Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

3.1 Introduction

Is coherence necessary for (epistemic) justification, in that one’s beliefs are justified only if one’s belief system is coherent? Is coherence sufficient for justification, in that one’s beliefs are justified if one’s belief system is coherent?Footnote 1 Is coherence truth-conducive, in that coherence implies a high probability of truth, or in that coherence implies a higher probability of truth, or in that, ceteris paribus, greater coherence implies a greater probability of truth? These questions are important, difficult, and have been widely discussed.Footnote 2 It would be helpful in answering such questions, it seems, if we had an account of coherence. It would be especially helpful if we had a quantitative account of coherence. I develop an account of that sort (a quantitative account) where coherence is defined (in large part) in terms of probability—a quantitative probabilistic account of coherence.Footnote 3

I do not aim to show that the account developed, hereafter “(CR),” is correct (or adequate), or even that it is preferable to all extant alternative accounts of coherence. I aim, rather, to show that at least in certain respects (CR) is preferable to (at least some of) the main extant probabilistic accounts of coherence: (i) Igor Douven and Wouter Meijs’s account (2007), hereafter “(CDM),”Footnote 4 (ii) Branden Fitelson’s account (2003, 2004), hereafter “(CF),”Footnote 5 (iii) Erik Olsson’s account (2002, 2005a), hereafter “(CO),”Footnote 6 and (iv) Tomoji Shogenji’s account (1999, 2001), hereafter “(CS).” I leave it for further investigation whether (CR) is preferable all things considered to (CDM), (CF), (CO), and (CS), whether (CR) is preferable all things considered to all alternative probabilistic accounts of coherence (extant or not) in addition to (CDM), (CF), (CO), and (CS),Footnote 7 and whether (CR) is preferable all things considered to all nonprobabilistic accounts of coherence.Footnote 8

The paper is organized as follows. In Sect. 3.2, I set out some desiderata for an adequate account of coherence, and clarify the notion of a “probabilistic” account of coherence. In Sect. 3.3, I explain, in the following order, (CS), (CO), (CDM), (CF), and (CR). Then, in Sect. 3.4, I test the accounts against some cases. I contend that (CR), but not (CS), (CO), (CDM), or (CF), tests well against each case. Next, in Sect. 3.5, I relate (CR) to an important, but little discussed, problem for standard varieties of coherentism, viz., the “Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs.” Last, in Sect. 3.6, I conclude.

3.2 Preliminaries

3.2.1 Some Desiderata for an Adequate Account of Coherence

I take there to be at least three desiderata for an adequate account of coherence. First, an adequate account of coherence should imply that (a) coherence and incoherence come in degrees, (b) logical consistency is insufficient for coherence, (c) the degree to which a set of claims is coherent or incoherent is independent of the ordering of the claims in the set, and (d) no particular size (greater than 1) is needed for a (finite) set of claims to have a degree of coherence or incoherence.Footnote 9 Suppose S 1 = {p, q, r}, S 2 = {q, r, s}, S 3 = {q, p, r}, and S 4 = {p, q, r, ∼p}, where:

  • p = No ravens are black;

  • q = This bird is a raven;

  • r = This bird is black;

  • s = Some but very few ravens are black.Footnote 10

S 1 is more incoherent (or has a higher degree of incoherence) than S 2; this illustrates (a). S 2 is logically consistent but not coherent (q, r, and s do not “hang together” in the requisite sense); this illustrates (b). S 1 and S 3 differ in the ordering of “p,” “q,” and “r,” and yet S 1 and S 3 have the same degree of incoherence; this illustrates (c). S 2 and S 4 differ in size, and yet each set has a degree of incoherence (S 4’s being greater than S 2’s); this illustrates (d).

One terminological note is in order. I use the expression “coherence value” so that any degree of coherence is a coherence value, any degree of incoherence is a coherence value, and the neutral point between incoherence and coherence (if there is such a point) is a coherence value.

Second, an adequate account of coherence should be intuitive or plausible (or at least should not be highly counterintuitive or implausible) in what it implies or does not imply with respect to particular cases (artificial or otherwise). Suppose some account implies that S 4 is maximally coherent. This implication is not intuitive, in fact, is highly counterintuitive, and so counts (strongly if not decisively) against the account. Or suppose some account is silent on S 4 in that it has no implication with respect to S 4’s coherence value (or even with respect to whether S 4 has a coherence value). The account thus fails to imply what seems obvious, viz., that S 4’s coherence value is very (perhaps maximally) low, that S 4’s coherence value is less than S 2’s coherence value, and so on. This counts against the account.

Third, an adequate account of coherence should be explanatory. Suppose some account implies that S 4 is incoherent, but only because the account has a proviso to the effect that S 4 is incoherent. This counts (though perhaps only weakly) against the account. The account should explain why, and not merely imply that, S 4 is incoherent.Footnote 11

(CDM), (CF), (CO), (CR), and (CS) all imply (a)–(d) and so all satisfy the first desideratum.Footnote 12 But not all of those accounts satisfy the second and third desiderata. Or so I argue in Sect. 3.4.

3.2.2 Probabilistic Accounts of Coherence

Let’s say that a “probabilistic” account of coherence is an account on which coherence is defined (at least in large part) in terms of probability.Footnote 13 Here is an example. Let S = {p 1,..., p n }. Then, on the “joint probability” account, “(CJ),” the degree to which S is coherent, “C J(S),” is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{J}}}(S) = \Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge \ldots \wedge {p_n}} \right). $$

(CJ) is implausible.Footnote 14 But, still, (CJ) serves as an example of a probabilistic account of coherence.

Two additional preliminary points are in order. First, on probabilistic accounts of coherence a set of claims can have different coherence values on different probability distributions, indeed, can be coherent on some probability distributions and incoherent on others.Footnote 15 It will help to consider an example. Suppose we have a deck of cards and randomly draw a card from the deck. Let S = {p 1, p 2}, where:

  • p 1 = The card selected is a heart;

  • p 2 = The card selected is red.

