Skip to main content

Davidson’s Meta-normative Naturalism and the Rationality Requirement

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Donald Davidson on Action, Mind and Value

Part of the book series: Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library ((LIAA))

  • 206 Accesses

Abstract

According to Michael Smith, normative realists cannot explain why people act on their normative judgments as reliably as they do, so we should embrace constructivism (or perhaps constitutivism) instead. Normative realists have countered by insisting that they can establish (1) that rationality typically requires people to act on their normative judgments and (2) that people typically are rational. I acknowledge that normative realists can establish (1) but argue that (2) poses problems both for non-naturalists and for reductive naturalists. I close by suggesting that Davidson’s non-reductive (or “anomalous”) form of naturalism may give normative realists a better chance of success.

This chapter is in its final form, and it is not submitted for publication anywhere else.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, e.g., Parfit (2011, Chap. 32), Enoch (2011, Chap. 7), and Scanlon (2014, lecture 4).

  2. 2.

    The “just too different” slogan is due to Enoch. See, e.g., his 2011, p. 4.

  3. 3.

    See Myers (2019). Davidson famously defends anomalous monism in the philosophy of mind in his 1970.

  4. 4.

    For the unfortunately named but still extraordinarily influential “argument from queerness,” see Mackie (1977, Chap. 1).

  5. 5.

    Unless I note otherwise, I will use the term "reason" throughout this paper to refer to normative reasons, not to operative or motivating reasons.

  6. 6.

    More could of course be said about what, exactly, distinguishes Humean accounts of deliberation from others, but this should do for our purposes here.

  7. 7.

    For Harman’s example, see his 1977, Chap. 1. McDowell (1995) raises similar questions about the implications to be drawn from examples of this sort.

  8. 8.

    As we shall see, one important question dividing philosophers here is how the motivating states explaining people’s actions are themselves to be explained.

  9. 9.

    Once again, while more could be said about what, exactly, distinguishes Kantian accounts of deliberation from others, this should do for our purposes here.

  10. 10.

    Since realists, as I understand them, deny that normative truths are mere products of rational deliberation, they will count as externalists in this sense.

  11. 11.

    See, e.g., Korsgaard (1996, Sect. 1.4) and Korsgaard (1997, Sect. 3).

  12. 12.

    Again, McDowell (1995) makes points of this broadly realist sort very forcefully.

  13. 13.

    Smith discusses his differences here with Williams in his 1995, Sect. 2.

  14. 14.

    Smith does not explicitly include (2); but see below, especially note 21.

  15. 15.

    For Smith’s own statement of this argument, see his 1994, Chap. 5.

  16. 16.

    For further discussion of this important worry, see, e.g., Dreier (1996).

  17. 17.

    For an example of a naturalist who takes this line, see Brink (1989, Chap. 3); for a non-naturalist, see Enoch (2011, Chap. 9).

  18. 18.

    As we shall see, I believe people’s desires necessarily aim, as a system, to get such reasons right, but that is a different matter.

  19. 19.

    See Smith (1994, especially Sect. 3.5) for more on his understanding of the notion of systematic justification as it relates to strength of will.

  20. 20.

    Revisionary naturalists could also define practicality rationality in terms of reason-responsiveness. But it is not easy to think of one who clearly does.

  21. 21.

    In Smith’s case, this has become clearer with his turn to constitutivism. See Smith (1994, Sect. 6.2), but also Smith (2013, 2015).

  22. 22.

    See especially her 1997 and 1999, but of course this theme runs throughout her 2009 and the papers collected in her 2008.

  23. 23.

    Many take their lead from John McDowell. See his 1979 and 1996.

  24. 24.

    See, e.g., Smith (1987). For a dissenting voice, see Little (1997).

  25. 25.

    In fact, he acknowledges it elsewhere in the same discussion (p. 436).

  26. 26.

    Parfit (2017, Chap. 12) provides a very powerful statement of this view.

  27. 27.

    See Myers (2012, especially the Postscript) for further development of this point.

  28. 28.

    This last point deserves more argument than I can give it here.

  29. 29.

    Scanlon develops this idea in his 1998, Chap. 1. See also his 2014, especially lecture 3.

  30. 30.

    I develop this point further in Myers (2012). Hieronymi (2009) also takes Scanlon to task here.

  31. 31.

    For more on this argument and its place in Davidson’s philosophy, see Myers and Verheggen (2016).

  32. 32.

    See Railton (1986) for a version of revisionary naturalism that proceeds along something like these lines.

  33. 33.

    This is what leaves him open to objections such as the ones Hieronymi offers in her 2009.

  34. 34.

    Scanlon discusses normative epistemology and the method of reflective equilibrium in his 2014, especially lecture 4.

  35. 35.

    See Davidson (1967, 1970, 1973), Myers and Verheggen (2016, especially Chap. 7), and Myers (2019).

  36. 36.

    See especially Davidson (1970). Davidson (1995) extends the argument from the philosophy of mind to metaethics.

References

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundation of ethics. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Causal relations. Reprinted in his Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events. Reprinted in his Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973). The material mind. Reprinted in his Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1995). The objectivity of values. Reprinted in his Problems of rationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (1996). Review of The moral problem. Mind, 105, 363–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1977). The nature of morality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hieronymi, P. (2009). The will as reason. Philosophical Perspectives, 23, 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1986). Skepticism about practical reason. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1997). The normativity of instrumental reason. Reprinted in her 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1999). Self-constitution in the ethics of Plato and Kant. Reprinted in her 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2008). The constitution of agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Little, M. (1997). Virtue as knowledge: Objections from the philosophy of mind. Nous, 31, 59–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1979). Virtue and reason. Reprinted in his Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1995). Might there be external reasons? Reprinted in his Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Two kinds of naturalism. Reprinted in his Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myers, R. (2012). Desires and normative truths: A holist’s response to the sceptics. Mind, 121, 375–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers, R. (2019). Davidson’s meta-normative naturalism. Journal of the History of Analytical Philosophy, 7, 48–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers, R., & Verheggen, C. (2016). Davidson’s triangulation argument: A philosophical inquiry. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2001). Rationality and reasons. In D. Egonsson (Ed.), Exploring practical philosophy: From action to value. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2006). Normativity. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 7). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vols. 1 and 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2017). On what matters (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1986). Moral realism. Philosophical Review, 95, 163–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2014). Being realistic about reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1987). The Humean theory of motivation. Mind, 97, 36–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1995). Internal reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55, 109–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2013). A constitutivist theory of reasons: Its promise and parts. LEAP: Law. Ethics, and Philosophy, 1, 9–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2015). The magic of constitutivism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 52, 187–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1980). Internal and external reasons. Reprinted in his Moral luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert H. Myers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Myers, R.H. (2021). Davidson’s Meta-normative Naturalism and the Rationality Requirement. In: Yang, S.CM., Myers, R.H. (eds) Donald Davidson on Action, Mind and Value. Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-7230-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics