Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Justice is a complex concept connected with liberty and law, ethics and politics; it is conceived as being beneficial to others when compared to courage, temperance and wisdom, virtues which are thought of as ‘self-regarding’. The history of concepts of justice from Antiquity to the Middle Ages and from then to the present helps us to see how this concept developed over time. Justice, one fundamental virtue or ideal among several, is generally considered as the foundation of social and political ethics. In its links with law and jurisprudence and in legal usage, justice has always had an ethical tinge as lawyers, when appealing to principles of ‘natural justice’, acknowledge that their system of law is meant to serve an ethical purpose and to follow ethically acceptable methods. In law as in social ethics, the concept of justice is acknowledged to have both a conservative and a reforming role. Conservative justice is to maintain the established order of things, taken to be entitlements, and assumes that everyone benefits from a stable social order, however imperfect. Reformative justice tries to remove imperfections in the redistribution of rights redistributing rights in order to make the social order more just or fair. It is linked with changes to the existing pattern of entitlements by taking account of merit and of need and is connected with the ideas of distributive justice .Footnote 1 Historically, the concept of justice has had ‘Ancient roots’ found in the Bible, in ancient drama (especially in Aeschylus ’ Oresteia), in philosophers such as Plato , (whose Republic is a treatise on justice, written as a dialogue between Socrates and some of his upper-class Athenian friends), or Aristotle (who in his Nicomachean Ethics gives an orderly account of the varieties of justice and analyzes justice as a virtue of character, in an effort to represent justice as “the disposition to give and receive neither too much nor too little”). At the same time, it is seen as a specific virtue. Justice has been widely discussed among jurists and theologians in the Middle Ages, and among philosophers of more modern times from Thomas Hobbes to Rawls and Robert Nozick .Footnote 2

In this chapter, I will focus on the concept of justice as it emerges during the Scottish Enlightenment in the social and political ethics developed by such Scottish philosophers of the eighteenth century as David Hume , Adam Smith , Lord Kames and Thomas Reid . As it has been noted by Knud Haakonssen , justice was treated mainly as a characteristic of the individual person within the various Scottish theories of natural jurisprudence.Footnote 3 Justice was considered by Scottish philosophers as a personal virtue, virtue meaning “the propensity to a certain type of behaviour and also the ability to appreciate the moral worth of such behaviour both in oneself and in others”.Footnote 4 In other words, the Scottish theorists dealt with justice as a characteristic of the individual and, paradoxically, they explained that concept as an institutionalized practice. Central to their theories was whether this virtue is an inherent part of human nature or whether it is artificial. Considered as a social or political virtue, bearing on the relations required by the very existence of community in a way that other virtues do not, the Scottish thinkers believed that their task was to explain why justice was distinguished from the other virtues by being the subject of the institutions of justice, namely adjudication, law and legislation.Footnote 5 For Hume —whose account of justice was extensive but narrowly interpreted—justice is an artificial virtue in the sense that it is the product of human conventions. Considering selfishness and limited generosity as qualities of the human mind,Footnote 6 Hume points out that “self-interest is the original motive to the establishment of justice” but “a sympathy with public interest is the source of the moral approbation which attends that virtue”,Footnote 7 and observes that justice lies in its utility in maintaining property as a condition of a stable society, a view criticized by other notable Scottish philosophers such as Lord Kames and Thomas Reid . Reid in particular, in criticizing Hume ’s theory of justice,Footnote 8 is considered as developing a rights-based theory arguing that justice’s utility is insufficient to distinguish it from natural virtues such as benevolence. On the other hand, Adam Smith , who has accepted many of Hume ’s ethical doctrines as well as the theories of the Ancients, mainly those of the Stoics and Cicero , developed in his The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) a richer theory of justice in an endeavor to connect it with the moral needs of individuals, relating justice to merit and injustice to demerit that consists in good or ill desert. In criticizing Hume ’s view that justice depends on utility, Smith coupled justice with beneficence as the two virtues directly concerned with our relationship to other people. He also rejected Hume ’s doctrine of the artificiality of justice, as he believed that justice is a natural virtue, based on the natural feeling of sympathy for the injured party, and it is the duty of man to make it perfect.Footnote 9 Although Smith has taken the characteristics of sympathy from Hume (who in the Treatise calls Sympathy, and in the Enquiry Benevolence, that which leads us to approve or disapprove of moral excellences and defects), he distances himself from him as he calls the sympathy for the person performing the action ‘direct sympathy’ and that for the person who is acted upon ‘indirect’.Footnote 10 Hume and Smith differ in a fundamental respect, as it has been noted, because “for Hume placing the observer in an imaginary position in another’s situation means sharing the pleasures or advantages of the agent or the recipient of the action, while for Smith it means feeling the passions of the agent or recipient of the action in order to carry out a comparison with the passions that they really display”.Footnote 11 The above-mentioned Scottish philosophers connect justice with liberty and equality as well as with law, rights, duties and obligations, and develop theories of justice that reflect their concern with moral and political problems of their age, and with empirical studies of human nature and of natural jurisprudence.Footnote 12 My purpose in what follows is to approach Hume ’s and Reid ’s views on justice in the main as developed in their moral, social and political theories in order to show, explore and explain their differences.

