1 Introduction

A central topic in current philosophy of time is temporal ontology or—with reference to the main options in it—the presentism/eternalism debate. What is at stake is the ontological status of the past and the future: according to presentism, all that exists is present; according to eternalism, the past and the future exist just like the present, and thus in particular, in sheer contrast with presentism, there exist things that are not present.Footnote 1 Many philosophers in recent years have argued that this dispute is not substantial, or at least have manifested skepticism about its substantiality, thereby giving rise to a trend characterizable as deflationism (about temporal ontology).Footnote 2 Others have reacted to it by defending, in different ways, the substantiality of temporal ontology, thus constituting a stance that we may call substantialism (about temporal ontology).Footnote 3 (Of course, we are using “substantialism” here in a sense that has nothing to do with the view that concrete temporal objects are enduring substances, or the view that times are independent entities.)

The main theme in the deflationist camp, the so-called triviality (or skeptical) challenge or objection, is basically this: “exists” could either be present-tensed and mean exists now (or presently) or be disjunctively tensed and mean has existed, exists now, or will exist;Footnote 4 and once the ambiguities are eliminated presentism and eternalism are either obviously true or trivially false.Footnote 5 At the dawn of temporal ontology, it was taken for granted that the dispute was substantial and that both tenseless and tensed language were intelligible, although A-theorists favored a tensed language and B-theorists a tenseless one (see, e.g., Gale 1968, part II). Not so now: in launching their attacks, the deflationists seem to reject or downplay the legitimacy of tenseless language and thus put forward disjunctively (or conjunctively) tensed predication in lieu of tenseless predication. In reaction to this, there are two main themes that emerge in the substantialist camp. One is that the dispute requires that the quantifiers be understood as absolutely unrestricted, ranging over an all-encompassing domain, or at least as temporally unrestricted, ranging over all temporal entities and ruling out from their domain only abstract entities such as numbers or universals (Crisp 2004a; Sider 2001, 2006).Footnote 6 The other theme is that the dispute requires that a tenseless predication or copula be appropriately brought to the fore, without confusing it with disjunctively tensed predication, so as to take “exists” as meaning exists tenselessly (or simpliciter) (Hestevold and Carter 2002a, b; Ludlow 2004; Oaklander 2008, 2014).

However, despite substantialists’ efforts, the efficacy of these ideas in vindicating the substantiality of the debate has not been fully appreciated. Indeed, the very intelligibility of a domain of (temporal) items over which (temporally) unrestricted quantifiers range and the intelligibility of tenseless predication have been questioned. There is in fact a new wave of deflationist works (Callender 2012, 2017; Deng 2018, Dolev 2018; Dorato 2018; Lombard 2010; Meyer 2013a, b), which have either ignored the above mentioned anti-deflationists attempts or have explicitly argued against the intelligibility or efficacy of their appeal to (temporally) unrestricted quantifiers and tenseless predication.Footnote 7 In particular, Lombard (2010) and Meyer (2013a, b) have done this in presenting the triviality challenge as a most telling pro-deflationist argument.Footnote 8 It should be noted here that some substantialists have reiterated a reply to the triviality challenge that appeals to either tenselessness (Baron and Miller 2013; Mozersky 2011, 2015; Oaklander 2012, 2014; Torrengo 2012) or unrestricted quantification (Deasy 2017a; Sider 2011), without responding to the issues raised by Lombard and Meyer.Footnote 9 We thus think that a reply to this new wave, which provides an additional clarification of tenseless predication, unrestricted quantifiers and their role in vindicating substantialism, is in order. To support the intelligibility of tenseless predication is most crucial, because, as we shall see, without it we cannot even state eternalism of the B-theoretical variety, and we end up endorsing a tensed ontology, which undermines the debate at its very outset. But it is also important to emphasize that the appeal to unrestricted quantifiers with a corresponding domain, and the recourse to tenseless predication, are not alternative strategies, but rather two sides of the same coin, since the substantiality of the debate crucially hinges on admitting quantifiers that are both tenseless and unrestricted.Footnote 10 Thus, as we shall see, our clarification will insist on these points. Since, as noted above, the use of a tenseless language is typically associated to B-eternalism, it is important to point out that in defending the legitimacy of tenseless predication we do not mean to side with that doctrine, nor for that matter with any other view in temporal ontology. We merely wish to defend the substantiality of the debate, which, in our opinion, depends on the use of tenselessness (as well as tensedness).

We shall first review how Lombard (2010) puts forward the triviality challenge in spite of earlier substantialist moves that advertize unrestricted quantification and tenselessness. We have chosen to concentrate on Lombard’s paper, rather than on Meyer (2013b), because the former focuses on both presentism and eternalism, whereas the latter, while basically providing the same argument, considers only presentism; however in due time we shall also refer to Meyer (2013b) in order to address important points that emerge from it.Footnote 11 We shall then consider the other recent deflationists attacks. We shall rejoinder by a further elucidation of tenseless predication and unrestricted quantification, which will include a reply to some specific points raised in this new wave of deflationism, by Dolev in particular. We shall then go back to the triviality challenge in the hope that it can be finally put to rest, by properly underlining the role of tenselessness and in particular how it is involved in the unrestricted quantifiers.

2 Lombard’s presentation of the triviality challenge

Lombard (2010) focuses on a “typical statement of presentism” and a “central claim of eternalism,” namely:

(P):

Everything that exists exists now;

(E):

There are things that do not exist now.Footnote 12

The use of “now” in (P) and (E) signals a present-tensed predication. We shall follow Lombard in using “now” in this way, but we shall also use “presently” with the same aim. The first occurrence of “exists” in (P) and the “are” of (E) are grammatically present-tensed. This may suggest that these verbs involve present-tensed predications. If so, Lombard tells us, (P) and (E) are to be interpreted as follows:

(P1):

Everything that exists now exists now;

(E1):

There now are things that do not exist now.

But clearly (P1) is trivially true since it is a tautology and (E1) is trivially false since it is a contradiction in terms (we are assuming that “there are” and “there exist” are equivalent).

In an effort to avoid this result, the first occurrence of “exists” in (P) and the “are” of (E) must be interpreted in different ways. Lombard first proceeds by assuming what some have called serious tensism (see, e.g., Crisp 2004a), i.e., the thesis that there is only tensed predication, and thus notes that alternative interpretations can only be obtained by reading these verbs as disjunctively tensed, or, in Lombard’s terminology, as “disjunctively omnitemporal.” Here they are:

(P2):

Everything that existed, exists now or will exist exists now;Footnote 13

(E2):

There were, are now, or will be things that do not now exist.

