1 Introduction

In this paper we discuss a novel field of research, quantum information biology (QIB). It is based on application of a novel quantum information formalism [110], quantum adaptive dynamics, outside of physics.Footnote 1 Quantum adaptive dynamics describes in the most general setting mutual adaptivity of information states of systems of any origin (physical, biological, social, political) as well as mutual adaptivity their co-observations, including self-observations (such as performed by the brain).

Nowadays quantum information theory is widely applied to quantum computers, simulators, cryptography, and teleportation. Quantum information theory is fundamentally based on quantum probability (QP).

We noticed that biological phenomena often violate the basic laws of classical probability (CP) [1231]; in particular, the law of total probability (LTP). Therefore in biology (treated widely as covering cognition and its derivatives: psychology and decision making, sociology and behavioral economics and finances) it is natural to explore one of the most advanced and well known nonclassical probability theories, namely, QP. This leads to the quantum information representation of biological information flows which differs crucially from the classical information representation.

Since any bio-system S is fundamentally open (from a cell to a brain or a social system), i.e., it cannot survive without contacts with environment (physical, biological, social), it is natural to apply the powerful and well developed apparatus of theory of open quantum systems [32] to the description of biological information flows. Adaptivity of the information state of S to an environment is a special form of bio-adaptivity: mutual adaptivity of information states of any pair of bio-systems \(S_1\) and \(S_2.\) Since quantum information theory provides a very general description of information processing, it is natural to apply it to model adaptive dynamics. This led us to quantum adaptive dynamics. Surprisingly we found that such an operational quantum formalism can be applied to any biological scale by representing statistical experimental data by means of QP and information. During the last years a general model representing all basic information flows in biology (from molecular biology to cognitive science and psychology and to evolution) on the basis of quantum information/adaptive dynamics was elaborated. In a series of our works [110] the general scheme of embedding of biological information processing into the quantum information formalism was presented and the foundational issues related to usage of quantum representation for macroscopic bio-systems, such as genome, protein,..., brain,..., bio-population were discussed in details and clarified.

Our theory can be considered as establishing the informational basis of decision making. Each bio-system (from a cell to a brain and to a social or ecological system) is permanently in process of decision making. Each decision making can be treated as a self-measurement or more generally as an adaptive reply to signals from external and internal environments.

On this basis, we believe that QIB is the best predictive tool to assess our future state on earth. We expect that this quantum-like operator formalism is a bold attempt to unify social and natural sciences.

2 Interrelation of Quantum Bio-Physics and Information Biology

This section is devoted to comparison of quantum bio-physics with QIB. Those who have been satisfied with a brief explanation given in footnote 1 can jump over this section.

First of all, we emphasize that our applications of the methods of QM to modeling of information flows in bio-systems have no direct relation to physical quantum processes in them, cf. [11]. For example, by considering quantum information processing by a cell or by a protein molecule [3, 5, 7, 8, 10] we do not treat either as a quantum physical system. In fact, already a single cell or even a protein molecule is too big to be treated in the conventional QM-framework, which was elaborated for microscopic systems.

Of course, in the quantum foundational community so-called macroscopic quantum phenomena have been discussed a lot. However, it seems that magnitudes of some important physical parameters of bio-systems do not match with scales of macro-quantum phenomena (e.g., Tegmark’s [33] critique of “quantum mind”, cf. with [11]). For example, bio-systems are too hot comparing with Bose-Einstein condensate or Josephson-junction. At the same time we can point to experiments of A. Zeilinger continued by Arndt, see [11], on interference for macro-molecules, including viruses. They were performed at high temperature. We can also point to recent studies claiming the quantum physical nature of the photo-synthesis, see again the review [11].

