Dan Zahavi argues that “the flowing self-manifestation of consciousness… does not merely concern the elapsing phases, but takes its point of departure in an immediate impressional self-manifestation.”Footnote 1 This entails that:

  1. 1.

    A conscious life’s consciousness of itself is not produced through its retentional (nor apparently, its protentional) grasp of itself, but rather, is “intrinsic”Footnote 2 to the current experience.

    And yet:

  2. 2.

    If this life’s “flowing self-manifestation” or time-constituting consciousness of itself is indeed “intrinsic” to each and every one of its moments and in no way comes to a moment of experiencing from without, then it becomes difficult to imagine that consciousness might emerge from nonconscious experience in some way, and exceedingly difficult to imagine that there could be anything like conflict in this emergence—or put otherwise, that a moment of consciousness, and in particular, its “now” moment, would get dragged into self-consciousness against its will, as it were. And more than all else, we would thus need to insist that self-consciousness could not be brought to a life from without that very life itself, as if a mere “product of socialization” that might, in Zahavi’s words, emerge “for contingent reasons” only.Footnote 3 As a result of this, various accounts of the unconscious would be rendered untenable, and Zahavi thinks we can “avoid the aporetical consequences suggested by some deconstructive readings.”Footnote 4 This is to say that, on the level of primordial self-temporalization, there would be “an operatively functioning accomplishing that is in fact solitary,” as Zahavi insists, or a power that belongs to conscious life unaided; here, he continues, “we are not dependent upon others.”Footnote 5

In this paper, I’ll argue against Zahavi’s ostensibly Husserlian position, beginning with an attack, in §1 of my essay, against the first of the above claims: “The flowing self-manifestation of consciousness,” we’ll see, does not “take its point of departure in an immediate impressional self-manifestation.” After this, I’ll then argue in §2 against the second part of Zahavi’s stance—a position, once again, which otherwise seems to follow immediately from the first claim. In order to accomplish my task, I’ll offer an encapsulated version of the historical development of Husserl’s own account of time-consciousness, examining the positions that Husserl takes and, most importantly, the reasons that he comes to these positions. In the process, it will become evident that the Zahavian position is unsustainable—particularly when we reach Husserl’s discovery of the mediated phenomenon of self-fulfillment, by which, as we’ll see below, Husserl is at long last able to resolve the paradoxes that plague his earlier accounts of time-consciousness.

Husserl’s writings on time-consciousness span the better part of four decades, and there is obviously far more to be said about them than a single essay could ever deliver. Rather than attempting the impossible,Footnote 6 then, I’ll focus on the development, not of Husserl’s account of time-consciousness per se, but of only a single theme from this: that of the manifestation of the “now.” As my introduction has explained, after all, the basic point at issue in the first part of this essay will be Zahavi’s understanding of this phenomenon; I’ll therefore only deal with other issues in Husserl’s account of time-consciousness insofar as my main theme requires it. Before beginning, also, I should note that I’m not interested here in Husserl interpretation for its own sake, but only as a resource to help clarify “the things themselves.” I ask the reader to keep this in mind, for in what follows, it will probably become fairly clear that I don’t believe Zahavi interprets Husserl’s account of time-constitution accurately—a belief that is not only my own, since John Brough, for one, claims that Zahavi’s reading “may not always be a snug fit for Husserl’s texts,”Footnote 7 and Toine Kortooms writes that “Zahavi… gives an interpretation of Husserl’s doctrine of absolute time-consciousness that diverges from the prevalent picture.”Footnote 8 Nevertheless, this matter—i.e., fidelity to Husserl—is ultimately beside the point, for getting Husserl right on this score is not necessarily equivalent to getting the phenomenon of temporalization right, and it is the latter, again, that is my real concern in §1.

It’s well known, in any event, that according to Husserl, time-consciousness and self-consciousness are essentially linked—a connection that forms a basic theme for a number of Zahavi’s works, in fact. In Husserl’s first accounts of time-consciousness, however, self-consciousness does not appear to be a theme at all. Certainly, we find no argumentation in Husserl’s early texts that explicitly advances a necessary connection between these two phenomena, at least. And there is much to make us believe that he saw no such connection at all at the time: for in Logical Investigations II, to take one example, Husserl claims that “we must leave theories [of the necessity of what he calls “inner perception”] on one side, so long, that is, as the need to assume the unbroken activity of inner perception cannot be phenomenologically demonstrated”Footnote 9—a claim that Husserl could never have made about our “perception” of time.Footnote 10

So how does Husserl conceive of time-consciousness in his earliest works on the matter? In his lecture notes from the winter semester of 1904–1905, Husserl’s main intuition is that an enduring event or temporal object can only be made manifest by a conscious act that endures in time itself; no instantaneous consciousness, if such a thing is possible, could ever “give” us time.Footnote 11 So the question then becomes: How do conscious acts endure? In these lectures, Husserl attempts to account for their enduring with his notion of “fusion:”Footnote 12 moments of experiencing merge with one another on both sides, so to speak, so that the “contents” of the stream of consciousness (i.e., the experiencing “in” it, or the “parts” of the streaming life itself) are never anything like isolated instants. Because of this enduring, Husserl argues, an apprehension coming to “animate” the streaming contents can thus manifest time, or put otherwise, can seize upon a temporally enduring object thereby made manifest as such by them.Footnote 13

But the question can be pushed back further still: What is fusion; what in fact makes possible the temporal “width” of experiencing? In these early lectures, Husserl doesn’t examine this matter at all. He does use the term “primary memory” in apparent reference to the problem, and yet although similarities between this notion and Husserl’s later notion of “retention” might cause us to conflate the two, they are not the same: for unlike retention (and its complement, “protention”), primary memory here is no self-apprehension, but rather, is an apprehension of the just-passed moments of the enduring object of consciousness, or maybe better, of whatever event it is in which the enduring object is involved.Footnote 14 In truth, then, the only apprehensions mentioned in Husserl’s early account of temporality are those that “depart” from the temporally extended contents of consciousness and “terminate” in the temporally enduring object thereby constituted. The moments of conscious life, in their serial flowing, do not seem to be apprehended as such on this view, or at least, not in straightforward perception; thus, it seems that Husserl simply does not connect self-awareness to time-constitution, nor pose the former as a necessary element of all consciousness, in this early account at all.

Before I move on to Husserl’s subsequent—and as we’ll discover, increasingly more adequate—analyses of temporalization, I should consider an objection that Zahavi would likely make at this point: namely, that the absence of any talk about self-apprehension in connection with time-consciousness must count as an advantage, and not disadvantage, of Husserl’s early account. But why would Zahavi think so, when he himself clearly links self-consciousness and time-consciousness? In a word: because of his insistence that “pre-reflective” self-consciousness, which we’ll soon discover to be inseparable from primordial time-constitution, is a wholly “non-objectivating” sort of awareness, which leads Zahavi to take issue as soon as any talk of apprehension emerges in Husserl’s account of the phenomenon.Footnote 15 Zahavi, that is, believes that this consciousness must be a non-apprehending or “irrelational” one,Footnote 16 for reasons we’ll go over shortly—as opposed to all other forms of consciousness, which have to be considered “relational,”Footnote 17 insofar as they bring to manifestation something exterior to the act itself, even if only a different aspect of the selfsame (as in self-reflection). However: Although there can be no doubt that the consciousness at issue cannot be objectivating in any usual sense, Zahavi nevertheless seems to go too far when he rails against all “relational” accounts of it, for consciousness is consciousness-of, after all—or so Husserl always claimed—and is thus, in this sense, a relation; otherwise, nothing appears and we are not talking about a consciousness. And yet without wanting to dispute the principle that all consciousness is intentional, Zahavi finds himself forced to deny that it must be “relational” without qualification, because as we’ll see just below, the refusal to allow for anything like an irrelational or wholly non-apprehending self-consciousness, specifically in the form of an “immediate impressional self-manifestation” at the heart of time-constitution, appears to lead to an insoluble dilemma, and thus, seems impossible to maintain. This, admittedly, may make Zahavi’s account seem quite convincing.

What, then, of this apparently insoluble dilemma that, I’m claiming, motivates Zahavi’s position? To understand it, we’ll have to turn to some of Husserl’s subsequent accounts of time-consciousness. Unlike his earlier work on the topic, Husserl’s ensuing (and once again, increasingly more accurate) accounts of temporality do explicitly link time-consciousness with self-consciousness: I’ve already noted that the phenomenon he calls retention (and further, protention) amounts to an apprehension of the passed-by (and to-come) moments of experiencing as such. Husserl reaches what is probably his most well-known version of this sort of account—his account of “absolute time-consciousness”—through a number of stages; perhaps the two most prominent of these are expressed, firstly, in Husserl’s lecture notes from the summer semester of 1909,Footnote 18 and secondly, in his Bernauer manuscripts from 1917–1918. Before the 1909 lectures, Husserl had already coined the term “absolute consciousness,”Footnote 19 but by 1909, he comes to conceive of this consciousness as being composed of a peculiar “double-intentionality” that involves what Husserl will sometimes call a “transversal [Quer-]” and “longitudinal [Längs-]” intentionality.Footnote 20 These are self-apprehensions pure and simple, no doubt, although not objectivating in any usual sense, or at least, so Husserl claims.Footnote 21 But why did Husserl come to believe that some sort of self-apprehension is required for time-consciousness at all (a view that first seems to emerge, in fact, in his lectures of the winter semester of 1906–1907Footnote 22)? What was wrong with his earlier view? There are in fact many problems with it, but all center around one main issue: namely, that the passed-by moments of consciousness must be apprehended as such, if, “through them”—via a sort of “double intentionality,” that is then to say—the past “phases” of a temporally enduring object are to be grasped as past “phases” themselves, and the objective duration is to become manifest. The same must go for anticipated moments to-come, etc. Were there no such self-apprehension, no manner in which a conscious life grasped its own temporal streaming or “temporalized” itself, but merely a “fused” enduring experience or preserved continuum of content, there would be no motivation whatsoever for the apprehension of objective time or duration by the experience.Footnote 23

By Husserl’s 1909 lectures, however, his account has become much more complicated than this would apparently imply, for the double-intentionality of time-consciousness on which Husserl focuses his attention in these lectures is not that by which an enduring transcendent object or event, or the objective time of its enduring, is constituted or made manifest. To be clear, the constitution of “objective time” does, as I’ve just noted, involve a sort of double-intentionality, but that is not the double-intentionality that Husserl means to indicate with his notion of transversal- and longitudinal-intentionality.Footnote 24 We can understand this other double-intentionality, rather, as a “splitting” of the above double-intentionality’s “inner” apprehension, i.e., of self-temporalization; along with it, the whole notion of the self likewise becomes divided.Footnote 25 This point is sometimes confused: for after all, isn’t transversal-intentionality supposed to grasp an object, unlike its longitudinal correlate?Footnote 26 In a qualified sense, yes; but transversal-intentionality, on this account, is understood to grasp, not an object in the usual sense (e.g., a transcendent thing), but rather, an “immanent object” in “immanent” or “subjective” time, which is to say, an enduring experience or conscious act apprehended as such.Footnote 27 Husserl writes, then, that “by virtue of one of the intentionalities”—namely, that of the “transversal” sort—“immanent time becomes constituted;”Footnote 28 transversal-intentionality, as an element of time-consciousness, must thus be understood as the constituting correlate of our streaming or enduring conscious acts or experiences, making them manifest as streaming or enduring acts or experiences. On this account, however, longitudinal-intentionality also grasps the “self,” albeit in a different sense: It apprehends something like the “streaming” phases of this very consciousness or “activity” of transversal-intentionality, in order to constitute the enduring “immanent objects” through them;Footnote 29 Husserl writes, therefore, that “in the other intentionality, it is the quasi-temporal arrangement of the phases of the flow that becomes constituted.”Footnote 30

In a very real sense, then, the account has been doubled: “Behind” the acts of what is now merely an “empirical ego”—which, constituted or made manifest in their streaming or “subjective” enduring, can thus constitute the objective duration of transcendent things within the world—we find an Urstrom or “primal-stream” of consciousness, which in some sense temporalizes itself (“longitudinally”) so that it can constitute, “transversally,” these acts of the empirical ego—again, conscious experiences in the usual sense—or make them its enduring, immanent, “objects.” The account of longitudinal- and transversal-intentionality that Husserl offers at this time is thus meant to clarify the nature of the two “levels” of consciousness that he had ostensibly discovered when, earlier (ca. 1907), he “distinguished the different levels of constitution in their essential structure:”

  1. 1.

    The things of empirical experience in objective time…;

  2. 2.

    the constituting multiplicities of appearance belonging to different levels, the immanent unities in pre-empirical [or what Husserl elsewhere calls “immanent”] time;

  3. 3.

    the absolute time-constituting flow of consciousness.Footnote 31

What Husserl comes to believe in the period we are now discussing is that each of these levels, or the objects “on” them, are made manifest by the intentional directedness emerging from the immediately “deeper” level—with the exception of the “deepest” level, that of absolute time-consciousness, which must then be intended by itself. The subject, or the streaming life of subjectivity, is thus given in two different ways, “immanently” and “absolutely,” by means of two different intentionalities; hence, the strange “doubling” of which I speak.