Suppose the deck of cards is standard, so that:

p 1

p 2

Pr

T

T

0.25

T

F

0

F

T

0.25

F

F

0.5

On this probability distribution, \( {C_{\mathrm{J}}}(S)=\Pr \left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_2}} \right)=.25 \). Suppose instead the deck of cards is nonstandard in that each of the 26 red cards is a heart, so that:

p 1

p 2

Pr

T

T

0.5

T

F

0

F

T

0

F

F

0.5

On this probability distribution, \( {C_{\mathrm{J}}}(S)=\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge {p_2}} \right)=.5 \). (CJ) thus implies that S’s coherence value is greater on the second probability distribution than on the first.

Second, a probabilistic account of coherence per se is neutral on the determinants (other than the axioms of the probability calculus) of the probabilistic facts in a given case. Here Shogenji (speaking in terms of beliefs and not in terms of claims) gives a disclaimer to the effect that his project is to give a characterization of coherence but not to identify what relations are responsible for coherence:

This paper does not discuss what makes beliefs (more) coherent; it characterizes coherence of beliefs without attempting to decide what relations—logical, explanatory, etc.—are responsible for it. Once we separate the characterization of coherence from what is responsible for it, our task is fairly straightforward, but its precise formulation is still helpful in understanding its bearing on truth. (1999, 338, emphasis Shogenji’s)

So one can accept a probabilistic account of coherence, and yet allow that the coherence facts in a given case, though directly determined by the probabilistic facts in the case, are indirectly determined by, say, the explanatory facts in the case—by allowing that at least certain of the probabilistic facts in a given case are determined by (in part) the explanatory facts in the case.Footnote 16

3.3 The Accounts Explained

In Sect. 3.3.1, I set out (CS). In Sect. 3.3.2, I set out (CO). In Sect. 3.3.3, I set out (CDM), (CF), and (CR).

3.3.1 (CS)

Let S = {p 1,..., p n }. Then, on (CS) the degree to which S is coherent, “C S(S),” is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{S}}}(S) = \frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge \ldots \wedge {p_n}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)\times \ldots \times \Pr \left( {{p_n}} \right)}} \footnotemark $$

If C S(S) < 1, S isShogenji spells out his account of coherence in terms of sets of beliefs, not in terms of sets of claims. But nothing of importance, for my purposes, hinges on this difference. incoherent. If C S(S) = 1, S is neither coherent nor incoherent. If C S(S) > 1, S is coherent. The minimum value for C S(S) is 0. There is no maximum value for C S(S). If some of the claims in S have a probability of 0, C S(S) is undefined.

Consider a two-member set: S = {p 1, p 2}. By (CS) the degree to which S is coherent is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{S}}}(S)=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge {p_2}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)\times \Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)}}=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)\times \Pr \left( {{p_2}\left| {{p_1}} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)\times \Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)}}=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_2}\left| {{p_1}} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)}}. $$

If \( \Pr \left( {{p_2}|{p_1}} \right)=\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)\,{C_{\mathrm{S}}}(S)=1 \). If \( \Pr \left( {{p_2}|{p_1}} \right)>\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)\,{C_{\mathrm{S}}}(S)>1 \). If \( \Pr \left( {{p_2}|{p_1}} \right)<\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)\,{C_{\mathrm{S}}}(S)<1 \). So, whether S is coherent hinges on whether p 1 is positively probabilistically relevant to p 2.

Note that positive (negative) probabilistic relevance is symmetrical. Thus, p 1 is positively (negatively) probabilistically relevant to p 2 just in case p 2 is positively (negatively) probabilistically relevant to p 1. So (CS) implies that whether a two-member set is coherent hinges on whether the claims in question are positively probabilistically relevant to each other.

(CS) is a generalization of the thesis that whether a two-member set of claims is coherent hinges on whether the claims are positively probabilistically relevant to each other. This thesis has some initial plausibility. Thus so too does (CS).Footnote 17

3.3.2 (CO)

Let S = {p 1,..., p n }. Then, on (CO) the degree to which S is coherent, “C O(S),” is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{O}}}(S)=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge \ldots \wedge {p_n}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\vee \ldots \vee {p_n}} \right)}}. $$

C O(S) can take values between 0 and 1 (inclusive). If C O(S) = 0, S is maximally incoherent. If C O(S) = 1, S is maximally coherent. It is unspecified where the neutral point is between incoherence and coherence (or even whether there is a neutral point). If \( \Pr \left( {{p_1}\vee \ldots \vee {p_n}} \right)=0,{C_{\rm O}}(S) \) is undefined.

Consider a two-member set: S = {p 1, p 2}. By (CO) the degree to which S is coherent is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{O}}}(S)=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge {p_2}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\vee {p_2}} \right)}}. $$

C O(S) measures how much of the total probability mass assigned to p 1 and p 2 falls in their overlap (or intersection). If p 1 and p 2 are equivalent to each other so that all of the total probability mass assigned to p 1 and p 2 falls in their overlap, then \( \Pr \left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_2}} \right)=\Pr \left( {{p_1}\vee {p_2}} \right) \) and C O(S) = 1. If, to take the other extreme, p 1 and p 2 are incompatible with each other so that none of the total probability mass assigned to p 1 and p 2 falls in their overlap, then \( \Pr \left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_2}} \right)=0 \) and C O(S) = 0 (assuming Pr(p 1p 2) > 0).

(CO) has some initial plausibility. (CO) is a generalization of the thesis that the degree to which a two-member set of claims is coherent is determined by how much of the total probability mass assigned to the claims falls in their overlap, and this thesis has some initial plausibility.Footnote 18

3.3.3 (CDM), (CF), and (CR)

(CDM), (CF), and (CR) are all instances of a certain schema (adapted from Douven and Meijs 2007; Fitelson 2004). So, before setting out the various accounts I want to set out the schema.