The Scots’ moral theory is perhaps the most studied aspect of their thought, and is connected with recent interest in their political and social theory. As empiricists, the Scots thought it necessary to consult experience in order to know about society.Footnote 13 Their debate on the foundations of morals started with Francis Hutcheson , David Hume and Adam Smith , while Thomas Reid continued the discussion in a critical way by reflecting on their theories.Footnote 14

Hume ’s basic claim is that all our knowledge is based on what we experience through the senses, and his ethical theory as a whole can be considered the ‘most important example of empiricist moral philosophy’. He exposes his moral theory in the third book of the Treatise and the Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, examining historically and critically moral theories, from antiquity till his age, dealing mainly with the moral philosophy of his predecessors: Hobbes , Locke , Grotius , Pufendorf , Mandeville and Hutcheson .Footnote 15 In the Treatise, Hume approaches in a psychological way the problem of ‘how morality is constituted, that is, what forces are capable of forming morality ’, while in the Enquiry he approaches morality ‘as a given social fact’.Footnote 16 As in his epistemology so in his moral philosophy, Hume tries to explain how a common world is created out of private and subjective elements; for that reason, examining the foundations of morality , he holds that they are, on the one hand, private and subjective, connecting with the principle of ‘oughts’, which by nature activates forces in our life, such as passions, and on the other hand, public and objective, as they bind people together and make a society possible. In this sense, the latter has a function that is dependent upon the existence of a common moral language, as every language includes, according to him, a set of terms by which we express praise or blame.Footnote 17 Hume was critical of the existing ‘foundation-theories’ of morality and law according to which moral and legal evaluation had an ultimate source in either the reasoning faculty or the moral sense. With his emotivist moral theory, and relying on the experience of sense and feeling, which was the key idea of Hutcheson ’s ethical theory,Footnote 18 Hume was concerned with the origin of evaluation and with trying to show how solid are the moral distinctions ‘derived from sentiment’: “All morality depends upon our sentiments; and when any action or quality of the mind, pleases us after a certain manner, we say it is virtuous; and when the neglect, or non-performance of it, displeases us after a like manner, we say that we lie under an obligation to perform it”.Footnote 19 Hutcheson ’s influence on Hume seems undeniable. Nevertheless, although he seems to argue in the Treatise that moral distinctions are derived from a moral sense, he uses in his discussions of Book III the terms ‘sentiment’ and ‘feeling’ instead of ‘moral sense’. As we know, Hume and Smith were hostile to the idea of a special sense of justice, and both analyzed the moral sentiments in general in terms of the operations of sympathy. Hume explicitly acknowledges the special character of the feeling of approval, and thinks that Hutcheson ’s description of the moral sense as disinterested approval of the disinterested motive of benevolence, being recognized by him as the whole virtue, is simple and mistaken.Footnote 20 Trying to explain the moral sentiments, Hume pursued a historical examination of justice, which Smith did not follow. Hume tried to stress the validity of the evaluations we make within social and historical contexts, especially in his theory of justice which is considered of great importance as it helped Adam Smith to develop a number of proposals included in his own theory of justice and jurisprudence, which in turn gave a new and original answer to the philosophical question of how legal criticism is possible.Footnote 21