What can we make of this doubling? On the face of it, the whole thing seems flawed at basis, given that, as Zahavi regularly points out,Footnote 32 it’s hard to make sense of the distinction between “transversal-intentionality,” on the one hand—or the consciousness we have of our own streaming conscious experience—and “longitudinal-intentionality,” on the other—or some purported “pure” consciousness of that very consciousness (i.e., of the transversal-intentionality). Yet Husserl seems forced to both posit two levels of consciousness and claim that both must be temporalized, since once again, our streaming conscious activity must be manifest in its streaming if the objects it brings to appearance are to be manifest as enduring themselves, but this apparently requires not only some “deeper” level of consciousness to apprehend our activity as such,Footnote 33 but also that, by the same token, this “deeper” level be manifest in its streaming too (or at least, in its “quasi-temporal arrangement”). Thus, we come to the notion of a doubly time-constituting consciousness, or Urstrom, “behind” our “empirical” egoic life or streaming acts of consciousness in the usual sense—a position that I hope the following diagram will suffice to illustrate (Fig. 1):Footnote 34

Fig. 1
figure 1

The questionability of the “Urimpression” is examined below

Husserl ostensibly “bites the bullet” by accepting this doubled account, one which (as Zahavi again notes) has to be seen as at least prima facie problematic; but he thereby finds himself faced with a dilemma that, amazingly, poses a greater problem still. On the one hand, that is, Husserl must presuppose, on pain of infinite regress, the notion of an “ultimate consciousness,”Footnote 35 or put otherwise, a consciousness that is not itself made manifest. He sees nothing at first to gainsay this understanding of what he originally called the “Urimpression”—the consciousness at the “now-point” of the Urstrom—for the reason that:

The flow of the consciousness that constitutes immanent time… must necessarily be apprehensible in the flowing…. [Yet] the phases of the flow of consciousness in which phases of the same flow of consciousness become constituted phenomenally cannot be identical with these constituted phases, and of course they are not. What is brought to appearance in the actual momentary phase of the flow of consciousness—specifically, in its series of reproductive [or “retentional”] moments—are the past phases of the flow of consciousness.Footnote 36

If this is so, then although via longitudinal-retention, the “passed-by” phases of the Urstrom would get apprehended (in order to constitute, again, enduring acts in immanent time through its transversal-intentionality), the present phase of the Urstrom, or the Urimpression, would not come to be apprehended or made manifest as such itself until it had actually passed and become retained. In this sense, it could be called “ultimate,” since not intended by anything for its own part, and as such, would head off regress.

And yet on the other hand, however, Husserl is at once forced to deny the very possibility of an Urimpression that is not consciously apprehended, but which would only become apprehended nachträglich, or after the fact.Footnote 37 After all, that cannot be so for the “now-phase” of the immanent “content” of consciousness (i.e., of experience in the usual sense): for in another text from roughly the same period, Husserl writes that

if it [“the beginning phase of an experience that is in the process of becoming constituted”] were intended only by retention, then what confers on it the label “now” would remain incomprehensible…. It is just nonsense to talk about an “unconscious” content that would only subsequently [nachträglich] become conscious. Consciousness is necessarily consciousness in each of its phases. Just as the retentional phase is conscious of the preceding phase without making it into an object, so too the primal datum is already intended—specifically, in the original form of the “now.”Footnote 38

Husserl’s deliberations on time-consciousness, that is, have convinced him of the need for a temporalizing apprehension of every phase of an “immanent” conscious experience, including, crucially, of the “now” phase: for otherwise, as Husserl indicates, nothing would ever be given to consciousness of its own activity as “now” at all (and as a result, nothing of a “worldly” object would ever be given as “right now” either), which is, surely, an absurd claim; and furthermore, a phase of experience could hardly be given through retention as “now-passed” anyways if it were never given consciously as “now” in the first place. We can thus see how much Husserl’s opinion changed on these matters in a few short years (for again, he originally did not see the need to connect self-apprehension to time-consciousness at all). And for just this reason, I think, the term Urimpression started to become rather intolerable: Husserl speaks instead in these passages of an Urbewusstsein (“primal-consciousness”), which he will later call Urpräsentation (precisely a presentation—transversal—of the now-phase of experience as such).Footnote 39 However, Husserl is thus left in a quandary, since by the very same reasoning, he will soon be led (in 1917–1918) to conclude that the Urpräsentation must then be intended as “now” itself: Husserl thus asks “what about the present being of the primal-process…, is this consciousness not again present, does this not require a further consciousness of presence etc.?”Footnote 40 For the Urpräsentation itself to be manifest as “now,” that is, there would then have to be yet another consciousness “behind” it, an Urstrom behind the Urstrom constituting it in its “nowness,” and then so on again to infinity—which would obviously be impossible. It is for just this reason that Zahavi proposes an irrelational or “immediate impressional self-manifestation” at the heart of temporalizing self-consciousness, writing that “if we are to avoid an infinite regress, this primitive prereflective self-awareness cannot be due to a secondary act or reflex.”Footnote 41 And despite the seemingly problematic nature of an “irrelational” consciousness, we should have to concur—or unless some other solution could be found for this dilemma (Fig. 2).

Fig. 2
figure 2

The dilemma facing Husserl’s account of “absolute time-consciousness”

This allows us to understand what is, at least at first glance, deeply appealing about Zahavi’s position. In his 1999 book, Self-Awareness and Alterity, Zahavi begins to advance his account of temporalization by arguing that “the clarification of inner time-consciousness is more fundamental than the clarification of different types of objectivating acts,” which leads to the claim that “the decisive problem is then to clarify the relation between the absolute flow…, on the one hand, and the constituted act, on the other.”Footnote 42 After then admitting that he does not believe “Husserl ever managed to achieve complete clarity on this issue,” Zahavi concedes, further, that there are not only multiple interpretations of Husserl’s account of it, but that an interpretation like the one I’ve just outlined is the “established view.”Footnote 43 Yet both because of the problem of regress as well as the difficulty in even making sense of the distinction between absolute and immanent time-consciousness, Zahavi argues that such a view cannot be accepted as an adequate account of the phenomenon of temporalization (whether or not we end up accepting it as Husserl’s account from this period is a different matter). Instead, Zahavi goes on, we ought to conclude, not that an act “is brought to givenness by something other than itself, namely by inner time-consciousness,”Footnote 44 but rather that, “apart from being intentional, the act is also characterized by its ‘inner consciousness,’… a pervasive dimension of self-manifestation.”Footnote 45 But then, for the reasons we’ve discovered, Zahavi concludes that “this self-givenness… takes its point of departure in an immediate impressional self-manifestation”Footnote 46 or the “now’s” irrelational self-appearance.

It should be obvious that the dilemma which apparently arises for Husserl’s account—infinite regress, or else no consciousness of the “now”—does not arise for Zahavi’s version of it. At the same time, his account has no need for a problematic “doubling” of self-temporalization (i.e., for any second level of time-constituting consciousness, “behind” the stream of consciousness itself), for as Zahavi argues, “if it is acknowledged that such a type of [irrelational] self-awareness exists, one might reasonably ask why it should… not already be a feature of the act itself.”Footnote 47 On his account, that is, the level of “empirical ego” or “immanent time” drops out, or at least, is nowhere to be found in straightforward perception; it is only constituted, Zahavi argues, in expressly self-reflective acts.

This should give us enough of Zahavi’s account to go on; but before we move on, let us note, once again, the kind of reductio ad absurdum that is ultimately supposed to justify Zahavi’s view. To put it summarily: The “now” moment of consciousness must be manifest as such, but since its self-manifestation cannot be “relational,” or articulable into apprehension and that-which-is-apprehended, without apparently leading to infinite regress, it seems that there must be a consciousness here that simply is not “relational” at all. This then leads to the Zahavian position that I illustrate below (Fig. 3):

Fig. 3
figure 3

The circular arrow that I must use to symbolize “impressional” consciousness is, sadly, a poor symbol for it, since this supposedly involves nothing like an apprehension or any “ray” of consciousness

The fact that the dilemma that would cripple Husserl’s account does not arise for Zahavi’s version of it, and that Zahavi can avoid any problematic “doubling” of consciousness also, can surely be seen as support for the Zahavian position, i.e., that the “flowing self-manifestation of consciousness” does involve an immediate, irrelational self-consciousness, which Zahavi takes to be Husserl’s Urimpression. In place of the problems that this would solve, however, new difficulties emerge: for how are we to understand an “irrelational” consciousness? This ought to be described, I think, before we can even consider accepting Zahavi’s resolution, since the very idea seems ad hoc. What would an irrelational consciousness actually be like, a consciousness which is somehow “of” the self, and yet without being “of” anything at all, since “irrelational?” Zahavi does not quite seem to realize the strangeness of the claim, and sadly, offers little in the way of any independent reasoning—or better, phenomenological description—in order to remove its ad hoc appearance. At most, so far as I can tell, Zahavi tries to do so by pointing out that “there is necessarily something ‘it is like’ for a subject to undergo an experience,”Footnote 48 a matter he then connects with his notion of an “impressional” self-consciousness. Yet the claim is very vague, and because of this, as we’ll discover later, Zahavi thereby only seems to conflate self-consciousness with a wholly different phenomenon (namely, sensing). But even leaving aside such worries for the time being, there are more difficulties yet for Zahavi’s position: for were Zahavi correct in claiming that the manifestation of the present phase of consciousness is irrelational, it should then be a mystery not only why this consciousness must be connected inextricably with time-constitution—but even, in fact, how it could be. Zahavi contends that “impressional self-manifestation stretches to include the retentionally given,”Footnote 49 but this only makes the difficulty here more apparent: for how could an “irrelational” self-manifestation—already, again, a potentially vacuous concept on its own—“stretch” to “include the retentionally given,” as Zahavi says it would, when the retentionally given, at least, must be given via apprehension: which is to say, “relationally?” Can an irrelational consciousness “stretch to include” a relational one, that is, given that “stretch” implies being connected in a continuum, but between impression and retention we would then have a difference in kind?Footnote 50 Or will Zahavi instead be forced to conclude (as he seems to want to deny, by admitting that retention and protention are “ecstatic”Footnote 51) that retention and protention are “irrelational” as well? An “irrelational” consciousness of the just-passed moments of experiencing, etc., sans apprehension—as if by speaking of the “of,” again, what we mean is not precisely something like an apprehending “relation?” And how, were we able to understand self-retention as being “irrelational enough” to allow for the required “stretch” or continuum with a proposed irrelational impressional self-manifestation—assuming that Zahavi’s account could be fleshed out on this point without simply leading to contradiction—would this not then simply return us to the problem Husserl faced in his earlier accounts of time-constitution, before he had connected the latter with self-apprehension: namely, that without apprehension of the just-passed moments of experiencing, there is no motivation for any constitution of the enduring of transcendent objects? For wasn’t the whole problem with mere fusion that it lacked the “relationality” that worries Zahavi so? The difficulties multiply themselves, and although we cannot say without further ado that there is no possible consistent response to them, nowhere, so far as I know, does Zahavi even address these issues, let alone resolve them to satisfaction.Footnote 52

I will not dwell on the possibilities of a Zahavian response to the questions I’ve just raised (although I should point out that the problem of continuity between the manifestation of the “now” and “retained” moments of consciousness is one that will surely prove fatal to the Zahavian position currently at issue if it cannot be adequately resolved on his account). What is crucial here, instead, is to recognize that Husserl’s further development of the notion of “absolute time-consciousness” in his 1917–1918 Bernauer manuscripts is also able to avoid the dilemma that troubled his earlier (ca. 1909) account, but without involving any of the difficulties (and apparent self-contradictions, even) of the Zahavian position. Revisiting his account of time-consciousness in these manuscripts, Husserl still takes himself to be dealing with the “longitudinal-intentionality” of the Urstrom, and yet he now focuses more intently upon the phenomenon of protention (or as Husserl sometimes says, “projection”Footnote 53). But by recognizing that consciousness always “protains” itself, however, Husserl is able to recognize that, through its retention, it must retain itself precisely as having-“protained” itself, a protention (or self-anticipating, as it were) which is continuously fulfilled just so long as conscious life continues (Fig. 4):Footnote 54

Fig. 4
figure 4

The development in Husserl's Bernauer account

Husserl thus writes that each arising moment of consciousness:

comes “welcome,” or each retentional momentary continuum maintains a protention into what follows…. Genetically speaking: if again and again, continuously, new core-data arise, so the old do not merely sink down retentionally, but rather, “shoot up” a protentional consciousness, which the new primal-data comes to meet and… fulfills.Footnote 55

As before, Husserl takes the “current” phase of the primal-stream to retain and protain phases of that same stream or flow, but he now also understands it to make itself manifest as the primal-stream’s “now,” so that it can serve as Urpräsentation, precisely insofar as it fulfills its earlier self-protention (or the “futural self-intending” of its previous phases, which for their own part, thereby get retained as so fulfilled). In this way, regress is averted without problematic recourse to an unmanifest consciousness (or a “now” moment of conscious experiencing that would not be given as such, again)Footnote 56—but also, without recourse to any irrelational consciousness.

This development, obviously, runs totally contrary to Zahavi’s advanced position; we might wonder, then, if he has an answer to it. And in fact, Zahavi does address this Bernauer development, but only to dismiss it out of hand, for all intents and purposes, with the following justification given for this alone:

Is it wise to attempt to understand self-constitution in terms of fulfillment? Fulfillment is a relational process. It is a relation between something that fulfils and something that is fulfilled…. Even if that which fulfils and that which is fulfilled turns out to be the same, we are still dealing with a dyadic structure, and the question is whether such a structure will enable us to understand self-constitution. Husserl explicitly argued [in Hua X, Zahavi says] that the retentional modification presupposes an impressional (primary, original, and immediate) self-awareness not only because consciousness is as such self-given, but also because retention of an unconscious content is impossible (Hua X/119). This notion of impressional self-awareness seems required if one is to avoid the aporetical consequences suggested by some deconstructive readings: Initially, consciousness is unconscious, and it only gains self-awareness nachträglich through the retentional modification.Footnote 57

What can we make of this response? At face value, it simply seems to beg the question, since it appears that the very problem that Husserl hopes to resolve with the development of his account in Bernau is to establish precisely how what he called Urimpression before truly can be Urpräsentation, or can present the current moment of experiencing as the “now” of the selfsame streaming consciousness, without this leading to regress. Husserl, that is, strives in these manuscripts to describe “such a structure” precisely in order to “enable us to understand self-constitution,” something that, for the reasons we saw above, he had come to see his earlier account did not adequately accomplish. Does Husserl’s account in Bernau, then, allow us to understand how the current moment of experiencing can be manifest as such, and yet without this committing us to an infinite regress? Zahavi’s response gives us no reason to see why not, although at face value, Husserl’s development seems to be successful on both fronts, for on the the one hand, the problem of regress certainly does not arise on such an account, while on the other, it would seem that the fulfillment of passed, and now retained, self-protentions should in fact continually come to pass as a conscious life’s consciousness of its own “now” just as Husserl claims. It is not as though in Bernau, Husserl conceded that the “now” is not given, and merely replaced its givenness with that of a retained moment of consciousness that had “aimed” at it, since—as Zahavi, who recounts Husserl’s Bernauer development quite accurately, well knowsFootnote 58—Husserl’s whole idea here is that it’s in the continual fulfillment of this prior “self-aiming” that the “now” of conscious life is given. Given that this is so, however, Zahavi’s response seems to simply amount to a bald assertion of his own opposed position—or unless there is an argument here well hidden between the lines.Footnote 59 (Of course, Zahavi’s own resolution doubtlessly would offer an alternative way out of the dilemma, but for the reasons I touched upon above, it doesn’t seem a route that Husserl himself would have wanted to take).

Now the principle of charity does compel us to find an argument in Zahavi’s response, if at all possible. Perhaps we can find one in the passage at issue, then, if we focus more on Zahavi’s assertion that the self-givenness of consciousness presupposes “an impressional (primary, original, and immediate) self-awareness;” for with this, Zahavi can be understood to infer that Husserl’s Bernauer development has to deny that the “now” comes to consciousness as such at all precisely because the resulting account denies self-temporalization its “immediacy.” After all, Husserl’s claim here is that, as a consciousness that comes to pass through the fulfillment of a retained self-protention, the Urpräsentation is a “mediated” consciousness!Footnote 60 But to draw this conclusion, if this is what Zahavi does do, would only be to equivocate on the basis of two different senses of the word “immediate,” a clear fallacy: for it simply does not follow that, since mediated in this way, the consciousness at issue would be unable to present what is “immediate” in the sense of making the “now” moment of consciousness manifest as “now.” Of course, it isn’t really clear that Zahavi does equivocate in this way; and yet if we assume that he doesn’t, it becomes difficult, once again, to find an argument against Husserl’s position here at all.Footnote 61

We are thus left with two opposed but “internally” successful solutions to the same dilemma: How, then, can we determine which of the two accounts represents self-temporalization accurately? We saw above that Zahavi’s account has something ad hoc about it, and yet Husserl, conversely, has independent reasons for maintaining that conscious life has the form of a “mediated-immediacy,” becoming manifest to itself in its current moment through the continual fulfillment of its earlier self-protentions. At face value, perhaps, Husserl’s solution might rather look like a bit of ad hoc reasoning also, a mere “construction” or convenient work-around if you will. But in fact, any phenomenological analysis whatsoever, carried on far enough, should ultimately lead us to affirm Husserl’s development, i.e., that conscious life comes to itself by fulfilling its passing-by, and now retained, self-protaining: since as Husserl finally realizes, intentionality always involves a sort of striving, and constitutes sense in any given case only insofar as this striving has been fulfilled in some way, but with this development in Bernau we come upon what Husserl will call the “general” form of all fulfillment.Footnote 62 Thus, to take one example, we find (e.g., in the genetic descriptions of perception presented in Husserl’s Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis) that the act of perception takes place as a continually developing unity from out of an interwoven series of act-moments, and that a current sense-experience comes to pass as one such moment of perceptual awareness, or of our consciousness of some transcendent, “worldly” being with which we find ourselves engaged, only insofar as it comes to pass as the concordant, or at times somewhat discordant, fulfillment of prior perceptual anticipations originating in the earlier moments of the course of the same experiencing.Footnote 63 But such fulfillment, once more, presupposes a life’s having-been “aiming” in general, or put otherwise, its having-been “futurally-directed” or protaining experiences to-come, whose fulfillment precisely results in the particular consciousness that thus comes to pass. So even had Husserl not had to propose this mediated-immediacy in order to safeguard his account of self-temporalization against infinite regress, he would have come face-to-face with the “phenomenon” anyways at some point.Footnote 64 And we may remember too, in this regard, that it isn’t only Husserl who finds evidence for the position: In Heidegger’s work on temporality, for instance, we read that “since the Dasein always comes-toward-itself from out of a possibility of itself, it therewith also always comes-back-to what it has been,”Footnote 65 which gets at this same formal structure of self-temporalization as a mediated “general fulfillment.”