But these interpretations, Lombard goes on, do not rescue presentism and eternalism from triviality, since we can appeal to an obvious truth, such as

(A):

Aristotle existed, but does not now exist,

to claim that (P2) is obviously false and (E2) is obviously true.Footnote 14

Lombard then turns to the option of resorting to tenseless predication and thus puts forward the following reading of (P):

(P3):

Everything that exists tenselessly exists now.Footnote 15

By the same token, he could have considered this interpretation of (E):

(E3):

There tenselessly are things that do not now exist.

Lombard argues that (P3) collapses into (P2), because either “tenselessly exists” is unintelligible, or it is equivalent to “existed, exists now or will exist,” inasmuch as the latter tells us what the former really means.Footnote 16 Similarly, he would probably agree that (E3) collapses into (E2). We find the same maneuver, even before Lombard’s paper, in the substantialist camp: Crisp (2004a, b) has also considered (P2) and (P3) as possible readings of (P) and also claimed that (P3) collapses into (P2). Presumably, we could add, he would similarly view (E3) as collapsing into (E2).Footnote 17

Clearly, the proposal of these collapses still appears to presuppose serious tensism, for it is based on the idea of reducing tenselessness to disjunctive tensedness. However, to take for granted serious tensism is problematic, because B-eternalists typically consider the use of a tenseless language as essential to state their ontological position. In their view, tensed claims do not commit to an essentially tensed reality inasmuch as they can be understood in a tenseless way, as we shall recall in more detail in Sect. 4 (Oaklander 2008, p. 5).Footnote 18 Thus, B-eternalists accept (E3) and not (E2). Moreover, even though, as eternalists, they reject (P3), they certainly recognize its meaningfulness qua thesis that stands in opposition to (E3), and not as a thesis that reduces to (P2). Thus, we need to avoid serious tensism and grant the legitimacy of tenseless predication in order to contemplate the opposition between (P3) and (E3). Now, it can be retorted here that this way of opposing the collapses in question presupposes the intelligibility of the tenseless language advocated by the B-eternalists, and for the deflationist this very intelligibility is problematic. Of course, if we simply took for granted the intelligibility of tenseless predication we would beg the question against the deflationist. However, in a final appendix we shall argue in favor of such intelligibility.

Among substantialists, there are, to be sure, those who explicitly advocate the use of tenseless predication in order to propose (P3) and (E3) as presentist and eternalist statements that can stand the triviality challenge. In addition to the above mentioned Oaklander (2008), two notable examples are Mozersky (2011) and Torrengo (2012). Unfortunately, we do not find in them a clear explanation of why, once tenseless predication is taken into account, the triviality challenge evaporates. This explanation is forthcoming, we think, only if the role of the quantifiers in the presentist and eternalist claims is properly appreciated (see Sect. 5 below). And here we come to another reason why serious tensism is troublesome. How should we understand the quantifiers in the presentist and eternalist claims? Crisp (2004a) argued that (P2) is not trivially false, by appealing to the idea that it involves a quantifier, “everything,” which is “unrestricted” and ranging over “our most inclusive domain of quantification,” or at least a quantifier restricted in such a way as to range over “the class of all things in time, which existed, exist now, or will exist” (Crisp 2004a, p. 18).Footnote 19 He reasons that it is not obvious that the domain in question includes Aristotle;Footnote 20 the presentist says it does not and the eternalist says it does, but it is not obvious who is right. However, in saying that (A) is trivially true and in conflict with (P2), we are presupposing the eternalist’s answer. We could add something similar about (E2). Lombard neglects Crisp’s paper and this is unfortunate, because Crisp is basically on the right track. But not completely though, because he fails to clarify whether this quantificational talk is tensed or tenseless. This lack of explicitness may mean that he takes quantifiers to be neither tensed, nor tenseless.Footnote 21 Be this as it may, the line that quantifiers are neither tensed nor tenseless has been explicitly taken some years later by Deasy (2017a), who cites Crisp, and claims that they are such, because they “are not verbs” (p. 381). Footnote 22 This line should not be welcome though, because, as we shall see in the following, the use of quantifiers involves predication, and, once we grant this, the predication in question could be taken to be either tensed or tenseless. Given serious tensism, this predication must be tensed (in the terminology of Ludlow (2004), this choice leads to what he calls very serious tensim). The price for this, as we shall argue in Sect. 5, is that one ends up being committed to a specific, tensed, temporal ontology, thereby begging the question against rival approaches. This of course makes the debate insubstantial in a trivial way.

Thus, substantialism requires tenseless predication and a most inclusive domain of quantification, which go hand in hand. If tenseless predication is assumed, there should be no deflationist worry. Yet, these notions keep being ignored or criticized, as we shall ascertain in the next section. And thus deflationist worries remain.

3 Recent attacks to tenseless predication and unrestricted quantifiers

According to Callender (2012, p. 74), “there is a very real threat that the answer to this question [whether the dispute in temporal ontology is substantial] is no” and, without considering any attempts by substantialists to support their position, except Sider (2006), he concludes that “the jury on triviality is still out” (p. 81). You may say that some substantialist efforts, such as those by Torrengo and Mozersky, were too recent for Callender to take notice of them in that paper. But we find basically the same verdict in Callender’s recent book (2017), where it is stated that the competitors in temporal ontology might be “notational variants” (2017, p. 294). To back up this claim, Callender refers to Callender (2000), Meyer (2013a), Savitt (2006) and Dorato (2006), and neglects the above mentioned attempts by Crisp, Oaklander, Torrengo, Mozersky, etc., to rescue substantialism by appealing to tenseless predication and unrestricted quantification. Similarly, Dorato (2018) maintains that temporal ontology may not be substantial, citing Savitt (2006), Dolev (2007) and Deng (2018) in support of this claim, and ignoring substantialist rejoinders in between Savitt’s and Dolev’s works and the recent paper by Deng.