Let S = {p 1,..., p n }. Let S* = {S′ | S′ is a non-empty subset of S}.Footnote 19 Let S** = {(S′, S ) | S and S are non-overlapping members of S *}. Let \( S^{***}=\left\{ {\left( {\wedge S^{\prime},\wedge S^{\prime\prime}} \right)|\left( {S^{\prime},S^{\prime\prime}} \right)\;\mathrm{is}\;\mathrm{a}\;\mathrm{member}\;\mathrm{of}\;S^{**}} \right\} \).Footnote 20 Let m be a measure of confirmation (or evidential support). Let \( S^{****}=\left\{ {m\left( {\wedge S^{\prime},\wedge S^{\prime\prime}} \right)|\left( {\wedge S^{\prime},\wedge S^{\prime\prime}} \right)\;\mathrm{is}\;\mathrm{a}\;\mathrm{member}\;\mathrm{of}\;S^{***}}\right\} \). Then, by account “(CX)” the degree to which S is coherent, “C X(S),” is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{X}}}(S)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {S^{****}} \right). $$

Different measures of confirmation can thus be used to generate different probabilistic accounts of coherence.Footnote 21

It will help to consider a few examples. First, suppose S = {p 1, p 2}. Then:

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} S^{*} & =\left\{ {\left\{ {{p_1}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_2}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_1},{p_2}} \right\}}\right\}\ ; \\ S^{**} & =\left\{ {\left( {\left\{ {{p_1}} \right\}\,\{{p_2}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_2}} \right\}\,\{{p_1}\}} \right)} \right\}\ ; \\ S^{***} & =\left\{ {\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}\ ; \\ S^{****} & =\left\{ {m\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}\ ; \\ {C_{\mathrm{X}}}(S) & = \mathrm{mean}\left( {S^{****}} \right)=\frac{{m\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)+m\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)}}{2}. \end{array} $$

Next, suppose S = {p 1, p 2, p 3}. Then:

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} S^{*}&=\left\{ {\left\{ {{p_1}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_2}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_3}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_1},{p_2}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_1},{p_3}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_2},{p_3}} \right\}\,\left\{ {{p_1},{p_2},{p_3}} \right\}} \right\}\ ; \\[2pt] S^{**} & =\left\{ {\left( {\left\{ {{p_1}} \right\}\,\{{p_2}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_1}} \right\}\,\{{p_3}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_2}} \right\}\,\{{p_1}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_2}} \right\}\,\{{p_3}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_3}} \right\}\,\{{p_1}\}} \right)\,}\right.\\[2pt] & \quad \left.{\left( {\left\{ {{p_3}} \right\}\,\{{p_2}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_1}} \right\}\,\{{p_2},{p_3}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_2}} \right\}\,\{{p_1},{p_3}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_3}} \right\}\,\{{p_1},{p_2}\}} \right)\,}\right. \\[2pt] & \quad \left.{\left( {\left\{ {{p_1},{p_2}} \right\}\,\{{p_3}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_1},{p_3}} \right\}\,\{{p_2}\}} \right)\,\left( {\left\{ {{p_2},{p_3}} \right\}\,\{{p_1}\}} \right)} \right\}\ ;\\[2pt] S^{***} & =\left\{ {\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,\left( {{p_1},{p_3}} \right)\,\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)\,\left( {{p_2},{p_3}} \right)\,\left( {{p_3},{p_1}} \right)\,\left( {{p_3},{p_2}} \right)\,\left( {{p_1},{p_2} \wedge {p_3}} \right)\,}\right.\\[2pt] & \quad \left.{ \left( {{p_2},{p_1} \wedge {p_3}} \right)\,\left( {{p_3},{p_1} \wedge {p_2}} \right)\,\left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_2},{p_3}} \right)\,\left( {{p_1}\wedge {p_3},{p_2}} \right)\,\left( {{p_2} \wedge {p_3},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}\ ; \\[2pt] S^{****} &=\left\{ {m\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_1},{p_3}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_2},{p_3}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_3},{p_1}} \right)\,}\right.\\[2pt] & \quad \left. { m\left( {{p_3},{p_2}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_1},{p_2} \wedge {p_3}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_2},{p_1} \wedge {p_3}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_3},{p_1} \wedge {p_2}} \right)\, } \right. \\[2pt] & \quad \left. { m\left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_2},{p_3}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_3},{p_2}} \right)\,m\left( {{p_2} \wedge {p_3},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}\ ; \end{array} $$
$$ {C_{\mathrm{X}}}(S)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\mathrm{S}^{****}} \right){=}\frac{{\begin{array}{*{20}{c}} {m\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)+m\left( {{p_1},{p_3}} \right)+m\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)} \\ {+m\left( {{p_2},{p_3}} \right)+m\left( {{p_3},{p_1}} \right)+m\left( {{p_3},{p_2}} \right)} \\ {+m\left( {{p_1},{p_2}{\wedge} {p_3}} \right)+m\left( {{p_2},{p_1}{\wedge} {p_3}} \right)+m\left( {{p_3},{p_1}{\wedge} {p_2}} \right)} \\ {{+}m\left( {{p_1}{\wedge} {p_2},{p_3}} \right){+}m\left( {{p_1}{\wedge} {p_3},{p_2}} \right){+}m\left( {{p_2}{\wedge} {p_3},{p_1}} \right)} \\ \end{array}}}{12}. $$

So, when n = 2, C X(S) is the mean of two confirmation values, and when n = 3, C X(S) is the mean of 12 confirmation values.

It can be shown that, where S = {p 1,..., p n }, C X(S) is the mean of \( \sum\nolimits_{i=1}^{n-1 } {\left( {\begin{array}{*{20}{c}} n \\ i \\ \end{array}} \right)\left( {{2^{n-i }}-1} \right)} \) confirmation values,Footnote 22 or, equivalently, of \( {3^n}-{2^n}^{+1 }+1 \) confirmation values.Footnote 23 So, when n = 4, C X(S) is the mean of 50 confirmation values, when n = 5, C X(S) is the mean of 180 confirmation values, when n = 6, C X(S) is the mean of 602 confirmation values, and so on.

Instances of the schema thus all agree in the idea that the degree to which a set of claims is coherent is equal to the average degree to which the (claims, or iterated conjunctions thereof, in the) various non-empty and non-overlapping subsets of the set confirm each other.Footnote 24 The best possible case is where the various subsets all maximally confirm each other. The worst possible case is where the various subsets all maximally disconfirm each other.