Hume developed his ethical theory in Book III of A Treatise of Human Nature, published in 1739–1740, addressed to specialists in philosophy, and then in his An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, first published in 1751, a book written for an educated general public. His account of justice has a fundamental role in both books, as in the Treatise he gives priority to the doctrine that justice is an artificial virtue, while in the Enquiry he concentrates on the utility of justice. He makes a distinction between nature and artifice in Book III of the Treatise, and in Part III of this Book, he includes his claim that some virtues, such as love of one’s children, beneficence, generosity, clemency, moderation, temperance and fragility, are natural, embedded as fundamental propensities of human nature itself, and points out that as individuals we respond to these virtues with approbation. In Part II of this Book, he quotes the traditional definition of justice as “a constant and perpetual will of giving every one his dueFootnote 22 and contrasts these natural virtues to the artificial virtues, such as justice, fidelity and allegiance. He distinguishes nature and artifice, and divides natural from artificial causes, which are instituted by men conventionally, clarifying as far as justice is concerned that both, nature and artifice, coexist. This aspect of his thought is more apparent when he tries to answer the question, ‘Whether justice is a Natural or Artificial Virtue?’Footnote 23 He is convinced that the sense of justice arises artificially and necessarily from education and human conventions.Footnote 24 Nevertheless, when discussing the moral character of justice, Hume clarifies in the Treatise that it is an artificial invention to a certain purpose, but also a natural tendency to protect the good of mankind.Footnote 25

Hume has been criticized because in his system the ideas of justice and of injustice are connected mostly with the idea of property and concern property arrangements.Footnote 26 He describes then how the notions of property, promises and governments were instituted as social artifices and tries to show why these are taken to have a moral dimension. He takes the approach that justice is not established as a moral virtue by means of a natural motive, as it comes into existence as a social practice or institution: “No virtue is more esteem’d than justice, and no vice more detested than injustice; nor are there any qualities, which go father to the fixing the character, either as amiable or odious. Now justice is a moral virtue, merely because it has that tendency to the good of mankind; and, indeed, is nothing but an artificial invention to that purpose. The same may be said of allegiance, of the laws of nations, of modesty, and of good-manners”.Footnote 27 Hume , discussing the origin of justice and property, is eager to show how we acquire the proper passion, and thus the moral obligation, to adhere to it and tries to answer to two questions, viz., “concerning the manner, in which the rules of justice are establish’d by the artifice of men; and concerning the reasons, which determine us to attribute to the observance or neglect of these rules a moral beauty and deformity”.Footnote 28 According to him, justice is an absolutely necessary ingredient in any kind of social life, it is a remedy to some and connected with the possession of external goods, and applies primarily to property. To the question ‘how the artifices of justice come into being as means for the promotion of our interests, and how our giving moral approbation to those who follow the artifices’ restraints’, Hume gives the answer that the “moral obligation” is a natural sentiment, and has to be just as a consequence of our sympathizing with the “public interest”,Footnote 29 or the “interest of the society”,Footnote 30 the “good of society”,Footnote 31 the “public good” or ‘the good of society’Footnote 32 or the “good of mankind”.Footnote 33 In concluding, he remarks that the artifices of justice are useful to society, like all useful things,Footnote 34 and beneficial to the members of society we sympathize with, especially with the fellow-citizens of our nation.Footnote 35