Deng (2018, §3) tells us that the triviality challenge shows that, for the dispute to be substantive, “exists” must mean something other than “exists now” or “existed, exists now or will exist” and then she urges that “[t]he near consensus is that what it means is ‘tenseless existence’ or else existence simpliciter, i.e., existence full stop.” She then makes it clear, by referring to Mozersky (2011), that she understands tenseless existence in terms of an unrestricted existential quantifier: “Standard presentism, then, is the view that only things that are present exist, full stop. Even when the quantifier’s wings are stretched as wide as they can be, no non-present things (that are still temporal things) are caught by it (I take the metaphor from Mozersky 2011, p. 124).”Footnote 23 She then claims that this tenseless existence “stands in need of elucidation” (p. 4)Footnote 24 and goes on to examine three attempts to explain why the presentism/eternalism debate is substantial. She concludes that they offer no such elucidation. She considers Sider (2011), Stoneham (2009) and Wüthrich (2013). Sider indeed appeals to a tenseless existential quantifier and tells us that it allows us to say that presentists and eternalists disagree on whether or not, e.g., there tenselessly are dinosaurs, but in the end she does not fully grasp how this disagreement is to be understood in spite of Sider’s attempts. And as regards Stoneham and Wüthrich, she finds no help in them because they do not really try to elucidate tenseless existence; they rather try to avoid tenselessness, but then end up presupposing it.Footnote 25

Dolev (2018) goes beyond merely claiming that tenseless existence is still in need of elucidation. He actually tries to argue that tenseless existence and more generally tenselessness are inescapably unintelligible.Footnote 26 Let us see how. According to Dolev, the presentist and eternalist claims are unintelligible, since they are entangled in a circle: they presuppose the intelligibility of tenseless existence, which in turn requires the intelligibility of the claims themselves. This line against tenseless existence permeates Dolev’s earlier work (2007), but it is stated most pointedly in Dolev (2018, p. 6). This paper is a reply to Orilia (2014), who argued that Dolev (2007), in contrast to his efforts to supersede temporal ontology, implicitly commits himself to eternalism. According to Dolev (2007, ch. 5), what is present depends on the context: it could be the winning arrival of an athlete or a single basketball match in the Olympic games, but also the whole Olympic games or even a much longer long-lasting cosmic event. But then, Orilia has argued, the “ontological inventory,” i.e., the set of everything that exists, includes the events that are typically acknowledged by the eternalist, e.g., the first winning arrival in the first day of the games, and then the second winning arrival, etc.

In his reply, Dolev urged that Orilia begs the question, because the Quinean notion of ontological inventory on which he relies presupposes a tenseless predication of existence and thus the intelligibility of a tenseless language, which Dolev rejects (2018, §3).Footnote 27 According to Dolev, tenseless language is no part of ordinary language and, therefore, is not something that we already understand on the basis of our ordinary linguistic competence. Consequently, the meaning of a tenseless predication of existence must be explained in some way, and, as just noted, this cannot be done, if not circularly, by appealing to the ontological inventory. Dolev considers the idea that tenseless predication of existence be introduced as a primitive in the technical jargon of philosophy. After all, he admits, primitive terms are introduced in scientific theorizing, and one could then think that an analogous move can be done in philosophy. But Dolev rejects this option, for the following reasons. Novel scientific terms draw their meaning from the roles they play within scientific theories in which they occur, and these theories are in turn supported experimentally. Contrariwise, in philosophy, or at least in temporal ontology, there is no experimental support and thus things are different: “Here too the new terms rely on the theory they figure in for their meanings, but the theory’s content is derived from the meaning the terms already have.” There is, therefore, again, a problem of circularity. And the case of tenseless predication of existence is no exception: “Say that, like me, you do not understand the tenseless use of ‘Exist’. Could acquainting myself with eternalism help? Not if to understand this theory I already need to understand tenseless ‘Existence’.” (Dolev 2018, §3)

Dolev (2018, §3) provides a further argument for taking the (tenseless) existence attributions of temporal ontology to be unintelligible: the intelligibility of such attributions presupposes a Quinean, univocal and context- or domain-independent notion of existence, on the basis of which one can speak of an ontological inventory that comprises all that exists; and yet this notion of existence is not available, since an existence attribution such as “X exists” is not meaningful unless a context or domain is specified.Footnote 28 Here Dolev relies on Scanlon’s (2014) notion of “domain” (Dolev seems to use at this juncture “context” as equivalent to “domain”). A domain is for Scanlon a realm or sector of our understanding of reality, e.g., mathematics, set theory, science, practical reasoning, etc. Domains (which may overlap with each other) are characterized and distinguished by (1) the concepts they involve, e.g., number, set, physical object, morally right action, etc., (2) the sort of claims they involve, including existential statements, and (3) the standards for making these claims (see Scanlon 2014, pp. 19–20). Dolev invokes the fact that meaning is always determined, at least partially, by use, and then argues that, in ordinary as well as in scientific language, the distinctness of the domains “is mirrored by a plurality of uses and thus of meanings of ‘exist’, and that no domain-independent meaning of ‘exist’, no ‘common denominator’ that is shared by the plurality of uses of this word and ties them to each other, can be distilled from the many domain dependent uses of it” (Dolev 2018, §3).Footnote 29

In sum, according to these new trends, tenseless predication, tenseless existence and unrestricted quantifiers with a corresponding all-encompassing domain are in bad shape. In the next section, we shall argue that there is no reason to be so pessimistic about them. We shall first defend tenseless predication and then turn to quantification and existence. Since quantification involves predication, it will be crucial to rely on the previous vindication of tenseless predication in order to grant that the unrestricted quantifiers invoked by the substantialists can be predicated tenselessly, and in order to make sense of tenseless existence.

4 General clarification of tenseless predication and tenseless existence

It seems then that deflationists do not doubt that we understand tensed predication; they admit that it is part of natural language and that we commonly use it. In contrast, they, or at least some of them, do not find tenseless predication in natural language and claim they do not understand the attempts by philosophers to introduce it. It is not so obvious, however, that natural language contains no tenseless predication. At the very least one should say that it is an empirical issue whether it does or does not, and that there is no clear verdict against the first horn of the dilemma. We shall briefly consider this issue in the appendix. But even if we assume that tenseless predication is extraneous to everyday English and only belongs to the technical language of philosophy, it does not follow that it cannot be understood.

Dolev urges that we cannot understand it, because in order to grasp it we must first grasp eternalism and in order to grasp eternalism we should first grasp tenselessness, so that we are trapped in a circle that precludes understanding. Here one may grant that in providing a definition one should avoid circularity and also admit that one cannot resort to the very theses of eternalism or presentism to define without circularity the tenseless reading of “exist.” Nevertheless, it is still possible that there is here, in the absence of a definition, a circle that favors, rather than precludes, understanding. For it may well happen that understanding the crucial issues of temporal ontology and understanding tenseless predication proceed pari passu: one could come to grasp tenseless predication by virtue of contemplating the contrast between the theses that presuppose it, in particular presentism and eternalism.Footnote 30 If one insisted that nothing like this could be true, because the introduction of tenseless predication in the technical jargon of philosophy is not experimentally supported, it could be retorted that this argumentative line leads to an implausible overgeneralization, since it suggests that all meaningful language is either ordinary language or is subject to some sort of verificationist criterion of meaning. If this were correct, it would be impossible to introduce new primitive terms not only in philosophy, but in all areas of inquiries where theories are not experimentally supported; in particular logic and mathematics, but perhaps also highly theoretical parts of human sciences such as political science and sociology.Footnote 31 Going back to philosophy and in particular to our specific concern here, namely tenselessness, the following could be added. Tenseless predication is presupposed by an atemporalistic conception of abstract entities or God. Some philosophers believe that abstract entities, e.g., numbers and sets, or God, are timeless or atemporal, i.e., they exist and have properties, but not in time. One may think this is irrelevant precisely because these entities are not temporal entities. But the point is that, since they are not temporal, it is wrong to say that they presently exist or presently have their properties; they exist or have their properties tenselessly. Thus, those who reject the intelligibility of tenseless predication must also reject the intelligibility of viewing abstract entities and God as timeless (and endorse, if they admit the existence of such entities, an omnitemporalistic conception of them).