In any event in QIB we are not interested in all complicated problems of macro- and, in particular, bio-quantumness. In particular, by applying our formalism to cognition we escape involvement in intense debates about a possibility to treat the hot and macroscopic brain as processing quantum physical (entangled) states, since we do not couple our model to the “quantum physical brain project”, e.g., theories of Penrose [34] and Hameroff [35]. For example, the complex problem whether micro-tubules in the brain are able to preserve quantum physical entanglement (before its decoherence) for a sufficiently long time, e.g., to perform a step of quantum computation, is outside of our theory. QIB describes well processing of mental informational states, independently of who will be right: Penrose and Hameroff or Tegmark. (It is also possible that this debate will continue forever). The ability of a bio-system to operate with superpositions of information states including brain’s ability to form superpositions of mental states is the key-issue.

For a moment, there is no commonly accepted model of creation of superposition of information states by a bio-system, in particular, there is no proper neurophysiological model of creation of mental superposition. For the latter, we can mention a series of attempts to model states superposition with the aid of classical oscillatory processes in the brain, as it was proposed by J. Acacio de Barros and P. Suppes [20], including classical electromagnetic waves in the brain, see, e.g., for a model [36] proposed by A. Khrennikov. In these studies mental states are associated with classical physical waves or oscillators, the waves discretized with the aid of thresholds induce the probabilistic interference exhibited in the form of violations of LTP.

In general we consider violations of LTP by statistical data collected in bio-science, from molecular biology to cognitive psychology, as confirmation of the ability of bio-system to operate with states superpositions. In an experiment, in QM as well as in biology, we do not detect superposition of “individual information states” such as superposition of two classical waves. Informational states of bio-systems are probabilistic amplitudes. In QIB we discuss the ability of bio-systems to represent probabilities by vector amplitudes and operate with such amplitudes by using the operations which are mathematically represented as the matrix calculus. From this operational viewpoint an electron does not differ so much from a cell, or a brain, or a social system.

In a series of works, see [14] for references, it was shown that, for probabilistic data of any origin, violation of LTP leads to representation of states by probability amplitudes (usual complex or more general, so-called hyperbolic)- the constructive wave function approach. It might be that bio-systems really use this algorithm of production of amplitudes from probabilities—the quantum-like representation algorithm. Footnote 2 In a bio-system probability can be treated as frequency. And frequencies can (but need not) be encoded in oscillatory processes in bio-systems.

Finally, we speculate that the brain could, in principle, use a part of its spatial representation “hardware” (its deformation in the process of evolution) for the vector representation of probabilities and hence, for decision making and processing of information at the advanced level. For a moment, this is a pure speculation.

3 From Information Physics to Information Biology

In QIB, similarly to quantum physicsFootnote 3, we treat the quantum formalism as an operational formalism describing (self-)measurements performed by bio-systems.

Neither QM nor biology (treated widely as covering cognitive science and psychology) can explain why systems under study produce such random outputs—violating the CP-laws. Moreover, in QM, according to the Copenhagen interpretation, it is in principle impossible to provide some “explanation” of quantum random behavior, e.g., by using a more detailed description with the aid of so-called hidden variables. In spite of this explanatory gap, QM is one of the most successful scientific theories. One may hope that a similar operational approach would finally lead to creation of a novel and fruitful theory for bio-systems.

We remark that in recent studies of D’ Ariano et al. [3942] the quantum formalism was derived from a set of purely operational postulates reflecting features of a very general measurement scheme. Such an approach can be applied to QIB as a theory of (self-)measurements. However, one should carefully check matching of D’ Ariano’s postulates with decision making done by bio-systems (considered as self-measurements). It is natural to expect that some of these (physically natural) postulates have to be modified and that new postulates can be in use. This is an interesting project waiting for its realization.

We also emphasize that recently the informational interpretation of the quantum state started to play an important role in QM and, especially, in quantum information theory, see the works of A. Zeilinger and C. Brukner [4347], C. A. Fuchs with C. M. Caves, R. Schack, and D. Mermin [4851], and M. D’ Ariano et al [3942]. By this interpretation the QM formalism is about the information processing related to experiments. The wave function is not treated as a physical state of, e.g., an individual electron. It is treated as representing information about possible outcomes of experiments. This viewpoint matches well with Schrödinger’s treatment of the wave function as an expectation catalog (of possible outcomes) [52]. The adherents of the information interpretation also often refer to the views of N. Bohr and W. Heisenberg who treated QM operationally. However, here the situation is complicated, since, for example, Bohr’s views on the interpretation of the wave function changed many times during his life, see, for example, A. Plotnitsky for discussions [37, 38].