Let’s turn now to (CDM), (CF), and (CR). I begin with (CDM).

(CDM) involves the difference measure of confirmation:

$$ d\left( {h,e} \right)=\Pr \left( {h|e} \right)-\Pr (h). \footnotemark $$

Suppose S = {p 1, p 2}. Then,Here “h” and “e” can be iterated conjunctions, e.g., \( {p_1}\wedge {p_2}\wedge {p_3} \). d(h, e) is defined only if e has a positive probability. by (CDM) the degree to which S is coherent, “C DM(S),” is given by:

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} {C_{\mathrm{DM}}}(S)& = \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {d\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,d\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ & = \frac{{\left[ {\Pr \left( {{p_1}\left| {{p_2}} \right.} \right)-\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)} \right]+\left[ {\Pr \left( {{p_2}\left| {{p_1}} \right.} \right)-\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)} \right]}}{2}. \end{array} $$

C DM(S) can take values between −1 and 1 (not inclusive).Footnote 25 (CDM) is naturally understood so that if C DM(S) < 0, S is incoherent, if C DM(S) = 0, S is neither coherent nor incoherent, and if C DM(S) > 0, S is coherent (though strictly speaking Douven and Meijs never explicitly say this; see Siebel 2005, 348–349). If some of the claims in S have a probability of 0, C DM(S) is undefined.

Note that one can find (CDM) to be attractive even if one does not find the difference measure to be attractive qua measure of confirmation. Likewise with respect to the various alternative instances of the schema above and the measures of confirmation involved in them.Footnote 26 The crucial question is whether the accounts are intuitive or plausible in what they imply or do not imply with respect to particular cases, and whether the accounts satisfy the various other desiderata for an adequate account of coherence.

(CF) is just like (CDM) except that (CF) involves the following measure of confirmation:

$$ \begin{array}{*{20}{c@{\quad}l@{\quad}l}} {f\left( {h,e} \right)} & = 1 & {\mathrm{if}\;e\vDash h\;\mathrm{and}\;e\nvDash \bot; } \\ & =-1 & {\mathrm{if}\;e\vDash \sim\ h;} \\ & =\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {e\left| h \right.} \right)-\Pr \left( {\left. e \right| \sim\ h} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {e\left| h \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {\left. e \right| \sim\ h} \right)}} & {\mathrm{if}\;e\nvDash h\;\mathrm{and}\;e\nvDash \sim\ h.\footnotemark } \\ \end{array} $$

SupposeThis measure of confirmation is a variant of John Kemeny and Paul Oppenheim’s measure (1952). S = {p 1, p 2}, and p 1p 2, p 1 ⊭ ∼ p 2, p 2p 1, and p 2 ⊭ ∼ p 1. Then, by (CF) the degree to which S is coherent, “CF(S),” is given by:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{F}}}(S) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,f\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\&=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {{p_2}\left| {{p_1}} \right.} \right)-\Pr \left( {{p_2}| \sim\ {p_1}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_2}\left| {{p_1}} \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {{p_2}|\sim\ {p_1}} \right)}}+\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\left| {{p_2}} \right.} \right)-\Pr \left( {{p_1}|\sim\ {p_2}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\left| {{p_2}} \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {{p_1}| \sim\ {p_2}} \right)}}}}{2}.\end{array} $$

CF(S) can take values between −1 and 1 (inclusive). If CF(S) < 0, S is incoherent. If CF(S) = 0, S is neither coherent nor incoherent. If CF(S) > 0, S is coherent.

(CR) is just like (CDM) and (CF) except that the measure of confirmation involved in (CR) is the following:

$$ \begin{array}{*{20}{c@{\quad}l@{\quad}l}} {a\left( {h,e} \right)} & = 1& {\mathrm{if}\ e\vDash h\;\mathrm{and}\;e\nvDash \bot; } \\ &= 0 &{\mathrm{if}\;e\vDash \sim\ h;} \\ &= \Pr \left( {h|e} \right)& {\mathrm{if}\;e\nvDash h\;\mathrm{and}\;e\nvDash \sim\ h.\footnotemark} \\ \end{array} $$

LetThis measure is best seen as a measure of absolute, as opposed to incremental, confirmation. Thus the “a” in “a(h, e).” S = {p 1, p 2}, and suppose p 1p 2, p 1 ⊭ ∼ p 2, p 2p 1, and p 2 ⊭ ∼ p 1. Then, by (CR) the degree to which S is coherent, “C R(S),” is given by:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{R}}}(S)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,a\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\left| {{p_2}} \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {{p_2}\left| {{p_1}} \right.} \right)}}{2}. $$

C R(S) can take values between 0 and 1 (inclusive). (CR) is naturally understood so that the neutral point between incoherence and coherence is 0.5.

3.4 The Accounts Tested

In Sect. 3.4.1, I discuss some problem cases for (CS), (CO), and (CDM) (but note that the case discussed in Sect. 3.4.1.1 is a problem case just for (CS) and (CDM)). In 3.4.2, I discuss some problem cases for (CF). In Sect. 3.4.3, I discuss some additional test cases.

3.4.1 Some Problem Cases for (CS), (CO), and (CDM)

3.4.1.1 Sets of Contradictory Claims

Suppose a fair six-sided die was just rolled. Let S 5 = {t, ∼t}, where:

  • t = The die came up two.

S 5, it seems, is incoherent, indeed, is highly if not maximally incoherent. Likewise, it seems, with respect to any set of contradictory claims.