Be this as it may, tenseless predication can be explained non-circularly, without relying on a previous understanding of the notion of ontological inventory or of the metaphysical thesis of eternalism (or timeless entities, for that matter), if one grants, as deflationists do, that tensed predication is understood as part of ordinary language: even if there is no tenseless predication in ordinary English, we can obtain it by abstracting from tense in tensed predication, i.e., we may say, by detensing. More specifically, tenseless predication can be understood as the result of detensing present-tensed predication. Thus, tenseless predication is what we are left with, if we strip present-tensed predication of its tense. Since of course there is predication when a predicate is predicated, we can put matters more concretely in terms of predicates: a tenseless predicate is a predicate that results from a present-tensed predicate by depriving it of tense. Detractors of tenselessness such as Deng and Dolev might reply that they do not understand how it is possible to deprive a present-tensed predicate of tense or that they fail to grasp what would remain after this deprivation. However, this does not seem right: we surely have a grasp of present-tensed predication; we also understand what tense is, i.e., what we are abstracting from; hence, there shouldn’t be a problem in understanding what detensing present-tensed predication consists in, and what its results is, i.e., tenseless predication. If one is still unconvinced, a comparison with placelessness may aid understanding.Footnote 32 It may be objected that to resort to this is a conceptual error, because time and space should not be confused. However, we are proposing no such error but only an analogy: even if ordinary English predication is thoroughly tensed, it can hardly be denied that placelessness is a very common analogue of tenselessness. Tenselessness is a kind of lack of semantic information regarding the instantiation of the property expressed by a predicate; the missing information is of course temporal. Now, typically, ordinary (tensed) predication fails to express spatial information about the instantiation. When we say that a certain animal is a dog, the predicate “is a dog” does not convey any spatial information about the instantiation of being a dog. Of course, the instantiation is somewhere, but the predicate gives us no indication about it. In a similar way, if “is a dog” is understood as tenseless, it does not convey any temporal information about the instantiation of being a dog; the instantiation is “somewhen,” we may say, but the predicate does not specify it. We could say that using tenseless predication to talk about temporal entities is to a certain extent analogous to using the ordinary “placeless” predication to talk about spatial entities.Footnote 33

Let us now turn to quantification. As noted, Crisp (2004b) and, more explicitly, Deasy (2017a), deny that tensedness or tenselessness apply to quantifiers. Let us see how Deasy (2017a, p. 381) motivates this view:

Why think the quantifiers have ‘tensed’ or ‘tenseless’ interpretations in the first place? According to Rini and Cresswell (2012, 65), the idea that the quantifiers are either ‘tensed’ or ‘tenseless’ is plausibly based on the idea that the quantifiers are verbs, so that (for example) expressions of the form ‘∃’ must be read as either ‘there is now an x such that α’ (i.e. as ‘tensed’) or ‘there is, was, or will be an x such that α’ (i.e. as ‘tenseless’). However, as Barcan (1962) points out, the quantifiers are not verbs, they are quantifiers: expressions of the form ‘∃’ can simply be read ‘for some x, α’, in which the tense (if any) is located entirely in α, and expressions of the form ‘∀’ can be read as ‘for all x, α’, in which the tense (if any) is located entirely in α. Therefore there is no good reason to think the quantifiers have either reading.

Setting aside the claim that tenselessness amounts to disjunctive tensedness (which we discuss elsewhere in this paper), the relevant point here is that the existential and the universal quantifiers simply are “for some x,” and “for all x,” and thus, as so understood, do not involve predication. This way of looking at the quantifiers may be traced back to the way in which Quine (1981, §12) explains the meaning of the variable binding quantifiers of symbolic logic by treating variables as anaphoric pronouns, while passing over the nature of the syntactic link between a quantifier with its associated variable and the open sentence (“matrix” in Quine’s terminology) to which the quantifier and the variable are prefixed. In contrast, Frege, whom Quine refers to as the progenitor of these now current quantifiers (p. 71), and then Russell, explicitly tell us (as we shall see) that there is a predication there. Thus, Quine explains (p. 68) that “(x)(x = x)” should be understood as “whatever you may select, it = it,” which in turn is a convenient manner of putting the more familiar “everything is identical to itself.” But he does not tell us how we should understand the link between “(x),” or “whatever you may select,” or “everything,” or “for all x,” for that matter, and the open sentence or predicate that follows. We are simply told that “everything” cannot be treated as a subject term such as “9” in “9 is less than, equal to, or greater than 0.” (In making this example, Quine focuses on the less generic “every number,” but of course the point is meant to be general.) Now, that there is a difference here is certainly correct, but in addition one should also note that the connection between the quantifier and the open sentence or predicate that follows is no mere juxtaposition, even when it is not marked by a verb because one uses a locution such as “for all x;” the obvious thing to say, we think, is that this connection is predication. Frege and Russell go on to say, in essence, that the difference in question is this: in one case the quantifier is predicated of a predicate, “is identical to itself,” whereas in the other case a predicate, “is less than, equal to, or greater than 0,” is predicated of “9.” We find this convincing and we shall thus stick to this in the following, but, independently of this point, what crucially matters for our present concerns is the acknowledgment of a predication, and thus of the issue of the tensed or tenseless nature of the predication in question.