Hume acknowledges the existence of natural moral sentiments that operate through sympathy, an involuntary, physiological reaction towards the joys and sufferings of others. At the same time, he recognizes that sympathy is a partial and unreliable mechanism as it gives way to self-interest or to other emotions, although in his Enquiry he agrees with Hutcheson , in this differing from Hobbes , in holding that man is capable of a disinterested regard for others and he seems to describe “the evolution of the artifices of justice as depending on their serving the interests of each person who participates in them”.Footnote 36 Hume had also discriminated in ethical experiences between the functions of reason and sentiment, in this making an important advance upon Hutcheson , who did not assign to reason a distinct and special office. Adam Smith agrees with Hume that morality is a matter of sentiment and traces the moral sentiments to an origin in sympathy, but whereas Hume stresses our sympathy with people in general, Smith stresses our sympathy with the person or persons principally involved. For him, to sympathize with the real or supposed sentiments of our fellow-men is to approve them.

Hume ’s account of justice is characterized as complicated and inconsistent, and it is developed not only in the Treatise or the second Enquiry, but also in his Essays, such as “Of the Original Contract” or “On National Characters”, as well as in his History of England. It has been noted that he has a narrow idea of justice, as he applies justice primarily to the rights of property; although in the Treatise he uses the term ‘fidelity’ for respecting and keeping promises and contracts, sometimes including this in justice, treating a promise as a voluntary transfer of the right to future goods or services. Hume was certain that justice’s artificiality lies in its dependence on the man-made conventions which create property rights; his goal was to defend the stability of property and society as he thought that individual rights are essential to that goal. So he focused his attention on property rights, and his moral theory is classified as rights-based in contrast to theories based on need or some sort of merit or desert,Footnote 37 as he disagrees with the common view that restricts ‘merit or moral worth’ to moral virtues as contrasted with natural abilities.Footnote 38 Baier , examining Hume ’s theory of justice as a whole in all his works, points out that in the Treatise he has a narrow notion of justice “as comprising merely honesty in property matters, and fidelity to promises and contracts”, while in his Essays and History of England he treats justice as a subject matter of jurisprudence and expands the concept beyond considerations of property.Footnote 39 Hume insists that there is no natural affection for or love of mankind in general, and that self-interest can run against the common interest as our partiality affects not only our actions but also our conceptions of virtue. Nevertheless, he believes that in small or large societies, such as nations, especially “as members of a political society, with which we have a common interest”, we can have a concern for the public interest by means of sympathy for those who are harmed by unjust actions, and that we come in this way “to a moral approbation of justice and a disapprobation of injustice”.Footnote 40 That opinion coincides with his view that justice and fidelity are social virtues, highly useful and absolutely necessary to the well being of mankind.Footnote 41

Hume ’s general theory of morals concerns the morally good and bad, virtue and vice. His account of justice is considered as part of a larger account of the moral and political virtues in general. Actually, in the Treatise, in the Section “Of the Origin of Justice and Property”, he discusses the moral quality of justice and raises the question, “Why we annex the idea of virtue to justice, and of vice to injustice”.Footnote 42 Nevertheless, his chief concern is to secure social order by the establishment of stable principles, (that is, a reliable legal system) for dealing with property relations and social cooperation in the organization of commerce. Additionally, in his theory of justice, Hume deals with the origin of justice and the moral value of justice, and although he wants to be precise sometimes he is not clear or consistent. According to Haakonssen , regarding the latter part of Hume ’s theory, that is the moral value and obligation of justice, which was criticized by Smith , his view can be formulated in the following way, including two solutions: “Either moral value and obligation have to be accounted for in terms of sympathy (Treatise solution), though that requires a concreteness of object which is just not present in the case of justice in the ‘anonymous’ society, that is the society beyond the family group; or they are accounted for by means of ‘fellow-feeling’ (Enquiry solution), which avoids this difficulty, but which is so optimistically forward looking, and in that sense rationalistic, that it is not to be found in ordinary men, but is rather a philosophers’ speculation”.Footnote 43 It has been observed that Hume wrote as a philosophical anthropologist, and not as a reformer, unlike Bentham and Mill . Both of the latter wanted to reform our moral outlook rather than merely to explain it. An ethical naturalist, like Hume , was looking to the function of the rules of justice in social life, although he went beyond an analysis of the emotions expressed in judgments of justice.Footnote 44