(CS) and (CDM), though, cannot explain this (why any set of contradictory claims is highly if not maximally incoherent). There are sets of contradictory claims on which (CS) and (CDM) remain silent. Let S 6 = {f, ∼f}, where:

$$ f=2+2=4. $$

S 6, like S 5, is highly if not maximally incoherent. But consider:

$$ \begin{aligned} {C_{\mathrm{S}}}\left( {{S_6}} \right) &= \frac{{\Pr \left( {f\wedge \sim\ f} \right)}}{{\Pr (f)\times \Pr \left( \sim\ f \right)}};\\ {C_{\mathrm{DM}}}\left( {{S_6}} \right) & = \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {d\left( {f,\sim\ f} \right)\,d\left( {\sim\ f,f} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\frac{{\left[ {\Pr \left( {f|\sim\ f} \right)-\Pr (f)} \right]+\left[ {\Pr \left( {\sim\ f\left| f \right.} \right)-\Pr \left( {\sim\ f} \right)} \right]}}{2}.\end{aligned} $$

Given that Pr(∼f) = 0,Footnote 27 it follows that \( \Pr (f)\times\Pr \left( {\sim\ f} \right)=0 \), hence C S(S 6) is undefined,Footnote 28 and it follows that Pr(f | ∼ f) is undefined, thus d(f, ∼f) is undefined, thus C DM(S 6) is undefined.Footnote 29

(CO), (CF), and (CR), by contrast, imply that S 6 is maximally incoherent:

$$ \begin{aligned} {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_6}} \right) & =\frac{{\Pr \left( {f\wedge \sim\ f} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {f\vee \sim\ f} \right)}}=\frac{0}{1}=0; \\ {C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_6}} \right) & = \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {f,\sim\ f} \right)\,f\left( {\sim\ f,f} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{-1+-1 }{2} = -1;\\ {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_6}} \right)& =\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {f,\sim\ f} \right)\,a\left( {\sim\ f,f} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{0+0 }{2}=0.\end{aligned} $$

f(f, ∼f) = −1 and a(f, ∼f) = 0, since ∼ f ⊨ ∼ f. f(∼f, f) = −1 and a(∼f, f) = 0, given that f ⊨ ∼ ∼f.

It is clear, of course, without any appeal to coherence considerations that one should not believe the claims in S 6. The point remains, however, that S 6 is incoherent and neither (CS) nor (CDM) can explain this.

(CS) could be modified to say that if the members of a set S = {p 1, p 2} are contradictory claims, then S is maximally incoherent even if \( Pr\left( {{p_1}} \right)\times Pr\left( {{p_2}} \right)=0 \). Likewise, (CDM) could be modified to say that if the members of a set S = {p 1, p 2} are contradictory claims, then S is maximally incoherent even if d(p 1 , p 2 ) or d(p 2 , p 1 ) is undefined. But then (CS) and (CDM) would be unable to explain why sets of contradictory claims one member of which is a necessary falsehood are incoherent.

3.4.1.2 Sets of Necessary Falsehoods

Let S 7 = {f, s}, where:

$$ f = 2+2=5; $$
$$ s = 2+2=6. $$

S 7, it seems, is incoherent, indeed, is highly if not maximally incoherent; f ⊨ ∼ s, and s ⊨ ∼ f. Likewise with respect to any set of necessary falsehoods.

(CS), (CO), and (CDM), however, are silent on S 7. Consider:

$$ \begin{aligned}{C_{\mathrm{S}}}\left( {{S_7}} \right)& =\frac{{\Pr \left( {f\wedge s} \right)}}{{\Pr (f)\times \Pr (s)}}; \\ {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_7}} \right) & =\frac{{\Pr \left( {f\wedge s} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {f\vee s} \right)}}; \\{C_{\mathrm{DM}}}\left( {{S_7}} \right) & = \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {d\left( {f,s} \right)\,d\left( {s,f} \right)} \right\}} \right) \\ &=\frac{{\left[ {\Pr \left( {f\left| s \right.} \right)-\Pr (f)} \right]+\left[ {\Pr \left( {s\left| f \right.} \right)-\Pr (s)} \right]}}{2}. \end{aligned} $$

Clearly, C S(S 7) and C O(S 7) are undefined. C DM(S 7) is undefined because, since both Pr(f | s) and Pr(s | f) are undefined, both d(f, s) and d(s, f) are undefined. The same is true of any alternative set of necessary falsehoods: (CS), (CO), and (CDM) remain silent.

(CF) and (CR), by contrast, do well with S 7:

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} {C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_7}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {f,s} \right)\,f\left( {s,f} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{-1+-1 }{2}=-1; \hfill \\ {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_7}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {f,s} \right)\,a\left( {s,f} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{0+0 }{2} = 0. \hfill \\ \end{array} $$

f(f, s) = −1 and a(f, s) = 0, since \( s\vDash \sim\ f.f\left( {s,f} \right)=-1 \) and a(s, f) = 0, given that f ⊨ ∼ s. Likewise for any alternative set of necessary falsehoods: (CF) and (CR) imply maximal incoherence.

(CS), (CO), and (CDM) could be modified to say, respectively, that any set S = {p 1, p 2} consisting of necessary falsehoods is maximally incoherent even if \( Pr\left( {{p_1}} \right)\times Pr\left( {{p_2}} \right)=0 \), that any set S = {p 1, p 2} consisting of necessary falsehoods is maximally incoherent even if \( Pr\left( {{p_1} \vee {p_2}} \right)=0 \),Footnote 30 and that any set S = {p 1, p 2} consisting of necessary falsehoods is maximally incoherent even if d(p 1 , p 2 ) and d(p 2 , p 1 ) are undefined. But then (CS), (CO), and (CDM) would be unable to explain why sets of that sort are maximally incoherent.

3.4.1.3 Sets Involving a Necessary Falsehood

Suppose S 8 = {p 1..., p n }, where {p 1..., p n } is very large and highly coherent (on any account of coherence). Suppose (adapting a case from Foley 1979, 249) S 9 = {p 1,..., p n , p n+1}, where p n+1 is the necessary falsehood that 38 is greater than 6,562.Footnote 31 S 9, it seems, has a lesser coherence value than S 8, but, still, not the minimum coherence value. S 9 has a greater coherence value than, say, the set {p, ∼p}, where p is the claim that all ravens are black. S 8 is highly coherent and, so, certain of the claims in S 9—viz., p 1,..., p n —hang together in the requisite sense. By contrast, none of the claims in the set {p, ∼p} hang together in the requisite sense.