According to Frege, quantifiers, qua predicates of predicates, stand for higher-level concepts that apply to lower-level ones, whereas Russell would rather speak in terms of propositional functions. Going beyond the terminological and ontological details that differentiate the two great masters, we find it congenial to view the existential and universal quantifiers as expressing properties of properties such as being instantiated or being exemplified, and being universal, respectively; which we take to be predicable of more garden-variety properties such as being a table, stone, dog or dinosaur. And accordingly, we propose to use the predicates “is instantiated” and “is universal,” as appropriate variants of “for some x,” “for all x,” and the like. Thus, when we say that for all x, x is a table, or that everything is a table, we are saying that the property of being a table is universal. Similarly, in saying that for some x, x is a table, or that something is a table, we are saying that being a table is instantiated. The nominalistically-oriented philosopher may simply take this as a mere façon de parler. Thus, in particular, our appeal to being instantiated and being universal as properties of properties in our discussion of the triviality argument should not be taken to imply that presentists and eternalists must be committed to properties and thus cannot be nominalists, for of course the whole discussion can be rephrased in terms of predicates. What matters, let us emphasize it again, is that, in using the quantifiers, predication is involved, so that the issue of the tensedness or tenselessness of the quantification in question arises. And the copula present in the locutions “is instantiated” and “is universal” has the virtue of making this crystal clear. Thus, for example, that F is instantiated, or is universal, can be understood either as F is presently instantiated, or is presently universal; or F is tenselessly instantiated, or is tenselessly universal.Footnote 34 What is the difference? If we say that being F is presently universal, we can infer from it that a is F only if we take “a” to refer to a presently existing object, but there is no such restriction if we say that F is tenselessly universal. Similarly, we can infer from a is F that being F is presently instantiated only if we take “a” to refer to a presently existing object, but there is no such restriction if we infer that being F is tenselessly instantiated. This makes a difference, depending on whether you are eternalist or presentist, since for the presentist, if “a” refers at all, it must refer to a present object; not so for the eternalist, according to whom “a” may refer to a non-present object. We shall see this difference at play in discussing the triviality objection.

Consider existence now. Following Frege and Russell, as is well known, general existential claims such as “tables exist,” “there exist tables” or “there are tables” are all equivalent and we can capture what they say by appealing to the existential quantifier: ∃x x is a table. And thus, in the light of what we said above, these claims can be taken to mean that the property of being a table is instantiated, so that existence turns out to be a property of properties expressed by the existential quantifier; second-order existence, we may say, i.e., being instantiated (or exemplified). However, following Quine (1960, §37), we can also say that there is a first-order property of existence, namely the absolutely general or trivial property of being identical to something, expressible by this open formula: ∃y y = x. Given this, saying that x tenselessly exists amounts to saying that the following property is tenselessly exemplified: being identical to x. Alternatively, we may put it in terms of an overall domain, ontological inventory or all-encompassing Master Class, the class U of self-identical things. Once such a class is assumed, we may say that to tenselessly exist is to be a member of U, but notice that tenselessness is deeply involved in such a claim; we are saying that a thing tenselessly exists if and only if this thing is tenselessly a member of U, and U in turn is defined as the class α such that a thing x tenselessly belongs to α if and only if x is tenselessly identical to x. Thus, we agree with Dolev when he claims, as we saw above, that one cannot appeal to the notion of an ontological inventory in order to define tenselessness. We differ from him, however, in taking tenselessness to be intelligible. And, once this intelligibility is granted, as we argued it should be, talking of an overall domain, ontological inventory or Master Class is legitimate, and may well aid understanding and imagination; of course, it does not lead to a definition of tenselessness, but this should not be sought, if this notion is independently granted.

Let us now dwell on the difference between predicating existence tensedly and tenselessly. We all agree that Trump is presently a president and thus, obviously, that he presently exists. Hence, there presently is a thing such that this thing is presently a president, i.e., being a president is presently instantiated. Both presentists and eternalists will agree on this. We also agree that Caesar crossed the Rubicon, and an eternalist may infer therefrom that there is a thing, or there is a member of the ontological inventory, such that this thing crossed the Rubicon. Here, second-order existence is predicated tenselessly of the property of having crossed the Rubicon. The eternalist is not saying that there is presently a thing such that this thing crossed the Rubicon; she is rather saying that there is tenselessly a thing, or there is tenselessly a member of the ontological inventory, such that this thing, or member, crossed the Rubicon. The presentist will of course deny that such a claim may be inferred from the truth that Caesar crossed the Rubicon. Or suppose that it is at time t that Caesar crossed the Rubicon. Then, an eternalist may claim that at t Caesar crosses, tenselessly, the Rubicon, and from this that there is, tenselessly, a thing such that at t this thing crosses, tenselessly, the Rubicon. This eternalist will not however infer that there is, presently, a thing such that at t this thing crosses, tenselessly, the Rubicon.Footnote 35 We may also predicate tenselessly the trivial first-order property of existence. The eternalist may further say, for example, that, since Caesar crosses the Rubicon at t, obviously at t Caesar tenselessly exists. Or she may say that there is tenselessly a thing such that this thing tenselessly exists and is also such that, at t, it tenselessly crosses the Rubicon.

It should not be forgotten that along with the rather standard Frege-Russell-Quine tradition, there is also the minoritarian Meinongian tradition, according to which there is a non-trivial first-order monadic property of existence, which some objects, the non-existents, may fail to have: Donald Trump exists, whereas the golden mountain does not. In this framework “there is an F” and “there exists an F” are not equivalent. For example, there is a golden mountain, but it fails to exist and thus it is not the case that there exists a golden mountain. The standard view is typically presupposed in temporal ontology and here we take it for granted, but for present concerns nothing hinges on whether or not we go Meinongian. From a Meinongian perspective, we simply have to make sure that we speak in terms of this non-trivial notion of existence, call it m-existence. Thus the Meinongian presentist will claim that all that tenselessly m-exists presently m-exists, and the Meinongian eternalist will rebut that there tenselessly are things that tenselessly m-exist and yet do not presently m-exist.

It is important to note here that the characterization of tenselessness that we have provided does not imply that there cannot be change in what there is tenselessly or more generally in the truth value of tenseless truth-bearers. To be sure this assumption is often made, presumably as a by-product of the fact that those who typically resort to a tenseless language are B-theorists. Indeed, from a B-theoretical point of view, there is no change in what there is tenselessly and in the truth value of tenseless truth-bearers. Thus, for example, “there are tenselessly dinosaurs” is true now, as there are presently no dinosaurs, just as it was true long ago when there were dinosaurs. However, there is no reason why presentists or other A-theorists should refrain from speaking tenselessly, and actually there are good reasons for them to do that; the very statement of presentism, we are arguing in this paper, requires a mixture of tenseless and tensed language. And, from the presentist perspective, there can be this sort of change. For example, a presentist may say that “there are tenselessly dinosaurs” is now false, but it was true long ago, when there were dinosaurs and “there are presently dinosaurs” was also true. Thus, eternalists and presentists disagree on what there tenselessly is, since according to the latter, but not according to the former, what exists tenselessly is subject to change.

