation that people bear to (at least some of) their actions. In the above passage, Reed expresses the pertinent practical relation with “came from,” an emphasized “does,” and “belong to.” Elsewhere, in one of his clearest and most concise statements of attributabilism, Reed connects “the relevant sense” of “belong to” with practical moral responsibility (i.e., moral responsibility for action)Footnote 3: “[Knowledge] must belong to the person as her own doing, much as an action for which a person is responsible must belong to her” (2009: 103).

Note that, contrary to what the third sentence of the longer quotation in the last paragraph may suggest (“the special relationship an agent bears to her action”), the practical relation to which the attributabilist assimilates propositional knowledge is not that of mere (action) performance. If the pertinent practical relation is mere performance, then both (a) the emphasized “does” (near the end of the longer quotation in the last paragraph) and (b) the phrase “for which a person is responsible” (in the shorter quotation at the end of the last paragraph) are not only unnecessary but also potentially misleading.Footnote 4 Charity thus demands that we interpret the attributabilist as appealing to a practical relation that’s logically stronger than that of mere performance.

The clarificatory material provided in the last couple paragraphs yields the following revised statement of attributabilism:

Each instance of knowledge is related to its subject in a way similar to that in which each action that belongs to its agent in a stronger-than-mere performance sense required for moral responsibility is related to its agent.

Now there’s a problem with this revised statement of attributabilism: Unless we read “moral responsibility” as “nonderivative moral responsibility” (where one is “non-derivatively morally responsible” for an action iff one’s moral responsibility for that action does not derive from one’s moral responsibility for some other action), the revised statement of attributabilism simply fails to pick out a practical relation and thus fails to assimilate knowledge to such a relation. While nonderivative moral responsibility does require a practical relation that’s logically stronger than mere performance—plausible candidates include intentional performance and metaphysically free performance—derivative moral responsibility does not require a practical relation that’s logically stronger than mere performance. To see this, consider a drunk driver who inadvertently strikes a pedestrian. We can imagine this case such that the driver is derivatively morally responsible for striking the pedestrian even though the driver’s striking the pedestrian was merely something that the driver did: the driver didn’t strike the pedestrian intentionally, or for a reason, or freely, or knowingly, etc.

Charitably interpreted, then, the attributabilist assimilates propositional knowledge to a certain practical relation that is (a) required for nonderivative moral responsibility and (b) logically stronger than mere performance. One such practical relation, of course, is nonderivative moral responsibility. But interpreting attributabilism in terms of nonderivative moral responsibility conflicts with Reed’s claim that the practical relation to which the attributabilist likens propositional knowledge does not entail moral responsibility. Writes Reed: “Just as an action… may be attributable to a person who does not deserve credit for it…, so an instance of knowledge… may be attributable to a person who does not deserve credit for it” (2007: 242; cf. 2009: 103).

I see four additional candidates for the practical relation to which the attributabilist likens propositional knowledge: metaphysically free performance; self-controlled performance; intentional performance; and apt performance—that is, performance whose success manifests some or other of the agent’s competences (cf. Sosa, 2015).Footnote 5 Interpreting attributabilism in terms of metaphysically free performance conflicts with Reed’s claim that the relevant practical relation does not entail (what John Martin Fischer [2008: 57] calls) regulative control—that is, control over (rather than mere control of) an event or state. (It’s extremely plausible to think that an action one performed was metaphysically free only if one was free with respect to—and therefore had control over—the action’s occurrence.) Writes Reed (2007: 242): “…knowledge is attributable to us, not because we have ultimate control over it, but because it comes out of a cognitive ‘Real Self’.” Now the sentence just quoted may suggest that attributabilism should be understood in terms of self-controlled performance. But such an interpretation of attributabilism conflicts with the obvious fact that an action for which one is nonderivatively morally responsible needn’t also be an instance of self-control—think, for example, of certain akratic or weak-willed actions (cf. Mele, 2012).

Unlike the previously rejected interpretations, statements of attributabilism that focus on either intentional action or apt action fit well with relevant material in Reed’s papers. For starters, an intentional action can be accurately described as “coming from an agent” and “belonging to an agent as their own doing” (Reed’s expressions), as can an apt action. Moreover, either of “does intentionally” and “does aptly” would be a charitable interpretation of the emphasized “does” in the following sentence (quoted earlier): “A reflexive leg-kicking… is not something that one does—it fails to belong, in the relevant sense, to the person who kicks” (Reed, 2007: 238–9). Finally, each of the following two theses is extremely plausible: (i) one is nonderivatively morally responsible for an action one performed only if one performed the action intentionally; (ii) any intentional action is an apt action.Footnote 6 Accordingly, both intentional performance and apt performance are practical relations that are stronger than mere performance and plausibly regarded as required for nonderivative (practical) moral responsibility.