S 9 is problematic for (CO). Consider:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right) =\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge \ldots \wedge {p_n}\wedge {p_{n+1 }}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\vee\ldots\vee {p_n}\vee{p_{n+1 }}} \right)}}. $$

Suppose \( \Pr \left( {{p_1}{\vee} \ldots {\vee} {p_n}{\vee} {p_n}_{+1 }} \right)>0 \). Then, since \( \Pr \left( {{p_1} {\wedge} \ldots {\wedge} {p_n} {\wedge} {p_n}_{+1 }} \right)=0 \), it follows that C O(S 9) = 0. (CO) thus implies that, even though S 8 is highly coherent and S 9 differs from S 8 only in that p n+1 (a necessary falsehood) is a member of S 9, S 9 is maximally incoherent.

S 9 is also problematic for (CS) and (CDM). Consider:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{S}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}\wedge \ldots \wedge {p_n}\wedge {p_{n+1 }}} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)\times \ldots \times \Pr \left( {{p_n}} \right)\times \Pr \left( {{p_{n+1 }}} \right)}}; $$
$$ \quad\;\;\;\;\, {C_{\mathrm{DM}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\{d\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,\ \ldots d\left( {{p_1},{p_{{\mathrm{n}+1}}}} \right)\,\ \ldots \}} \right). $$

Since \( \Pr \left( {{p_n}_{+1 }} \right)=0 \), it follows that \( \Pr \left( {{ p_1}} \right) {\times} \ldots {\times} \Pr \left( {{p_n}} \right){\times}\Pr \left( {{p_n}_{+1 }} \right)=0 \), hence C S(S 9) is undefined. It also follows that \( \Pr \left( {{p_1}|{p_n}_{+1 }} \right) \) is undefined, thus \( d\left( {{p_1},{p_n}_{+1 }} \right) \) is undefined, thus C DM(S 9) is undefined. So, (CS) and (CDM) are silent on S 9.Footnote 32

(CF) and (CR), on the other hand, do well with S 9. Suppose p 2p 1 and p 2 ⊭ ⊥. Then it follows that:

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} {C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\{f\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,\ \ldots \}} \right)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\{1,\ \ldots \}} \right)>-1; \hfill \\ {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)\,\ \ldots } \right\}} \right)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {1,\ \ldots } \right\}} \right)>0. \hfill \\ \end{array} $$

Note that CF(S) = −1 only when each of the various confirmation values (over which the mean is taken) equals −1, and that C R(S) = 0 only when each of the various confirmation values (over which the mean is taken) equals 0.Footnote 33

(CS) could be modified to say that if a claim in a set S = {p 1, p 2,..., p n } has a probability of 0, then, though \( \Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)\times \Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right) \times \times \Pr \left( {{p_n}} \right)=0 \), S is maximally incoherent. (CDM) could be modified in a similar fashion. But then, for one thing, though (CS) and (CDM) would not be silent on S 9, (CS) and (CDM) would yield the wrong result with respect to S 9.

3.4.2 Some Problem Cases for (CF)

(CF), like (CR), does well with sets of contradictory claims, sets of necessary falsehoods, and sets involving a necessary falsehood (at least in that (CF), like (CR), implies that sets involving a necessary falsehood can have a coherence value greater than the minimum). I turn now to some test cases with which, arguably, (CF), unlike (CR), does not do well.

3.4.2.1 Pickpocket, Rabbit, and Rabbit*

Mark Siebel argues that (CF) is inadequate in its implications with respect to (at least some) two-member sets of subcontrary claims (2004, 2005).Footnote 34 Suppose a murder has been committed. There are ten suspects. Each suspect has a probability of 1/10 of being the murderer, and each suspect has committed at least one crime: two suspects have committed robbery but not pickpocketing; two suspects have committed pickpocketing but not robbery; six suspects have committed robbery and pickpocketing. Let S 10 = {r, p}, where:

  • r = The murderer has committed robbery;

  • p = The murderer has committed pickpocketing.

Let’s call this case “Pickpocket.” Each suspect has committed robbery or pickpocketing, so r and p are subcontrary claims (given the background information). Siebel holds that S 10 is coherent (given the high overlap between the set of robbers and the set of pickpocketers). (CF), though, implies that S 10 is not coherent:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{10 }}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {r,p} \right)\,f\left( {p,r} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {p\left| r \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {p|\sim\ r} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {p\left| r \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {p|\sim\ r} \right)}}+\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {r\left| p \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {r|\sim\ p} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {r\left| p \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {r|\sim\ p} \right)}}}}{2}\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{.75\hbox{--} 1}}{.75+1 }+\dfrac{{.75\hbox{--} 1}}{.75+1 }}}{2}=-.143. \end{array}\footnotemark $$

In fact, (CF) impliesHere and below at several points I have rounded for convenience. The decision procedure PrSAT developed by Branden Fitelson (in collaboration with Jason Alexander and Ben Blum) provides an extremely efficient means of obtaining or verifying results such as those explained in this subsection (Sect. 3.4.2) and the next (Sect. 3.4.3). See Fitelson (2008) for a description of PrSAT and some applications. that no two-member set of subcontrary claims is coherent.

(CR) implies that, as Siebel holds and contra (CF), S 10 is coherent. Observe that:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{10 }}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {r,p} \right)\,a\left( {p,r} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {r\left| p \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {p\left| r \right.} \right)}}{2} = \frac{.75+.75 }{2}=.75.\end{array} $$

The table below compares the various accounts with respect to Pickpocket:

 

Pickpocket

C S(S 10)

0.938

C O(S 10)

0.6

C DM(S 10)

−0.05

CF(S 10)

−0.143

C R(S 10)

0.75

(CS) and (CDM) agree with (CF) that S 10 is not coherent. (CO) agrees with Siebel and (CR) that S 10 is coherent.

It might seem that (CR) is incorrect in its implication that S 10 is coherent. For, it might seem that, at least with respect to two-member sets of claims, coherence is a matter of positive probabilistic relevance and incoherence is a matter of negative probabilistic relevance. \( \Pr \left( {r|p} \right)=.75<\Pr (r)=.8 \), and \( \Pr \left( {p|r} \right)=.75<\Pr (p)=.8 \). So the claims in S 10 are negatively probabilistically relevant to each other. It might seem, then, that S 10 is incoherent, hence, contra (CR), is not coherent.