This development in Husserl’s account, in any event, leads to a decisive move in the “C-Manuscripts,” Husserl’s final work on time-consciousness: namely, the notion of “absolute time-consciousness,” and everything that is problematic with this doubled-account, is dropped. The entire reasoning behind this doubling, we saw, was to have, “behind” our enduring conscious acts or experiences, a consciousness to constitute them as such. Now that Husserl has discovered how a stream of experiencing can be self-constituting in a strict sense, however, another “level” of consciousness “behind” that of the streaming empirical ego appears totally superfluous; instead, the “egoic” streaming conscious life must simply be understood to temporalize itself in the intricate fashion attributed in Bernau to its “absolute” double.Footnote 66 This evidently fits the phenomenological facts much better, for longitudinal-intentionality always appeared chimerical (Zahavi is right to insist this). But then, if Husserl no longer needs to “bite” this particular “bullet,” which he is able to avoid in a different way than Zahavi, he is thus able to eliminate everything that appeared problematic about his earlier account—the “doubled” account of consciousness, as well as the dilemma in which this thereby placed it, involving the threat of infinite regress—but without taking on Zahavi’s ad hoc amendment. Instead, Husserl has recourse only to a position that he must insist upon anyways for independent reasons: one backed by all the phenomenological evidence, and not simply reached through a highly speculative reductio.

With this, we see that Zahavi’s first claim is totally undone: The “now” moment of conscious life is manifest as such, given to itself as something like the “current” phase of the streaming and on the horizon of this developing totality, not as if purely from its own “powers.” This consciousness, rather, is mediated or comes to the moment from without: i.e., through its relation to the other moments of this life, in particular, vis-à-vis the retained moment of experiencing that has been awaiting it as the coming of the selfsame. Thus, the “flowing self-manifestation of consciousness” does not “take its departure” from the now-moment’s self-awareness; it is rather the self-protention of the streaming conscious life that again and again “awakens”Footnote 67 each emerging experience, or brings it to consciousness as what is current in the unfolding life.

What, then, about the other half of the Zahavian position: a second claim, once again, which would apparently have followed quite simply from the first? Were we forced to accept the first part of Zahavi’s position, that is—that there is some “irrelational” self-awareness inherent in the now-phase of experiencing, from which self-temporalization “takes its departure”—then as we saw above in the introduction to this essay, we would have to accept also that the self-presence of conscious life could not come from without any given moment of experiencing, let alone, be “forced upon” it; and thus ultimately, that it could not come to a life from without that very life itself—for example, through something like a more primordial sociality or, as Zahavi says, “concrete encounter with the other.”Footnote 68 That is to say, the “linguistic–pragmatic” and “deconstructive” positions Zahavi opposes would have no sound footing.Footnote 69 Casting aside the Zahavian position on self-temporalization, however, we are obviously no longer forced to accept this second proposition. Can it be defended otherwise? Prima facie, it would certainly seem possible to do so: for after all, Husserl did not arrive at the Zahavian position himself, regarding the purported necessity of an “immediate impressional self-manifestation,” and yet he nonetheless surely did hold the same position as Zahavi on this second point, irrespective of all the developments in his account of time-constitution.Footnote 70 Might Zahavi be able to “avoid the aporetical consequences suggested by some deconstructive readings” by other means, then? Or rather, could it be instead that Zahavi’s hope to affirm this second proposition is in truth out of line with the more satisfactory account of the phenomenon of temporalizing self-constitution that we’ve been able to reach by working through Husserl’s developing thought on the issue? Although it should take a separate work to fully prove the point, in the remainder of this essay I’ll give good reason to believe that it is this latter claim that must be affirmed.

But why must we affirm it? Surely, if self-consciousness comes, in a certain sense, to each moment from without—albeit via other moments within the same streaming conscious life, at least, as part and parcel of that life’s ongoing self-temporalization—then this consciousness must incessantly impose itself, so to speak, upon something like nonconsciousness, or upon experiences that could only be counted as the experiences of the selfsame conscious life, as its own moments, because of the process of temporalization that would keep “gathering them up” as such.Footnote 71 In this regard, it is imperative to note that Husserl does not entirely do away with the notion of an Urstrom in the C-Manuscripts, although he does deny it any consciousness or intending: “The stream of experiences,” he writes, “accomplishes no authentic temporalization and is no corresponding performance of consciousness.”Footnote 72 As a mere “hyletic stratum,”Footnote 73 Husserl comes to believe, the Urstrom is a stratum of nonconscious experiencing that does not bear intentionality in itself: a sphere of pure sensation in which sensorial prominences or hyletic unities are simply “built up” or “fused” (we can no longer say constituted in the strict sense).Footnote 74 What motivates the modification of his view? This change in Husserl’s conception of the Urstrom, for which we have evidence in the C-Manuscripts, would seem to simply result, once we jettison the “absolute” level of time-constitution and relocate the dynamic of self-fulfilling temporalization to streaming “egoic” life: for the arising sense-experiences, which once again, can only come to consciousness as “my now” by fulfilling an earlier protentional-“openness,” thus have to arise, for their own part, independently of any conscious accomplishing, leaving the formation of unity in sensing wholly to nonconscious processes. In his Lectures Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis, conversely, Husserl was still working within his Bernauer-era account of absolute time-consciousness, and thus believed he could account for the production of unified sensorial-prominences via the “absolute” level, which then had to be seen, before all else, as the original field of hyletic unification and differentiation.Footnote 75 The problem with this, of course, is that the account, already problematic as a “two-level” theory, thus turned into a sort of “sense-data” theory as well: for through what Husserl called passive intentionality, these unities were thus understood to be given by consciousness—even if only an “absolute” consciousness—as enduring unities of experience, “prior” to the further syntheses that could ultimately turn them into intentional acts or presentations of transcendent being. However important Husserl’s analyses of the fusion of hyletic unities may be, though (and this cannot be denied), the claim that these unities are intended as such by consciousness simply cannot be defended phenomenologically. Sensory experiences are instead presupposed, and not constituted, by consciousness—and in fact, they are “there” for us only insofar as they are part of our intentional activity precisely because they come to be constituted as the current moment of conscious life by fulfilling its ongoing self-protention, while it is just this synthesis, as I noted above, that continually invests the experience with its intentional directedness; as such, the sensory experience manifest as an experience of consciousness is always manifest as “ego-cogito-cogitatum,” as Husserl often puts it,Footnote 76 or as “my” ongoing engagement with some enduring object thereby made manifest too.Footnote 77 But given this, Husserl’s removal of the formation of hyletic unities from consciousness in his C-Manuscripts must be considered a crucial, and welcome, amendment to his original “genetic” account.