Hume ’s theory of justice was criticized by three other eminent Scottish philosophers, Lord Kames and Thomas Reid , both of whom attacked Hume ’s view that justice is artificial, and by Adam Smith , who having Hume in mind generally criticizes the view that justice depends on utility.Footnote 45 In what follows I shall focus on Reid ’s account of justice, as he was the immediate and most important critic of Hume ’s philosophy. It is well known that Reid , the “fit representative of the Scottish philosophy”,Footnote 46 was aroused to philosophical activity by the speculations of Berkeley and Hume , as both had assumed and carried to their logical conclusions the scholastic doctrine of representative perception, that is, perception by means of intermediate ideas. Reid protested in the name of Common Sense against the special principles and inferences of Berkeley and Hume , and against the pronounced skepticism of the latter. He criticized Hume ’s theory of ideas, first set out by Locke , and insisted that it is not ideas but objects which are immediately present to the mind. Reid therefore tried to examine and undermine the ideal theory of sense-perception and to establish the doctrine of common sense. In his theory of perception, judgment plays an important role, as it is immanent in every perception, and one could say it is the basis of the Common Sense philosophy. Reid distinguishes between necessary judgments and contingent judgments, and calls the latter natural. Contingent judgments are always connected with perception; for that reason, their subject is not an idea but the external object. For Reid , as well as James Oswald, James Beattie and Dugald Stewart, morality has been understood as a power of judgment, not inherently different from other forms of reasoning.Footnote 47 Reid emphatically rejects the doctrines of Hutcheson , Hume and Smith on the nature of virtue as we can understand from the following passage: “The formal nature and essence of that virtue which is the object of moral approbation consists neither in a prudent prosecution of our private interest, nor in benevolent affections towards others, nor in qualities useful or agreeable to ourselves or to others, nor in sympathizing with the passions and affections of others, and in attuning our own conduct to the tone of other men’s passions; but it consists in living in all good conscience—that is, in using the best means in our power to know our duty, and acting accordingly”.Footnote 48 Reid constructs his moral theory according to his theory of knowledge, acknowledging that “by our moral faculty, we have both the original conceptions of right and wrong in conduct, of merit and demerit, and the original judgments that this conduct is right, that is wrong; that this character has worth, that demerit”.Footnote 49 In his Essays on the Active Powers of Man, which appeared in 1788, Reid enlarged on his moral theory which is connected to his epistemology and to his account of will and action as well as to virtue in general. In his moral theory Reid distinguishes the will, which is appropriate to the power and act of determining, from sensations, affections and desires; he states principles of morals connected (a) to virtue in general and (b) to the different branches of virtue. Taking will as the power that affects the acts of the understanding in attention, deliberation, and resolution or purpose, he points out that some acts of will are transient and others permanent and that all acts, virtuous or immoral, are always voluntary. Reid considers that some things in human conduct merit approbation and praise, others blame and punishment, and thinks that involuntary acts deserve neither. According to him, what is necessary cannot be the object of praise or blame, as men are culpable for omitting as well as for performing acts; for that reason we ought to use the best means to learn our duty. It is our duty to fortify ourselves against temptation, to prefer a greater to a lesser good, to follow the intuitions of nature and to act towards another as we should wish him to act towards us; an act that deserves moral approbation must be believed by the agent to be morally good. His ethical theory has a rational basis as it implies judgment as perception does, but in a different way, because in the case of the external senses sensations precede judgment, while in moral perception “the feeling is the consequence of the judgment, and is regulated by it”. Thus, he adds, “an account of the good conduct of a friend at a distance gives me a very agreeable feeling, and a contrary account would give me a very uneasy feeling; but these feelings depend entirely upon my belief of the report”.Footnote 50