We have before us two tenable interpretations of attributabilism: one that invokes intentional action, and one that invokes apt action. If one of the indicated practical relations is logically stronger than the other, then we should focus first on the interpretation of attributabilism that invokes the stronger relation, since Reed’s incompatibility argument would be more likely to succeed on the stronger interpretation of attributabilism (as we strengthen the interpretation of attributabilism, we weaken Reed’s incompatibility thesis, thereby making the latter easier to establish). Is one of the indicated practical relations stronger than the other?

Arguably, yes: while all intentional actions are apt actions, some apt actions are non-intentional actions. Consider the following case, which is inspired by Alfred Mele and Paul Moser (1994: 41) as well as Duncan Pritchard (2012: 260)Footnote 7:

An informant whom I justifiedly believe to be extremely reliable tells me that the winning numbers in tomorrow’s pick-your-own-number lottery will be 8675309. On this occasion, my informant is in fact just guessing about tomorrow’s winning numbers. But my informant’s guess turns out to be accurate, for—unbeknownst to both me and my informant—there exists a sufficiently powerful and knowledgeable third party whose job is to ensure that tomorrow’s winning numbers turn out to be whatever I think they will be. Through my informant’s testimony, I acquire a justified but accidentally true belief that the winning numbers will be 8675309. I acquire an intention to win the lottery by picking 8675309. I intentionally pick those numbers. I win the lottery.

This example can be understood such that I non-intentionally won the lottery—that is, I won the lottery but did not do so intentionally (cf. Gibbons, 2010; Mele, 1987; Mele & Moser, 1994).Footnote 8 In support of the ascription of aptness to my lottery win—and to echo what Mele (1992: 208) says about a relevantly similar case—note that in winning the lottery, I followed the plan component of my intention to do so and that there was no deviant connection between my intention and my picking the pertinent numbers or between my picking those numbers and my winning the lottery. Accordingly, I seem to have carried out or executed my intention to win the lottery, which in turn seems to suffice for my lottery win’s manifesting some or other pertinent competence, though not for my lottery win’s being something that I did intentionally (cf. Mele, 1992: 207–8).Footnote 9

We’ll return to this lottery case below (section 3). For now, we just need to take from it the lesson that some apt actions are non-intentional. Assuming that’s right, it follows that intentional action is logically stronger than apt action and that we should focus first on the interpretation of attributabilism that invokes intentional action, since Reed’s incompatibility argument is more likely to succeed on that (relatively strong) interpretation of attributabilism. If Reed’s argument were to succeed on the “intentional action” interpretation of attributabilism, we could then go on to consider whether his argument also succeeds on the “apt action” interpretation of attributabilism.Footnote 10

2 II

Having justified my clarificatory statement of attributabilism, I can now start moving toward a full formal statement of Reed’s argument for the incompatibility of fallibilism and attributabilism. The following passage—in which Reed is discussing an arbitrarily selected instance of fallibly justified knowledge—provides a rough initial statement of his argument:

The result, then, is that the person’s cognitive performance is not good enough to allow her to reach the truth. Her performance must be supplemented by something extrinsic—and therefore unattributable—to her. Thus, [fallibly justified] knowledge itself is not attributable to the person, either. Attributabilism is therefore false, as long as we are committed to fallibilism. (2007: 248)

To see a problem with this rough initial statement of Reed’s argument, notice that the second claim in the passage entails the third only on the following “transfer of non-attributability” assumption:

If S’s knowing that P depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is not attributable to S, then S’s knowing that P is not attributable to S.Footnote 11

Since one knows that P only if P is true, the indicated assumption entails the extremely implausible thesis that one could not have attributable knowledge of a proposition whose truth is not itself attributable to one (cf. Reed, 2007: 248–9)—for example, a necessarily true proposition which is both self-evident and obvious.

Fortunately, Reed’s argument is in fact much more nuanced and, accordingly, much more promising than is the one suggested by the passage just quoted. We can state Reed’s argument more fully and formally as follows:

2.1 Reed’s Incompatibility Argument (2007: 249–258; 2009: 94–101)

  1. (1)

    If Attributabilism is true, then there could not be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both “extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness” (2009: 99; cf. 2007: 249–50).