In its extreme subjective form the information interpretation is presented as QBism, quantum Bayesian approach—C. A. Fuchs with C. M. Caves, R. Schack, and D. Mermin, see, for example, [4851]. QBists really belief that the QM-formalism is simply a mathematical tool to assign subjective probabilities to expected outcomes of experiments. QBism’s position is very supporting for the part of QIB related to the project “quantum(-like) cognition”. Probabilities assigned to possible events by decision makers are subjective. It is worse with our more general project. Subjective probability, what would it mean for a cell? for a protein? for a social or ecological system?

Even for quantum cognition, we cannot simply (as C. A. Fuchs and his collaborators do in QM) assign a subjective probability to some event: “the brain produces it in some way”. By discussing the cognitive component of decision making it would be natural to try at least to imagine how a subjective probability is assigned to the concrete event.

One can speculate that, in fact, the probability which appears at the conscious level as the feeling of “subjective probability” is an esemble probability at the unconscious level. Unconscious has a plenty of factors for and against the possibility of occurrence of some event A. These factors are weighted by unconscious, so in the mathematical terms it operates with a probability measure corresponding to summation of weights of the factors in favor of A.

This unconscious-ensemble viewpoint to subjective probabilities in QM and in this way connection “quantum-mental” as the basis of QBism was advertised by one of the coauthors (AKH). During many years it was discussed with C. A. Fuchs, but his reaction was not supporting. Moreover, another author of this paper (IB) strongly rejects the unconscious-ensemble viewpoint on quantum probabilities which she otherwise interprets as subjective.

It is worse to present the viewpoint of C. A. Fuchs [53], footnote 14:

Most of the time one sees Bayesian probabilities characterized (even by very prominent Bayesians like Edwin T. Jaynes) as measures of ignorance or imperfect knowledge. But that description carries with it a metaphysical commitment that is not at all necessary for the personalist Bayesian, where probability theory is an extension of logic. Imperfect knowledge? It sounds like something that, at least in imagination, could be perfected, making all probabilities zero or one—one uses probabilities only because one does not know the true, pre-existing state of affairs. Language like this, the reader will notice, is never used in this paper. All that matters for a personalist Bayesian is that there is “uncertainty” for whatever reason. There might be uncertainty because there is ignorance of a true state of affairs, but there might be uncertainty because the world itself does not yet know what it will give – i.e., there is an objective indeterminism. As will be argued in later sections, QBism finds its happiest spot in an unflinching combination of “subjective probability” with “objective indeterminism.”

Thus, for Fuchs, the complete reduction of subjective probability to ensemble probability (even for ensembles of mental states) is impossible. Nature is a generator of “objective indeterminism.” The latter cannot be reduced to lack of knowledge. And it seems that “objective indeterminism” is the essence of subjective viewpoint on probability.

We remark that at the very beginning A. Zeilinger and C. Brukner did not emphasize so much the subjective probability viewpoint to QP, they stressed that QM is about information, that this is a step towards, so to say, information physics. However, the recent talk of A. Zeilinger at the conference “50 years of Bell theorem”, Vienna, June 2014, was very much in the QBism spirit. And this is not surprising. The interpretation of Zeilinger-Brukner is heavily based on the assumption that quantum randomness is irreducible. This idea that quantum randomness crucially differs from classical one was present already in von Neumann’s book [54]. He pointed out that quantum randomness is individual, e.g., even an individual electron is intrinsically random, and classical randomness is related to variation of states in an ensemble. Fuchs’ objective indeterminism and von Neumann-Zeilinger-Brukner’s irreducible randomness are close notions which can be seen from von Neumann’s description of the latter, cf. with the above citation of Fuchs.