Reid was a close friend of Henry Home , Lord Kames , and his criticism on justice is similar to that of Kames . Henry Home, a judge and jurist who had a reputation as a moral philosopher, included in his Essays on the Principles of Morality and Natural Religion (1751) a chapter (Essay II, ch. 7) on justice and injustice. He refutes Hume ’s view that justice is an artificial virtue and shows that man has a variety of principles, such as self-love, benevolence, sympathy and utility, consonant to the divine will; he has also as a separate principle, in his nature and constitution, a moral feeling or conscience by which he judges all his motives to action. Additionally, examining Hume ’s theory, he shows that it annihilates all real distinction between right and wrong in human actions.Footnote 51 Reid describes justice in terms of a distinction between a favour and an injury. Favour and injury are benefits or hurts done intentionally to some other person or persons, and produce naturally gratitude or resentment, respectively. He defines justice and injustice in terms of rights and the violation of rights, and thinks that justice is a positive respect for the rights of others that is connected with charity or favour.Footnote 52 Whatever one thinks of Reid ’s theory of justice as a whole, his classification of rights is helpful in pinpointing the deficiencies of Hume ’s account. Answering Hume ’s original question about the nature of this fundamental virtue, he believes that justice is a natural rather than an artificial virtue, and admittedly, consistent with his philosophy, a complex one, involving judgment as well as sentiment: “When a man’s natural rights are violated, he perceives intuitively, and he feels that he is injured. The feeling of his heart arises from the judgment of his understanding; for if he did not believe that the hurt was intended, and unjustly intended, he would not have that feeling. He perceives that injury is done to himself, and that he has a right to redress. The natural principle of resentment is roused by the view of its proper object, and excites him to defend his right […]. These sentiments spring up in the mind of man as naturally as his body grows to its proper stature”.Footnote 53 By arguing that the utility of justice is insufficient to distinguish it from natural virtues, such as benevolence, which also have utility, Reid produces an alternative to Hume ’s theory of justice as an artificial virtue.Footnote 54 Criticizing Hume ’s conception of justice as restricted to property and fidelity to contracts, he tried to provide an alternative account through an examination of a more generally accepted notion of justice.Footnote 55

In his Essays on the Active Powers of Man, he calls on his knowledge of jurisprudence to list the six respects in which a man may be injured, and indicates six branches of justice or rights: namely, safety of one’s person, safety of one’s family, liberty, reputation, property and fidelity to engagements. He notes that, “A man may be injured, first, in his person, by wounding, maiming or killing him; secondly, in his family, by robbing him of his children, or any way injuring those he is bound to protect; thirdly, in his liberty, by confinement; fourthly, in his reputation; fifthly, in his goods or property; and, lastly, in the violation of contracts or engagements made with him”.Footnote 56 He claims that man has natural rights , in the sense of being “innate” to life, family, friends, liberty and reputation, which, in contrast to property and contractual rights, are “founded upon the constitution of man, and antecedent to all deeds and conventions of society”.Footnote 57 Of all the rights cited above, the last two are acquired “not grounded upon the constitution of man, but upon his actions”. Reid notes that Hume deals in his Treatise with property and fidelity to engagements; these are called acquired rights, as they are the result of a preceding act; occupation, labour or transfer, in the case of property; promise, in the case of engagements. In his critique, Reid maintains that these acquired rights depend on natural rights and so are not wholly artificial or conventional.Footnote 58 He also argues that distributive justice is absent from Hume ’s account, and thinks that the right to the acquisition of property of one individual can be restricted by the right to subsistence of another individual, “as justice, as well as charity, requires, that the necessities of those who, by the providence of God, are disabled from supplying themselves, should be supplied from what might otherwise be stored for future wants”.Footnote 59 Connecting the conception of justice with the sense of duty or obligation,Footnote 60 he regards “injustice as the violation of rights and justice as yielding to every man what is his right”.Footnote 61 Believing that “the direct intention of Morals is to teach the duty of men: that of Natural Jurisprudence to teach the rights of men”, he gives the above-mentioned list of rightsFootnote 62 that are natural in contrast to Hume ’s property rights that are acquired. Additionally, Reid points out that rights can exist before or outside political society, and he extends justice beyond a concern for property rights linking justice as a fundamental virtue with man’s natural rights . In his discussion of property, although he admits that the right of property generally is “not innate, but acquired” and grounded “not upon the constitution but upon man’s actions”Footnote 63; he insists that property can be acquired initially through occupation and labour, in a state of nature, prior to political convention; in another sense, the right of property it is natural as it flows from man’s natural right of liberty,Footnote 64 which is a freedom “to act in gratifying desires, a positive rather a negative liberty , as it is restricted not simply by what would hurt others but also by the duties of an individual to God and to self”.Footnote 65 Reid wanted to criticize Hume ’s neglect of the “natural rights ” in his theory of justice and make a distinction between innate or natural rights and adventitious or acquired rights, claiming that the former do not presuppose any human action, whereas acquired rights do.Footnote 66