  2. (2)

    If Fallibilism is true, then there could be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on its exemplification of justification-independent non-accidental truth—that is, non-accidental truth whose absence is compatible with the pertinent belief’s being justified in the way that it actually is.

  3. (3)

    Justification-independent non-accidental truth is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness.

  4. (4)

    If fallibilism is true, then there could be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness [2,3].

  5. (5)

    If both fallibilism and attributabilism are true, then there both could and could not be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness [1,4].

  6. (6)

    It’s false that there both could and could not be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness.

  7. (7)

    Either fallibilism is false or attributabilism is false [5,6].

This argument is valid, and we can’t question (2) or (6). But what about (1) and (3)?

Unlike the “transfer of non-attributability” principle discussed earlier, (1) arguably allows for the possibility of one’s having attributable knowledge of a proposition whose truth is not itself attributable to one. Reed addresses (1)’s compatibility with the truth requirement on knowledge in the following two passages:

Let me begin… by returning to the attributability of actions—for example, climbing a mountain. This is something that can be fully attributable to a climber (assuming nothing unusual—for example, being carried part of the way by a sherpa guide—happens). Nevertheless, in order to climb a mountain there must be a mountain, a fact that is surely not attributable to the average climber. This does not, however, undermine the attributability of the climber’s achievement. The existence of the mountain provides the goal at which she aims. Given that the mountain is there, her reaching the top of it is something that can be entirely her own doing. Similarly, in the case of knowledge, the sense in which the truth of a belief is not attributable to the person who has it is irrelevant epistemically. In order to know that it is raining outside, I do not have to make it rain. Given that it is raining, however, I may come to know it. The truth of the proposition provides the goal at which I aim. (2007: 249)

The widespread intuitive response to Gettier cases shows that knowledge must be more than merely justified belief that is also true. The something more is that there has to be the proper connection between the subject’s justification and the truth of her belief. When that proper connection obtains…, the truth is the attained end of the subject’s performance… [T]he truth may be extrinsic to the subject’s performance, but, when that performance is properly connected to the truth, the truth then is not external to the subject’s awareness. (2009: 99)

On the basis of what Reed says in these passages, I’m happy to concede (1)’s compatibility with the truth requirement on knowledge. Moreover, on the basis of what Reed says in the following passage, I’m happy to concede (1)’s compatibility with the extremely plausible claim that knowledge is (at least) reliably produced/sustained belief:

Given that reliability supervenes, not only on the subject’s belief-forming processes but on general facts about the surrounding environment as well, we will have to grant that the subject is constituted in part by that environment. Those general facts are external to the person’s subjective awareness, but they are not extrinsic to the subject’s cognitive nature. (2007: 247)

In sum, then, I’m happy to concede that—unlike the previously discussed “transfer of non-attributability” principle—(1) is compatible with the truth and reliability requirements on knowledge.

We’ll return to (1) in the next section. As for (3), here’s what Reed says in support of the thesis that justification-independent non-accidental truth is extrinsic to the subject’s cognitive performance:

[General facts about the subject’s surrounding environment] are not extrinsic to the subject’s cognitive nature. However, the same cannot be said about the environmental factors whose presence may give rise to problematic accidentality. These are different in kind from the much more general features of the surrounding environment that help constitute reliability and are therefore intrinsic to the subject. So, when the factors that might lead to accidentality are absent, this is not something that can be attributed to the subject. (2007: 247-8; cf. 2009: 97)

On the basis of what Reed says in the above passage (and related ones), I’m happy to concede that justification-independent non-accidental truth is extrinsic to cognitive performance.

What does Reed say about (3)’s other element, the thesis that justification-independent non-accidental truth is external to the subject’s awareness? Focusing on a subject (Bridget) who forms (under normal conditions) a visual belief that there’s a barn in the field, Reed says the following:

The subject’s performance is not aimed at ensuring that [the relevant anti-accidentality condition] is satisfied… Bridget’s performance is directed at determining whether there is a barn in the field in front of her. She is not also trying to determine whether the surrounding fields have genuine barns or mere barn facades. In that sense, Bridget is blind as to whether the anti-accidentality condition has been met… The simple fact that there aren’t any facades around her makes no epistemic difference to her. What is problematic about the anti-accidentality condition, then, is that it is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness. Truth and justification (conceived in an externalistic way) may be one or the other, but they are not both. (2009: 99)

The above passage suggests the following argument for the “external to awareness” portion of premise (3):

In simply forming a belief that P, one isn’t trying to determine (learn, ascertain) whether one is forming a non-accidentally true belief that P. If one isn’t trying to determine whether one is forming a non-accidentally true belief that P, then one isn’t trying to form a non-accidentally true belief that P. So, when one simply forms a belief that P, one isn’t trying to form a non-accidentally true belief that P. So, belief doesn’t aim at non-accidental truth. So, a belief’s exemplification of non-accidental truth is external to the subject’s awareness.