Let us now consider Dolev’s point about the allegedly polyvocal and domain-dependent nature of existence attributions. In a nutshell, what Dolev seems to be saying is that in different domains we speak of irreducibly different things and thus, depending on the domain, when we claim that things in that domain exist, we use “exist” in different ways, so that there is no domain-independent meaning of “exist,” which accordingly has a plurality of meanings.Footnote 36 In reply, let us note first of all that it is far from obvious that the irreducible plurality of things, which should of course be granted, corresponds to a plurality of uses, and hence of meanings, of “exist.” We may say both of physical objects and of morally right actions that they exist, and understand this in terms of the standard, tenselessly used, existential quantifier: there are, or exist, physical objects and there are, or exist, morally right actions, and if a is a physical object or a morally right action, there is, or exists, something to which a is identical to. Physical objects and morally right actions are, no doubt, very different sorts of things, but why should we infer from this that we have used “exist” in different senses? By the same token, we should infer from the diversity of a whale and a mouse that we use “mammal” with different meanings when we say that both the whale and the mouse are mammals.Footnote 37 But even if it were true that the irreducible plurality of entities gave rise to different meanings of “exist,” say, exist1, exist2, exist3, etc., we could still assume that there is also a disjunctive reading of “exist:” exist1 or exist2 or exist3 or…, and take this reading to be at play in temporal ontology. Thus, for example, the presentist would be saying that all the things that tenselessly exist1 or tenselessly exist2 or,… are such that they presently exist1, if tenselessly existing1, and they presently exist2, if tenselessly existing2 and… And similarly the eternalist would be saying that there are things that tenselessly exist1 and do not presently exist1 and things that tenselessly exist2 and do not presently exist2 and… After all, Scanlon himself (2014, p. 23) admits that “we can form a coherent idea of a domain concerned with the general idea of existence that applies to everything we are committed to quantifying over in a range of particular domains.” The only problem he sees in it is a lack of “thickness” (Scanlon 2014, p. 23). By this he means that this general notion of existence does not yield new standards for making existence claims in addition to those of the specific domains. But this is as it should be, given the all-encompassing character of the general notion of existence.

Thus, tenseless predication seems to make perfect sense and, to further certify this, it is interesting to see that Dolev himself implicitly makes use of it. Dolev (2018) complains that Orilia classifies him as eternalist simply because he speaks of past and future events and begs the question against him by taking for granted that there is a general ontological inventory and thus tenseless predication and tenseless attribution of existence. However, Orilia more specifically relies on Dolev’s (2007) talking of past and future events as parts of a temporally extended event, which, given the appropriate context, is taken to be present. According to Dolev (2007), the present tense or “now” allow us to pick up, depending on the context, a more or less temporally extended present event. This contextual account of presentness surfaces again in Dolev’s reply (2018), when he considers the case of his “[h]aving coffee with Mark,” thereby picking up “a present event which has parts that are past or future—chatting before the coffee arrives, ordering another scone, and so on” (Dolev 2018, §2). Since, according to Dolev, there is no tenseless predication, it would be wrong to say that he meant to appeal to it in his description of this example. Yet, it seems to us that this description must involve tenseless predication for it to make sense. Let us see why. Call the present event in question e. Since we are assuming that we are in a context in which e as a whole is present, we can hardly say that e has presently past or future parts. Consider the parts mentioned by Dolev: a chatting, e1, a coffee arrival, e2, a scone ordering, e3. For one of them to be past or future it must be occurring either before or after now. However, by hypothesis it is e as a whole that occupies the now in question, and neither e1, nor e2, nor e3 are before or after e, as all of them are comprised in it. We should certainly agree, however, that these parts are ordered by the earlier/later relation and only in this sense we can speak of them as past or future: e1 is earlier than e2, which is earlier than e3, so that e1 is past with respect to e2, which in turn is future with respect to e1, and similarly for e2 and e3. And for this to make sense the predication must be tenseless: it is not the case that e1 is presently before e2 or that e2 is presently before e3, for what is presently occurring, according to Dolev, is e as whole; it is rather the case, then, that e1 is tenselessly earlier than e2, which is tenselessly earlier than e3.

5 A full reply to the triviality challenge

Let us now go back to the triviality challenge. In Lombard’s formulation, on which we shall dwell in the first part of this section, the objection unfolds by presupposing serious tensism. It is instructive to see that, because of this presupposition, the objection, when carefully analyzed, involves a commitment to a specific tensed ontology and “proves” the insubstantiality of the debate in a trivial way, by begging the question against other ontologies. Accordingly, the objection, as so understood, cannot be used to support deflationism. This result is independent from the defense of tenselessness that we put forward in the previous section, and thus we may hope that even the obstinate serious tenser who did not find such a defense compelling could see here reasons in favor of substantialism. However, once tenselessness is admitted, as we think it should be, a full vindication of substantialism requires checking that, with tenseless predication available, the triviality objection does not still go through. In the second part of this section we shall then move to this task.

Let us focus with a logical microscope on (P2) and (E2). Consider the former first. There is an “everything” that hides a predication. We can bring it to light by using the “is universal” locution so as to put (P2) as follows:

(P2ʹ):

being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now is universal.Footnote 38

Now the issue of interpreting the “is” of “is universal” arises. Insofar as the deflationist is assuming serious tensism, as Lombard at least initially does, this interpretation should be tensed. This worry is raised by Ludlow (2004) in his reply to Crisp (2004a), who, as noted, appeals to unrestricted quantifiers to counter the triviality challenge.Footnote 39 Crisp (2004b, p. 42) counter-replied that, if one wants tensed quantifiers, (P) can be read thus: “For every past, present, or future thing x, if x existed, exists, or will exist, then x is a present thing or, more simply,… Every past, present, or future thing is a present thing.” (He then claims that both these readings are non-trivial and thus escape the triviality challenge.) These readings however operate on the property of which universality is predicated and tell us nothing about how, tensedly or tenselessly, universality is predicated of this property. For example, in Crisp’s first proposal universality is predicated of this property: being a thing such that, if this thing is past or present or future, then it presently exists, provided it existed, exists now, or will exist. But is it predicated tensedly or tenselessly? We are not told. However, there is no need to fuss with the property of which universality is predicated. What is needed is that universality be predicated tensedly, if serious tensism is assumed. At the same time, the serious tenser, qua deflationist, needs a universally quantified assertion with respect to which (A), i.e. the claim that Aristotle did, but does not now exist, works as a counterexample. In other words, the deflationist must be able to instantiate from the universal quantifier of the universally quantified assertion to Aristotle and infer

(A*):

if Aristotle existed, or exists now or will exist, then Aristotle exists now,

in order to then claim that (A*) is in conflict with (A), i.e., that Aristotle existed but does not exist now. But whatever tensed interpretation of “is universal” is chosen by the deflationist, this result can hardly be achieved, unless, as anticipated, we presuppose a very specific and controversial view in temporal ontology. We shall see this in a moment, but let us first pause to notice that this point is overlooked not only by Lombard and Crisp, but also by another substantialist such a Mozersky (2011), when he concedes, in practice, that (P2′) is in conflict with (A), without questioning the deflationist’s right to obtain (A*) without tenseless predication available. Let us now see what the options for the deflationist serious tenser are.