Recall that (CS) implies that whether a two-member set of claims is coherent hinges on whether the claims in the set are positively probabilistically relevant to each other (in that if the claims are positively probabilistically relevant to each other then the set is coherent, if the claims are probabilistically irrelevant to each other then the set is neither coherent nor incoherent, and if the claims are negatively probabilistically relevant to each other then the set is incoherent). It is no surprise then that (CS) agrees with (CF) that S 10 is not coherent.

The idea that, at least with respect to two-member sets of claims, coherence is a matter of positive probabilistic relevance and incoherence is a matter of negative probabilistic relevance has some initial plausibility. But, it runs counter to another idea with some initial plausibility—the idea that, at least with respect to two-member sets of claims, maximal coherence is a matter of mutual entailment (where the one claim entails the other claim, and where each claim has a probability greater than 0) and maximal incoherence is a matter of incompatibility (where the one claim entails the negation of the other claim). Suppose S = {p 1, p 2}. Suppose p 1 and p 2 are mutually entailing. Suppose \( \Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)=1=\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right) \). Then, by the idea that maximal coherence is a matter of mutual entailment and maximal incoherence is a matter of incompatibility, it follows that S is maximally coherent. But, by the idea that coherence is a matter of positive probabilistic relevance and incoherence is a matter of negative probabilistic relevance, it follows that, since \( \Pr \left( {{p_1}|{p_2}} \right)=\Pr \left( {{p_1}} \right)=1 \) and \( \Pr \left( {{p_2}|{p_1}} \right)=\Pr \left( {{p_2}} \right)=1 \), S is neither coherent nor incoherent, hence is not maximally coherent.Footnote 35

I prefer the idea that, at least with respect to two-member sets of claims, maximal coherence is a matter of mutual entailment and maximal incoherence is a matter of incompatibility.Footnote 36 One reason for this preference concerns sets of contradictory claims. Recall S 6 = {f, ∼f}, where f is the claim that \( 2+2=4 \). This set, as with any set of contradictory claims, is incoherent, in fact, arguably, is maximally incoherent. But, since Pr(f) = 1 and Pr(∼f) = 0 and since, thus, it is not the case that f and ∼ f are negatively probabilistically relevant to each other (for one thing, \( \Pr \left( {\sim\ f|f} \right)=0=\Pr \left( {\sim\ f} \right) \)), it follows from the idea that coherence is a matter of positive probabilistic relevance and incoherence is a matter of negative probabilistic relevance that it is not the case that S 6 is incoherent. By contrast, because f and ∼ f are incompatible with each other, it follows from the idea that maximal coherence is a matter of mutual entailment and maximal incoherence is a matter of incompatibility that S 6 is incoherent, indeed, is maximally incoherent.Footnote 37

(CF) is initially attractive because, in part, it implies each of the following:

  1. (a)

    A set S = {p 1, p 2} is maximally coherent if p 1 and p 2 are logically equivalent and S is satisfiable;

  2. (b)

    A set S = {p 1, p 2} is maximally incoherent if each of {p 1}, {p 2}, and {p 1, p 2} is unsatisfiable;

  3. (c)

    A set S = {p 1, p 2} is coherent if S is “positively dependent,” where S is positively dependent just in case (a) f(p 1, p 2) > 0 and (b) f(p 2, p 1) > 0;

  4. (d)

    A set S = {p 1, p 2} is incoherent if S is “negatively dependent,” where S is negatively dependent just in case (a) f(p 1, p 2) < 0 and (b) f(p 2, p 1) < 0.

(a) and (b) capture the idea that maximal coherence is a matter of logical equivalence and maximal incoherence is a matter of unsatisfiability. This idea is similar to the idea that maximal coherence is a matter of mutual entailment and maximal incoherence is a matter of incompatibility. (c) and (d), in turn, capture the idea that coherence is a matter of positive support (or confirmation) and incoherence is a matter of negative support. This idea is similar to the idea that coherence is a matter of positive probabilistic relevance and incoherence is a matter of negative probabilistic relevance. It turns out, though, that because (CF) implies each of (a)–(d) it yields some rather odd results.

This point is due to Meijs (2006). So too are the two remaining cases in this subsection: “Rabbit” and “Rabbit*.” First, I shall set out the cases and show what (CF) implies with respect to them. Then I shall show what (CR) implies with respect to them.

Suppose there is a small island somewhere in the Pacific Ocean with a population of 102 rabbits: 100 of the rabbits are grey and have two ears; one of the rabbits is grey and has one ear; one of the rabbits is albino and has two ears. Let this be Situation I. Suppose, instead, 100 of the rabbits are grey and have two ears, and two of the rabbits are albino and have one ear. Let this be Situation II. Let S 11 = {g, e}, where:

  • g = This rabbit is grey;

  • e = This rabbit has two ears.

This case is Rabbit. (CF) implies that in Situation I, where S 11 is negatively dependent, S 11 is incoherent:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right) &= \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {g,e} \right)\,f\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {e\left| g \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {e|\sim\ g} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {e\left| g \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {e|\sim\ g} \right)}}+\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {g|e} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {g|\sim\ e} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {g|e} \right)+\Pr \left( {g|\sim\ e} \right)}}}}{2}\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{100/101\hbox{--} 1}}{100/101+1 }+\dfrac{{100/101\hbox{--} 1}}{100/101+1 }}}{2}= -.005. \end{array}$$

Things are quite different with respect to Situation II. (CF) implies that in Situation II, where g and e are logically equivalent (given the background information) and S 11 is satisfiable, S 11 is maximally coherent:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {g,e} \right)\,f\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right) = \frac{1+1 }{2} = 1. $$

(CF) thus implies that S 11 is incoherent in Situation I and is maximally coherent in Situation II, hence has a very much greater coherence value in Situation II. This is an odd result, given that the two situations differ hardly at all (in terms of rabbits and their properties). S 11, it seems, is coherent in Situation I, and, what is crucial, has just a slightly greater coherence value in Situation II.