This argument has a false premise—namely, the claim that if one isn’t trying to determine whether one is forming a non-accidentally true belief that P, then one isn’t trying to form a non-accidentally true belief that P. Your simply forming a non-accidentally true belief that P is a different state of affairs from your determining whether you’ve formed such a belief. Hence, the indicated premise is false: possibly, one aims to form a non-accidentally true belief that P without also aiming to determine whether one is forming such a belief.

Despite this reservation about the “external to awareness” portion of (3), I’m happy to concede premise (3) to Reed. Nevertheless, I believe that Reed’s incompatibility argument fails. Indeed, I believe that the argument defeats itself: premises (1) and (3) are themselves jointly incompatible. Let me explain.

3 III

Recall the lottery example described and discussed above (section 1):

An informant whom I justifiedly believe to be extremely reliable tells me that the winning numbers in tomorrow’s pick-your-own-number lottery will be 8675309. On this occasion, my informant is in fact just guessing about tomorrow’s winning numbers. But my informant’s guess turns out to be accurate, for—unbeknownst to both me and my informant—there exists a sufficiently powerful and knowledgeable third party whose job is to ensure that tomorrow’s winning numbers turn out to be whatever I think they will be. Through my informant’s testimony, I acquire a justified but accidentally true belief that the winning numbers will be 8675309.Footnote 12 I acquire an intention to win the lottery by picking 8675309. I intentionally pick those numbers. I win the lottery.

As we’ve already noted, this example can be understood such that I aptly but non-intentionally won the lottery. Notice, though, that we can convert the above case into one in which I intentionally win the lottery by making my belief about the winning numbers non-accidentally true:

An informant whom I justifiedly believe to be extremely reliable tells me that the winning numbers in tomorrow’s pick-your-own-number lottery will be 8675309. On this occasion, my informant does indeed know that the winning numbers will be 8675309. Through my informant’s testimony, I acquire a justified and non-accidentally true belief that the winning numbers in tomorrow’s lottery will be 8675309. I acquire an intention to win the lottery by picking 8675309. I intentionally pick those numbers. I win the lottery.

This example can be understood such that I intentionally won the lottery (cf. Mele & Moser, 1994: 60f.; Gibbons, 2010: 81). Reflection on the above pair of cases thus reveals the following modal fact: There could be an action whose status as intentional depends on a pertinent belief’s exemplifying justification-independent non-accidental truth.

Now, to begin to see the conflict between premises (1) and (3) of Reed’s argument, consider the following argument against (1):

3.1 An Argument Against (1)

  1. (8)

    There could be an action whose status as intentional depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness.

  2. (9)

    If both (8) and attributabilism are true, then there could be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness.

  3. (10)

    Even if attributabilism is true, there could be a belief whose status as knowledge depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness (hence, ~ 1) [8,9].

This argument is valid, and (9) is extremely plausible.Footnote 13 But what about (8)?

It turns out that if (3) is true, then so is (8), and the above argument against (1) succeeds. That’s how (1) and (3) conflict. Here’s an argument for the claim that (3) entails (8):

If (3) is true, then justification-independent non-accidental truth is a condition whose satisfaction is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness. But there could be an action whose status as intentional depends on a pertinent belief’s exemplifying justification-independent non-accidental truth. So, if (3) is true, then there could be an action whose status as intentional depends on the satisfaction of a condition whose obtaining is both extrinsic to the subject’s performance and external to the subject’s awareness (= 8).

This valid argument’s first premise is trivially true, and its second premise is just the modal fact revealed earlier by reflection on the two lottery cases. We can conclude, then, that (3) entails (8). But, as we saw in the last paragraph, (8) entails the denial of (1). Hence, (3) entails the denial of (1). I conclude, therefore, that Reed’s incompatibility argument fails due to self-defeat.