So consciousness, Husserl comes to believe, continually wins itself from out of nonconscious experiencing. But how, precisely, does he understand this relation to nonconsciousness? In his C-Manuscripts, Husserl comes to understand the Urstrom, not as a “lower level” of consciousness, again, but as a stream of otherwise nonconscious sensing in which a streaming life of intentional activity emerges. Accordingly, Husserl begins to refer to the emergent self-temporalization as an “act” and “ego” temporalization,Footnote 78 in order to distinguish it from the formation of “hyletic unities” that makes up the Urstrom itself.Footnote 79 For there is admittedly, in the fusing of these unities or of enduring prominences in sensing, something like a “pre-temporalization,” as Husserl sometimes says,Footnote 80 and yet it is no genuine temporalization or constitution of any kind, since for their own part, these fusions (and further, the other purely “pre-active” associations that follow on their heels) exhibit no retaining consciousness in the sense of a consciousness of the passed-by experiencing as the passing and continual enduring of the selfsame life, and likewise, no protentional consciousness of experiences to-come with this. Rather, in them—and this is of course a return to Husserl’s original use of the term “fusion”Footnote 81—the prominences in sense-experiencing are simply built up in their actual endurance, without thereby becoming manifest as such.Footnote 82 Doubtless, self-temporalization would be impossible, were sensation itself not always an enduring, or were it some individual and isolated “time-slice.” Rising and falling in intensity, the enduring prominences provide the “material” presupposed by a streaming life conscious of itself as such.Footnote 83 But this alone is not enough; if a streaming sensing life is to be a streaming conscious one, constituted for itself in its streaming identity, a “primal identification” of egoic life, as Husserl now puts the matter,Footnote 84 must arise within it, or a process of self-protaining, which can make the enduring prominent sensations or built up unities of sensing manifest as the sensory “affections” belonging to this life’s intentional activity, precisely insofar as they come to pass as a further fulfillment of the process. Only thereby does each experience live itself out as a moment of the selfsame streaming, once again, or as its “now” phase, leading Husserl to write that:

Going back from the always already constituted ego, which as such presupposes the ego already in function, [there is] thus affection on the pure ego-pole…. This pure ego-pole, thus as mere unity passing through the total life-stream, unity out of passive temporalization, [is] over against the hyle, which in its stratifications, likewise persists. From it, the affection-rays—from the ego, act-rays…. Identical ego with affection- and action-rays as constant stratum in the life-stream, thus, hyletic (ego-alien) stratum and egoic stratum…. Each “experience,” taken concretely, is two-sided, ego-side and side of the ego-alien.Footnote 85

Zahavi himself notices this “two-sidedness,” or what he calls a “reflexive scissiparity”Footnote 86—writing that “pre-reflective self-awareness is characterized by this inner fracture” between “an egoic and a non-egoic dimension”Footnote 87—and yet without concluding much further regarding its ultimate significance. But Husserl continues:

In the totality of the streaming present [there is] a totality of null-affection, the total null: background of the unconscious. Put more clearly… the functioning ego with its acts and all its authentic affections—correlatively the universe of the thematic—is, in the streaming primal present, thus streamingly, constantly “raised up” [abgehoben]…, distinguished from the night of the unconscious.Footnote 88

The following diagram can help to illustrate the position reached (Fig. 5):

Fig. 5
figure 5

Husserl’s ultimate account of time-consciousness, as developed in his C-Manuscripts

We just saw that Zahavi does not seem to want to deny the notion of the nonconscious per se.Footnote 89 Yet on Zahavi’s account, in which givenness or self-presence is “intrinsic” to the moment of experiencing, it appears quite difficult, to say the least, to understand how consciousness might emerge from something like nonconsciousness at all—unlike the account we’ve been able to develop by working through Husserl’s later works on temporalization—and thus, to understand what place the “unconscious” might possibly have in Zahavi’s account. In fact, I think it now becomes apparent that Zahavi is so little able to make room for anything like nonconscious experience in his account, that he simply conflates the immediacy of sensing from which self-awareness can emerge with that self-awareness itself: or conflates, that is, “hyletic” experiencing, or what we could call pure sentience, with self-temporalization, or the “being-for-itself” of ongoing intentional activity, in which sensory experiences can come to take their place. It is for just this reason that Zahavi believes he can describe self-awareness by simply pointing out, as we saw above, that “there is necessarily something ‘it is like’ for a subject to undergo an experience.” Yet to be self-aware is not simply to undergo an experience (or to have there be something “it is like” to undergo it, as Zahavi says somewhat redundantly), but rather, is precisely to be conscious of it, i.e., to have a sense of the experience undergone or to be related to it as such: which is just to say, for it to be manifest as “my own,” the current moment of an ongoing life.Footnote 90 And it is precisely through the mediated-immediacy of a fulfilled self-protention, we’ve discovered, that the experience is brought to consciousness in this way.

Why is this important; what does it have to do with the second Zahavian position at issue in this essay, which insists that the accomplishment of self-temporalization “is in fact solitary?” To recognize that self-temporalization “imposes itself” upon something like nonconscious experience (or that, through the protaining that gets fulfilled, it continually brings to consciousness moments of experiencing that arise of their own accord) is certainly not yet to accept that this process must originate from without the experiencing life itself, or that it need come, socially or intersubjectively and perhaps as though through a kind of compulsion or subjection, from others. Yet precisely insofar as it leads us to the question of the emergence of this “power” within a stream of nonconscious experiencing, it certainly moves us in this direction. And in this regard, it will be helpful to recall a particular remark that Husserl makes in his lectures on passive synthesis. Via the most basic of these “syntheses,” Husserl claims—syntheses which he will later come to see as that of originally nonconscious experience—an action, or perhaps better, behavior, gets stimulated. Husserl thus writes that in:

a constant broad horizon of background lived-experiences to which the ego is not present and “in” which it does not reside [or in a background without “lived-experiences in the specific sense of wakefulness, lived-experiences of the ego-cogito”]…, tendencies, lived-experiences of drive, may be rooted… which for instance incline away from malcontentment, but the ego is not present there.Footnote 91

How is it that such “tendencies” are “rooted” in nonconscious experiencing? For a body to be sensing is already for it to be rearranging itself, adapting itself to its environment: e.g., the unpleasant feeling of something abrasively brushing against one’s legs is already a shuffling away from the contact. Without any apparent need for conscious intervention, sensation is, in Heideggerian terms, “disinhibition,”Footnote 92 whether on the basis of instinct (“nature”) or habit (“second nature”). But to the extent that the experience “rises up” to consciousness, assuming it is to be so risen, it precisely gets lived through as a moment of the selfsame life, again, and sense is thereby made of the sensing-experience now “interpreted” or made manifest in this light, so that there is world-constitution—I perceive, e.g., a person bumping into my lower extremities as I sit here on the subway. Over and above the immediacy of a “sensation-behavior circuit,” that is to say, here I am, pre-reflectively conscious of myself as enduringly involved in the world, directed towards this or that persisting being.