Von Neumann pointed out [54], pp. 301–302, that, for measurement of some quantity R for an ensemble of systems (of any origin), “ it is not surprising that R does not have a sharp value..., and that a positive dispersion exists. However, two different reasons for this behavior a priori conceivable:

  1. 1.

    The individual systems \(S_1,\ldots , S_N\) of our ensemble can be in different states, so that the ensemble \([S_1,\ldots , S_N]\) is defined by their relative frequencies. The fact that we do not obtain sharp values for the physical quantities in this case is caused by our lack of information: we do not know in which state we are measuring, and therefore we cannot predict the results.

  2. 2.

    All individual systems \(S_1,\ldots , S_N\) are in the same state, but the laws of nature are not causal. Then in the cause of the dispersion is not our lack of information, but is nature itself, which has disregarded the principle of sufficient cause.”

In a series of papers [4347] this ideology was developed in the quantum information framework and it serves as the base of the Zeilinger-Brukner interpretation. It seems that QBism can proceed even without referring to the irreducible quantum randomness.

In principle, in QIB we can proceed as QBists, i.e., without looking for biological sources of irreducible randomness. On the other hand, it is important to pose the following stimulating question:

Is an individual bio-system intrinsically random?

In other words, Do bio-systems violate the principle of sufficient cause? Are their behaviors non-causal?

In principle, for human beings (and applications of QIB to cognition and decision making), one can try to couple the intrinsic quantum(-like) randomness with free will. Both can be treated as violations of the principle of sufficient cause. Thus if free will “exists” the randomness of decisions of human beings has to be similar to the intrinsic quantum randomness. Surprisingly, irreducibility of the quantum randomness cannot be justified without the free will assumption guarantying the freedom of choice for experimenters, choice of setting of experimental devices (orientations of polarization beam splitters in experiments on violation of Bell’s inequality).

In the recent debates on non/causal nature of quantum processes, the role of non/existence of free will was actively discussed. At the moment two opposite positions aggressively coexist. We remark that the rejection of free will, the position of G. ‘t Hooft [55] known as super-determinism, opens a possibility to treat QM as a deterministic theory, e.g. [56, 57]. (We also remark that a part of quantum foundation community thinks that the issue of non/existence of free will is irrelevant to the problem of quantum (in)determinism).

Exploring the free will assumption may be helpful to motivate the presence of intrinsic mental randomness and in this way to couple QIB even closer to Zeilinger-Brukner interpretation. However, by proceeding in this way one has to be ready to meet a new problem of the following type:

Have a cell, DNA or a protein molecule a kind of free will?

We can formulate the problem even another way around:

Is human free will simply a special manifestation of intrinsic randomness which is present on all scales of nature?

We remark that in general the problem of interrelation of classical and quantum probabilities and randomnesses is extremely complex. In some way it is easier for probabilities, since here we have satisfactory mathematical models, e.g., the Kolmogorov model [58] (1933) of CP. However, even in the classical case a commonly acceptable notion of randomness has not yet been elaborated, in spite tremendous efforts of the during the last one hundred years, see [59, 60] for details.

In fact, this position in application to mental phenomena and their unification with natural phenomena was expressed in a series of works, see, e.g., [61], of one of the coauthors of this paper (A. Khrennikov), where a version of Bohmian mechanics on information spaces was in use. We remark that some Bohmians, e.g., D. Bohm by himself and B. Hiley, interpreted the wave function as a field of information. But this information field was still defined on the physical space, because, for D. Bohm (as well as his predecessor L. De Broglie), the physical space was indisputable reality. In works of A. Khrennikov mental information fields were defined on “information space” reflecting hierarchic tree-like representation of information by cognitive systems (mathematically such mental trees can be represented with the aid of so called p-adic numbers [62]). However, later A. Khrennikov became less addicted to the idea of information reality.

The main problem of the information interpretation of QM is to assign a proper meaning to the notion of information. It is very difficult to do—especially by denying reality; one has to define information not about some real objectively existing stuffs, but information as it is by itself. Of course, one can simply keeps Zeilinger’s position (private discussions): information is a primary notion which cannot be expressed through other “primitive notions”. However, not everybody would be satisfied by such a solution of this interpretational problem.