Reid wanted to refute Hume ’s view that justice, meaning property rights, is artificial and in his manuscript notes of his lectures on jurisprudence he focus more on the topic of specific rights than on the concept of justice. In his lectures, which clarify his own social, moral and political thought, he defines justice as abstaining from injury and distinguishes between commutative and distributive justice . Dealing briefly with commutative justice that is described in terms of rights and defined as “fair dealing, honesty, integrity”, he then turns to a definition of distributive justice , in its strict and proper sense, as “the Justice of a Judge in executing the Laws and distributing Rewards and Punishments”.Footnote 67 Reid , in his Lectures on jurisprudence Footnote 68 as in his Active Powers, was more preoccupied with Hume ’s account of property rights than with a general analysis of justice. His central question of whether justice is artificial or natural in his practical ethics was mostly a critique of Hume ’s attack on the natural law tradition. Reid propounded in the eighteenth century an account of justice stressing the obligation to help the needy as a requirement of justice that was based on theology. Connecting religion and politics, he draws an analogy between a family and mankind as the family of God, and maintains that ‘justice as well as charity’ makes the same requirement for ‘the family of God’ as for a conventional family with regard to the necessities of those members who cannot fend for themselves, making this a duty of strict obligation. Reid acknowledges the strict obligations of special relationship to family, friends and close associates, as well as other obligations of keeping faith in promises, contracts and shunning deceit.Footnote 69

D. D. Raphael , in his valuable book Concepts of Justice, when referring to Reid ’s claim that there is an essential connection between justice and rights, and to Hume ’s view of justice in terms of property rights, believes that both were mistaken, because there can be justice in the absence of rights and rights in the absence of justice. Raphael himself has accepted a distinction between rights of action and rights of recipiency, that nowadays are described by theorists as liberty-rights and claim-rights, pointing out that both are more closely connected with obligation than with justice. Nevertheless, he concludes that the association of justice with rights chiefly concerns claim-rights, that is, the right to receive equality of opportunity in the sense of moral rights.Footnote 70

It is worth noting that a common factor in the moral theories of both Hume and Reid is linked to the word improvement. Hume concluded his Treatise by claiming that as human beings we have a capacity for sharing good and ills through sympathy, acting for the common good, and he believes that a better understanding of our nature can serve to improve our understanding of human morality .Footnote 71 Reid , conversely, by focusing on men’s rights and mainly on their duties, acknowledges the positive role of the teaching of morals through a system of natural jurisprudence, and accords to the government a role in the improvement of the moral character of the individual.Footnote 72 In conclusion, I would like to add that all the Scottish thinkers of the Enlightenment, since the Act of Union with England in 1707, were concerned with the moral dimensions of modernization and the economic improvement of their commercial or civil society; institutions, such as justice, law, rights and obligations were highly valued by them since they wanted a stable society and government in order to secure the future. It is not surprising then that rights and justice were crucial to them and a matter of wide discussion.