Admittedly, as I just noted, Husserl was still laboring under some of the misconceptions of his “absolute time-consciousness” view when he gave his lectures on passive synthesis. When he wrote the words I just quoted from these lectures, then, he thus still imagined that sensation-experiences (or mere “hyletic unities”), even prior to the dawning of the “empirical ego” (or when “the ego is not present” yet in them, and thus, no world-constitution either), nonetheless are already intended or given consciously, namely, as “transversally” apprehended “immanent objects.” But once we have been able to clarify self-temporalization as a continual “rising up” of conscious experiencing within the nonconsciousness of the hyletic stratum, the full significance of this stratum can be understood: we discover here, in the hyletic “realm,” the affection of a purely sensing life, which for its own part, once more, is already behavior, already instinctual or habitual adaptation to an environment, without, at least as of yet, any involvement of consciousness whatsoever.Footnote 93 Lived purely in this way, such experiences, we can thus say, are characterized by a distinctive sort of “captivation”—though this is another specifically Heideggerian way of putting the matterFootnote 94—or put otherwise, are distinguished by a non-self-temporalized total absorption in the immediacy of behavior and its satiation, coming and going as bodily adaptations without being made manifest as the current moment of the selfsame streaming life in which they happen to arise (and so, without being given as an engagement with enduring things within the world, which as we’ve seen, self-temporalization alone makes possible). The investigation of this “realm,” of course, goes beyond phenomenology in the strict sense, and Husserl calls the existence of experiences that are lived fully without consciousness—or the “total null”—a phenomenological “hypothesis,”Footnote 95 although it is, evidently enough, a well-founded one empirically speaking; for so far as we can tell, sensing life, qua sensing, does sometimes go on fine “under the surface” of our own lives without ever temporalizing itself, without becoming self-consciousness (which is what Husserl means when he claims in his C-Manuscripts that “not every prominence is affective”Footnote 96), just as it seems to go on entirely for most other animals, and even infant humans. But what we can demonstrate phenomenologically, in any event, is that since it possesses its “tendency” already as a “disinhibition” or stimulation of behavior, simply by virtue of its “happening” as mere sense-experience, a moment of living that is self-temporalized, and so, lived consciously or as the “now” of the selfsame life, thereby becomes what we will have to call a mediated behavior, precisely insofar as the concrete behavior that is instinctually or habitually connected with it is placed at a remove from itself, as it were, so as to be oriented, as if from “without,” by what the life, as a whole, is “for.” This is to say that, insofar as it is conscious, a life is no longer always captivated in the immediacy of its behavior, but instead, has its “purposes.” At times, the instinctual or habitual behavior connected to a given sensing-experience is promoted by this guidance and cultivated further; but at times, it is reproached or directed otherwise.

Husserl may have never fully reached this point in his own descriptions of temporalization, yet in his C-Manuscripts, he at least seems to have been moving in the same direction. For it must have been just these considerations that led him to write that:

I bear in my present life my unholy, untrue, contradictory existence, facticity—but also in me, the idea of my true being, my should-be and precisely with it, the ideal capacity of self-criticism, or the critique of this facticity: at each point in time, the capacity and conceivability of another can-do, which would have determined the whole further run of my life otherwise, had I so acted.Footnote 97

But in what direction does this move our account? What seems motivated now (contra a position that Husserl, in at least his earlier work, too often assumed) is that a self-temporalizing life does not, in the first place, go on “projecting itself” simply so as to theoretically understand enduring transcendent being; rather, its self-temporalization is, at the basis of this, the occurrence of a responsibility for what it is to-be—or put otherwise, my own being’s being at issue. For to the extent that it is risen up to consciousness through this life’s self-temporalization, the current experience is obligated to be “for” the purposes of that greater life, even though at present these ends may contradict its immediate tendency.Footnote 98

Here, then, there is already a sense in which self-conflict is engendered in the temporalization of consciousness: Made manifest, the moment of living can always be given as if “out of step” with the “direction” of the total streaming, given the lived-tendency (stimuli of behavior) that already belongs to it as “mere” sensation-experience. But does this conflict point to something like a conflict or self-diremption of a “deeper” and more general (or perhaps, a more “primordial”) sort, which, coming from without a life itself, would prefigure or subtend that life’s self-temporalization? That is to say: Is this “being-there” of my own being as something I have to deal with—protentional openness as essentially the form of a life’s self-responsibility, or its concern for what it is to-be—something that is ultimately self-inflicted, a sort of “self-alienation” of sense-experiencing that would arise within an originally nonconscious life totally by its own power, as if a life wholly absorbed in the immediacy of its behavior could somehow strike down the absorbedness, the vanity, of this all by itself? Or rather, does it come—as Emmanuel Levinas, for one, will insist—from without that very life: namely, from the others, before whom, in the first place, I am brought to my responsibility? According to Levinas, the true significance of Husserl’s inability to ever ignore the hyletic sphere lies in this; it indicates a schism of sorts, effected within the non-egoic realm of sensibility or enjoyment, that has been produced by another who comes to humble a life and dispossess it of its immediacy by calling the living being made subject to account for itself.Footnote 99 But if we are to accept this, then the second claim implied by the Zahavian position will have to be definitively cast aside: self-temporalization, and so, consciousness per se, would have to be understood as first emerging from sociality, in the sense of being preconditioned by a life’s subjection to accountability before the others.

The themes that I’ve just hinted at, such as Levinas’s notion of the ethical relation, clearly all point beyond the confines of this essay and cannot be investigated in any detail here. Nevertheless, I’d like to point these themes out, because it’s precisely in order to keep open the direction in which they lead our thinking—and so ultimately, in which Husserl’s account of temporality leads our thinking—that I here oppose myself to the Zahavian claims I’ve critiqued. Self-consciousness, according to Zahavi, is “irreducible and fundamental” and cannot be explained “by reducing it to something more basic.”Footnote 100 Were we to accept this position, which I believe would simply hide away that which is most significant about the “human condition,” all thinking into the presuppositions of temporalizing self-consciousness would be arrested before it began. This work has instead been motivated by a desire to help keep open a future for the phenomenology of time.