In any event the information interpretation matches perfectly with our aims, although its creators may be not support the attempts to apply it outside of physics. (We remark that the position of A. Zeilinger was quite positiveFootnote 4). There is a chance that physicists using this interpretation would welcome the birth of quantum cognition and more generally QIB. There was no any chance to find understanding of physicists keeping to the orthodox Copenhagen interpretation – the wave function as the most complete representation of the physical state of an individual quantum system such as an electron.

4 Nonclassical Probability? Yes! But, Why Quantum Probability?

One may say: “Yes, I understood that the operational description of information processing in complex bio-systems can be profitable (independently from a possibility to construct a finer, so to say hidden variables, theory). Yes, I understand that bio-randomness is nonclassical and it is not covered by CP and hence classical information theory cannot serve as the base for information biology. But, why do you sell one concrete nonclassical probability theory, namely, QP and the corresponding information theory? It is possible, as Zeilinger suggested (see footnote 4), that, while QP and quantum information serve well for a special class of physical systems, their application to biology may meet hidden pitfalls. Yes, we agree that there is a logical gap: nonclassical does not imply quantum. Negation of CP is not QP.

Nevertheless, why exploring QP and quantum information are so attractive? First of all, because these are the most elaborated nonclassical theories. It is attractive to use their advanced methods. Then one may expect that some basic nonclassicalities of random responses of bio-systems can be described by the standard quantum formalism. This strategy can be fruitful, especially at the initial stage of development, as it was done for quantum cognition [14, 17, 29].

Now the crucial question arises:

Can the standard quantum formalism cover completely information processing by bio-systems?

Here “standard” refers to Schrödinger’s equation for the state evolution, the representation of observables by Hermitian operators and the von Neumann-Lüders projection postulate for quantum measurement.

Our answer is “no”. Already in quantum information one uses the open system dynamics and generalized observables given by positive operator valued measures (POVMs). It is natural to expect that they can also arise in bio-modeling. Another argument to departure from the standard quantum formalism is that in the constructive wave function approach, i.e., construction of complex probability amplitudes from data of any origin violating LTP [14], in general observables are represented not by Hermitian operators, but by POVMs and even by generalized POVMs which do not sum up to the unit operator [14].

A strong argument against the use of solely Hermitian observables in cognitive science was presented in [63]: it seems that the Hermitian description of the order effect for a pair of observables AB,  i.e., disagreement between \(A-B\) and \(B-A\) probabilities, is incompatible with \(A-B-A\) respectability: first A-measurement, then B-measurement, then again A-measurement and the first and the last values of A should coincide with probability 1. At the same time the standard opinion polls demonstrating the order effect have the property of \(A-B-A\) respectability. However, it seems that this problem is even more complicated: even the use of POVMs cannot help so much [63]. The counterargument based on non-double stochasticity of matrices of transition probabilities appearing in cognitive psychology was discussed in [14], see also references in it; other counterarguments were presented in works [20, 64, 65].

It seems that we have to go really beyond the quantum measurement formalism, beyond theory of quantum instruments. One of such novel generalizations was proposed by the authors [5, 10]—quantum adaptive dynamics.

5 Open Quantum Systems, Adaptive Dynamics

The dynamics of an isolated quantum system is described by the Schrödinger equation. In the standard quantum framework measurements are mathematically represented by orthogonal projectors \((P_i)\) onto eigen-subspaces corresponding to the observed values \((a_i)\). A quantum observable can be formally represented as a Hermitian operator \(A=\sum _i a_i P_i.\) The probability to obtain the fixed value \(a_i\) as the result of measurement is given by Born’s rule. Let a system have the physical state given by a normalized vector \(\psi \) of complex Hilbert space H. Then

$$\begin{aligned} p(a_i)= \langle P_i \psi \vert \psi \rangle = \Vert P_i \psi \Vert ^2 \end{aligned}$$
(1)

and the post-measurement state is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \psi _{a_i} = P_i \psi /\Vert P_i \psi \Vert . \end{aligned}$$
(2)