Suppose the “is” is understood as present-tensed:

(P2ʹa):

being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now is presently universal.

As remarked in Sect. 4, what we can infer from the fact that a certain property, P, is presently universal, is that the Eiffel tower presently has it, Trump presently has it, and so on, as long we name presently existing objects; we cannot infer, e.g., that Aristotle also presently has property P. Thus, in particular, we may infer from (P2ʹa) that, e.g., Trump has now the property being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now, and thus claim that if Trump existed, or exists now or will exist, then Trump exists now. But we may not infer that Aristotle has now that property and thus claim (A*).

Suppose then that the “is” of “is universal” is understood as disjunctively tensed:

(P2ʹb):

being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now was universal, or is now universal or will be universal.

We can instantiate to Aristotle at most from the first disjunct of (P2ʹb).Footnote 40 However, since such a disjunct is past-tensed, presumably all that we can infer in this way from it is not (A*), but rather a past-tensed version of (A*):

(A**):

it was the case that if Aristotle existed, or presently exists or will exist, then Aristotle presently exists.

But it is simply (A*), not its past-tensed version (A**), that we need in order to license the claim that (A) is a counterexample to (P): (A) contradicts (A*), not (A**). In sum, even if we could rule out the second and third disjuncts of (P2ʹb), which we can’t, with this interpretation of “is universal” the triviality objection does not go through.

Finally, the deflationist could appeal to a conjunctively tensed reading:

(P2ʹc):

being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now was universal, and is now universal and will be universal.

In this case the proposition wherefrom we can perhaps instantiate to Aristotle, namely that being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now was universal, is a conjunct, rather than a disjunct. This is an advantage, because we can immediately infer it from (P2ʹc). But, as we already saw, all we can infer from it is (A**) and not what the deflationist needs, i.e. (A*).

Let us move now to the controversial ontological position hidden behind the triviality objection. It is a position that Lombard, as we shall now see, indeed appears to accept. Lombard considers the notion of a most inclusive domain of quantification, but he thinks he can appeal to it with only a tensed language available. This surfaces in his discussion of Zimmerman’s (1998) proposal to define presentism in terms of a “largest class of all real things.” At that juncture Lombard considers “is now real” as a reading of “tenselessly exists,” where in turn, “is now real” is interpreted as “is now a member of the Master Class.” The term “Master Class” is Lombard’s favorite label for Zimmerman’s largest class of real things, or, we may say, Crisp’s most inclusive domain; or, we may also say, the ontological inventory. Something is now a member of the Master Class, we are told, if and only if this something either existed or exists now or will exist, or would exist if there were no times. The latter disjunct is, in Lombard’s terminology, the condition for being an abstract object and presumably must be understood as tenseless (let us pass this); since presentism and eternalism should not be understood as theses regarding abstract objects, this may be ignored.Footnote 41 In sum, Lombard concedes that there is now a Master Class, and that the entities that are now members of this class are the entities that are now real, i.e. are such that they either existed or exist now or will exist. In admitting this, Lombard emphasizes that to be real is different from existing: Aristotle and Clinton are both real (now), in that the former existed and the latter exists now, whereas Superman is not real (now) in that he neither existed, nor exists now, nor will exist. In the light of this, then Lombard also claims that Aristotle, qua member now of the Master class and thus now real, “can be the value of unrestricted quantification… can be referred to (indeed is now being referred to by me [= Lombard], and be the subject of present-tensed predications (though he cannot now have any property that implies current existence)” (Lombard 2010, p. 60). Presumably, if one takes this stand, one can then infer from (P2ʹa) that, (now) if Aristotle existed, or exists now or will exist, then Aristotle exists now. But let us carefully see what this option involves. Lombard is seemingly ruling out that Aristotle is now a philosopher, or that Aristotle is now lecturing on metaphysics, or that he is now sleeping, or now awake, or now sitting, or now standing; since being a philosopher, etc. are all properties that imply current existence. But he is not ruling out that Aristotle is now a value of unrestricted quantification, that is now such that Lombard refers to him, that he is now such that he was a philosopher and lectured on metaphysics, since all this is compatible with Aristotle’s not existing now. This is really to say that there is now a thing such that Aristotle is now identical to this thing, i.e. that now ∃y now y = Aristotle. According to the standard conception of existence reviewed above, to exist is to be identical to something, and thus to exist now is now to be identical to something, or more precisely now to be now identical to something, a property expressible with the open formula “now ∃y now y = x.” However, Lombard tells us that this is only to be real now and that this differs from existing now. He is then diverging from the standard conception of existence. This may be only a terminological issue: Lombard is using “is real” in the way in which “exists” is used in the standard conception. But there is a more serious and substantial issue. According to Lombard, there is now a y such that now y = Aristotle and now Lombard refers to y and y existed and y was lecturing on metaphysics and y is not now lecturing on metaphysics. What kind of doctrine is it? It appears to be the thesis defended by Williamson (2002), according to which merely past objects such as Aristotle do not go out of existence, as the presentist has it, nor do they just exist at past times, but exist now as “ex-concrete” objects, i.e. objects that were concrete in the past, and thus occupied space and had properties such as sitting or lecturing on metaphysics, but are not now concrete and thus cannot have now such properties; they can now have only properties such as having lectured on metaphysics or being referred to by Lombard. There is a difference in terminology of course. Lombard would say that these objects are now real, but all the properties they now have do not imply “current existence” and thus these objects do not now exist. Williamson would rather say that they now exist, but are not now concrete, as all the properties they now have fail to imply concreteness. But apart from the terminological differences, they are committed to the same ontological view. An interesting but far from obvious view, which has been taken to be a form of eternalism (see Zimmerman 2008, §3), but, if such, it is certainly not the only form of eternalism.Footnote 42 According to a more standard eternalist view, there are tenseless propositions such as that Aristotle is a philosopher at a certain past time t, and that Lombard qua existing at t, the time of utterance, refers to Aristotle, qua existing at a certain past time (Torrengo 2010, § IV), which do not imply that there is now an entity which is Aristotle, which is now such that he was a philosopher and he is now such that Lombard now refers to him. Once the Williamsonian eternalism that Lombard seems to espouse is taken for granted, it makes sense to say that (A*) follows from (P2ʹa), for, given this sort of eternalism, Aristotle (qua ex-concrete) is among the present entities. Accordingly, from this perspective, one can say that presentism is contradicted by (A). But no charge of triviality against presentism can be levelled, because it is not obvious that (A*) follows from (P2ʹa): it does only after assuming a very specific view in temporal ontology, thereby begging the question against other views, including presentism and versions of eternalism.Footnote 43

Consider (E2) now. According to Lombard, it is obviously true in the light of (A). How can this be? Presumably we must be able to take (A) as obviously true and then take (E2) as also true qua derived from (A) in an obvious way. Let us see whether this is possible. (E2) is a disjunction of three claims:

(E2i):

there were things that do not now exist;

(E2ii):

there are now things that do not now exist;

(E2iii):

there will be things that do not now exist.