However, the situation that an isolated quantum system propagates in space-time and then suddenly meets a measurement device is too ideal. In the real situation a quantum system interacts with other systems, the presence of an environment cannot be ignored. In particular, measurement devices can also be treated as special environments. The corresponding part of quantum theory is known as theory of open quantum systems. Here dynamics of a state is described by quantum master equation, its Markovian approximation is known as equation Gorini–Kossakowski–Sudarshan–Lindblad (GKSL) equation [32].Footnote 5 This equation has numerous applications in quantum physics, especially quantum optics. It was applied to model decision making (in games of the Prisoners’ Dilemma type) in a series of papers [14], see also [30] for applications for decision making in political science. However, the GKSL-equation is an approximation and its derivation is based on a number of assumptions constraining essentially the domain of its applications. One of the main assumption is that the environment is huge comparing with the system under study. We cannot apply the GKSL-equation to model the state dynamics of an electron interacting with another electron or a few electrons considered as an environment.

The GKSL-dynamics can be operationally represented by completely positive trace preserving maps acting in the space of density operators, so called superoperators; adjoint maps describe observables given by POVMs. This approach is used in theory of quantum instruments.

In decision making typically there are two brain’s functions, as, e.g., sensation and perception, which interact and produce the output of one of them, e.g., the output-perception. In such a situation the GKSL-equation is not applicable. In our work [5] we developed general theory of quantum adaptive dynamics which, in particular, contains the standard theory of open quantum systems as describing a special sort of adaptivity, to a bath, see [10]. In our novel formalism the state dynamics is described by more general class of state transformers than in the standard theory. In particular, in theory of open quantum systems all state transformations, quantum operations, are completely positive maps. An adaptive dynamical map need not be completely positive nor even simply positive. The tricky point is that in quantum physics, for a given state, one can in principle measure any observable. It seems that in problems of decision making this assumption can be relaxed. We consider “generalized states” which permit measurements of only special (state-dependent) classes of observables; often just two observables,e.g., sensation and perception. The class of adaptive dynamical maps is essentially larger than the class of (completely) positive maps. This simplify essentially modeling of concrete phenomena, for example, recognition of ambiguous figures [9].

6 Conclusion

In this paper we discussed the main foundational issues of QIB, a very general theory of adaptivity of bio-systems represented in the quantum information framework. We repeat once again that all bio-systems are adaptive to a variety of environmental factors, including internal mental environments of cognitive systems. This adaptivity can be mathematically represented with the aid of theory of open quantum systems and more general quantum adaptive dynamics developed by the authors during last years [5, 10]. Our approach to adaptivity covers all scales of life: from genes, proteins, cells to brains, social, political, economic, and financial systems.

Among the basic factors leading to the use of the quantum formalism we can point to contextuality of probabilistic data generated by measurements on bio-systems implying nonclassicality of the representation of probability (non-Kolmogorovness). Thus in information biology one has to apply nonclassical probability models and QP is one of the most advanced and well tested among such models. Therefore it is natural to proceed with QP, although it is clear that it may be just one of possible nonclassical probability models serving for information biology. In logical terms the use of nonclassical probability means the use of non-Boolean logic and again quantum logic is one of the most advanced and well tested among nonclassical logic models.

In our foundational analysis of QIB we emphasized the role of various versions of the information interpretation of quantum states (Zeilinger, Brukner, Fuchs, Mermin, D’ Ariano). Such interpretations match well with attempts to apply the quantum formalism not only to the states of physical systems, but to information processors of any kind, especially bio-systems. (We repeat that bio-systems as well as quantum physical systems are fundamentally contextual and it seems that contextuality and context-adaptivity induce similarities in processing of information about these systems).

We pointed to the role of QBism in QIB. The subjective interpretation of QP matches well with its use in theory of decision making. QBism provides the most natural interpretation for quantum-like models of decision making by humans and complex cognitive systems (its applicability to information processing in, e.g., molecular biology, has to be analyzed in more detail).Footnote 6