For (E2) to be true, as the deflationist claims, at least one of these disjuncts must be true. (E2ii) is (E1), which Lombard took to be obviously false. We may then choose either (E2i) or (E2iii). Let us consider, for simplicity’s sake, only (E2i), since what we shall say about it could be repeated mutatis mutandis for (E2iii). How should we interpret (E2i)? It seems to involve an existential quantifier taking wide scope over the past-tensed “were things” and the present-tensed “do not now exist.” In other words, (E2i) is telling us that the following conjunctive property is instantiated: having been a thing (or having existed) and not existing now. But now we must interpret “is instantiated.” Given serious tensism, it must mean “is now instantiated” and thus (E2i) should mean that now there exists a thing such that it existed and does not now exist.Footnote 44 This is contradictory, unless we read “exist” in two different ways by a recourse to the controversial ontological position taken for granted by Lombard, which we connected to Williamsonian eternalism. That is, we read (E2i) as either: now there is a real thing such that it existed and does not now exist; or as: now there exists a thing such that it existed and it is not now concrete. If we assume this ontological standpoint, we can in turn understand (A) as true and as a logical ground for the truth of (E2i), because “Aristotle” is taken to be a referring term whose referent is now real but not now existent, or now existent but not now concrete. But since this ontological position is controversial, we cannot take (E2) to be obviously true.

In sum, given serious tensism, in order to make the inferences that the triviality objection appears to require, one needs a commitment to Williamsonian eternalism or something like that, and then the objection goes through, so to speak, only by begging the question against other positions.

Let us now see what happens once tenselessness enters the picture. We can now interpret (P2ʹ) as follows:

(P2ʹd):

being such that if it existed, or exists now or will exist, then it exists now is tenselessly universal.Footnote 45

Now any eternalist, not just the Williamsonian eternalist, can infer from (P2ʹd) that, if Aristotle existed, or exists now or will exist, then Aristotle exists now. And then, since the eternalist will take this to be in conflict with (A), she will consider (P2ʹd) false. But in order to argue that (P2ʹd) is not only false, but obviously false, we must also admit that the inferential move performed by the eternalist in instantiating to Aristotle is trivial. And this is far from obvious, because this move presupposes that “Aristotle” has, tenselessly, a referent, which is fine for the eternalist, but begs the question against the presentist.Footnote 46 This is at bottom, we think, what Crisp (2004a) is proposing when he tells us that the universal quantifier of (P2) is unrestricted, so that it ranges over “the class of all things in time, which existed, exist now, or will exist,” and not just over present things, although it is not obvious that this class includes Aristotle. But in putting things à la Crisp we fail to appreciate that tenseless predication is involved, and so we find Deasy (2017a) explicitly claiming that quantifiers are neither tensed nor tenseless. In contrast, (P2ʹd) has the virtue of letting us see clearly how tenselessness is at play in the formulation of presentism. Of course, once tenseles predication is admitted, the substantialist can also resort to (P3) as expression of presentism, or, more precisely, to:

(P3ʹ):

being such that if it tenselessly exists, then it exists now is tenselessly universal.

This is not trivial, for the same reasons that make (P2ʹd) non-trivial.

The presentist must of course agree with the eternalist that “Aristotle existed” and “Aristotle does not now exist” are true, but she can interpret them in such a way that their truth is compatible with the truth of (P2ʹd). For example, she can interpret the past tense as involving a Priorean past-tense operator and proper names to be definite descriptions in disguise. Then, assuming the Russellian analysis of definite descriptions, “Aristotle existed” is interpreted as “it was the case that there is exactly an A,” where “A” is a predicate corresponding to the proper name “Aristotle.”Footnote 47 Similarly, “Aristotle does not now exist” means “it is not the case that there is presently exactly an A.” And the truth of these claims is compatible with the truth of (P2ʹd). There would not be such a compatibility if we could infer from (P2ʹd) that, if it was the case that there is exactly an A, or it is now the case that there is exactly an A or it will be the case that there is exactly an A, then presently there is exactly an A. But there is no way to infer this from (P2ʹd).Footnote 48

As regards (E2), we can now take “is instantiated” to mean “is tenselessly instantiated” so as to take (E2i) above to mean that there is, tenselessly, a thing such that it existed and does not now exist. We can infer this in an obvious way from (A), by existential generalization, if we in turn interpret (A) as involving a term, “Aristotle,” that has tenselessly a referent. But (A), as so interpreted, is not obviously true, for its truth appears to require eternalism. The presentist will agree that Aristotle existed and does not exist now, but, as noted, she will take it to mean that it was the case that there is exactly an A, and that it is presently not the case that there is exactly an A.Footnote 49 Of course, with tenseless predication available, the substantialist can resort to (E3) rather than to (E2); and (E3) does not lead to triviality just like (E2).

6 Conclusion

In recent years deflationists about temporal ontology have argued that the presentism/eternalism dispute is not substantial. Denying or downplaying the meaningfulness of tenseless language and wielding the so-called triviality objection have been their main argumentative tools. Substantialists about temporal ontology have opposed this deflationist trend, mainly by bringing to the fore tenselessness or unrestricted quantification in an attempt to resist the triviality objection. Despite their efforts, there has been in the past few years a new wave of deflationism, wherein the triviality objection and qualms about the legitimacy of tenselessness and unrestricted quantification still loom large. We have reacted to this new wave and joined the substantialist camp, by providing a new clarification of tenseless predication, unrestricted quantifiers and their role in rescuing substantialism from the triviality objection. Since our proposal does not involve taking a stand in favor of any of the contenders in temporal ontology, it will not lead to a step forward in the resolution of the dispute, which as a matter of fact may well be perennial. We hope, however, that it will contribute to eradicate worries about its substantiality.