This result, it turns out, does not depend on the number of two-eared grey rabbits. Suppose there are ten million rabbits on the island, where all but two of the rabbits are grey and have two ears, one of the other two rabbits is albino and has two ears, and the one remaining rabbit is grey and has one ear. Let this be Situation I. Suppose instead all but two of the rabbits are grey and have two ears, and the other two rabbits are albino and have one ear. Let this be Situation II. This case is Rabbit*. In Situation I CF(S 11) < 0:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right)&=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {g,e} \right)\,f\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {e\left| g \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {e|\sim\ g} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {e\left| g \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {e|\sim\ g} \right)}}+\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {g\left| e \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {g\left| {\sim\ e} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {g\left| e \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {g\left| {\sim\ e} \right.} \right)}}}}{2}\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{9999998/9999999\hbox{--} 1}}{9999998/9999999+1 }+\dfrac{{9999998/9999999\hbox{--} 1}}{9999998/9999999+1 }}}{2} = -.00000005. \end{array} $$

In Situation II CF(S 11) = 1:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right) = \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {g,e} \right)\,f\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{1+1 }{2}= 1. $$

So, (CF) yields the odd result that S 11 is incoherent in Situation I, is maximally coherent in Situation II, and thus has a very much greater coherence value in Situation II.

How does (CR) do with Rabbit and Rabbit*? In Rabbit in Situation I:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {g,e} \right)\,a\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {g\left| e \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {e\left| g \right.} \right)}}{2}=\dfrac{{\dfrac{100 }{101 }+\dfrac{100 }{101 }}}{2} =.990.\end{array} $$

In Rabbit in Situation II:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {g,e} \right)\,a\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{1+1 }{2} = 1. $$

In Rabbit* in Situation I:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right) &= \mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {g,e} \right)\,a\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\frac{{\Pr \left( {g\left| e \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {e\left| g \right.} \right)}}{2} =\dfrac{{\dfrac{9999998 }{9999999 }+\dfrac{9999998 }{9999999 }}}{2}=.9999999. \end{array}$$

In Rabbit* in Situation II:

$$ {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{11}}} \right)=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {g,e} \right)\,a\left( {e,g} \right)} \right\}} \right)=\frac{1+1 }{2}=1. $$

S 11 is thus coherent, indeed, highly coherent, in Situation I in Rabbit, and is slightly more coherent in Situation II in Rabbit. The same is true with respect to Rabbit*.

The table below compares the various accounts with respect to Rabbit and Rabbit*:

 

Rabbit

Rabbit*

 

Situation I

Situation II

Situation I

Situation II

C S(S 11)

0.9999

1.02

0.99999999999999

1.0000002

C O(S 11)

0.980

1

0.9999998

1

C DM(S 11)

−0.0001

0.020

−0.00000000000001

0.0000002

CF(S 11)

−0.005

1

−0.00000005

1

C R(S 11)

0.990

1

0.9999999

1

(CS), (CO), and (CDM) agree with (CR) in implying that S 11’s coherence value is just slightly greater in Situation II in Rabbit than in Situation I in Rabbit, and is just slightly greater in Situation II in Rabbit* than in Situation I in Rabbit*. (CO), but neither (CS) nor (CDM), further agrees with (CR) in implying that S 11’s coherence value is high both in Situation I in Rabbit and in Situation I in Rabbit*.

The claims in S 10 are negatively probabilistically relevant to each other. Likewise, the claims in S 11 both in Situation I in Rabbit and in Situation I in Rabbit* are negatively probabilistically relevant to each other. I turn now to a case, “Samurai Sword,” where the claims in the set at issue are positively probabilistically relevant to each other. I take the case from Douven and Meijs (2007, 414).

3.4.2.2 Samurai Sword

Suppose a murder has been committed on a street in a city with 10,000,000 inhabitants. One thousand fifty of the 10,000,000 inhabitants are Japanese and do not own a Samurai sword, 1,050 of the 10,000,000 inhabitants own a Samurai sword and are not Japanese, and just 9 of the 10,000,000 inhabitants are Japanese and own a Samurai sword. The murderer lives in the city and each person in the city is equally likely to be the murderer. Let this be Situation I. Suppose, instead, the murderer lives on the street on which the body was found, 100 people live on that street, 1 of the 100 people is Japanese and does not own a Samurai sword, 1 of the 100 people owns a Samurai sword and is not Japanese, and 9 of the 100 people are Japanese and own a Samurai sword. Let this be Situation II. Let S 12 = {j, o}, where:

  • j  = The murderer is Japanese;

  • o = The murderer owns a Samurai sword.

Intuitively, S 12 has a greater coherence value in Situation II than in Situation I, indeed, has a much greater coherence value in Situation II than in Situation I. Furthermore, intuitively, S 12 is very far from being maximally coherent in Situation I.

(CF), though, implies that S 12 has a just slightly greater coherence value in Situation II than in Situation I, and that S 12 is nearly maximally coherent in Situation I. In Situation I:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{12}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {j,o} \right)\,f\left( {o,j} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {o\left| j \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {o\left| {\sim\ j} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {o\left| j \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {o\left| {\sim\ j} \right.} \right)}}+\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {j\left| o \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {j\left| {\sim\ o} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {j|\left| o \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {j\left| {\sim\ o} \right.} \right)}}}}{2}\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{9/1059\hbox{--} 1050/9998941}}{9/1059+1050/9998941 }+\dfrac{{9/1059\hbox{--} 1050/9998941}}{9/1059+1050/9998941 }}}{2}=.97559. \end{array}$$

In Situation II:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{F}}}\left( {{S_{12}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {j,o} \right)\,f\left( {o,j} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {o\left| j \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {o\left| {\sim\ j} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {o\left| j \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {o\left| {\sim\ j} \right.} \right)}}+\dfrac{{\Pr \left( {j\left| o \right.} \right)\hbox{--} \Pr \left( {j\left| {\sim\ o} \right.} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {j\left| o \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {j\left| {\sim\ o} \right.} \right)}}}}{2}\\ &=\dfrac{{\dfrac{{9/10\hbox{--} 1/90}}{9/10+1/90 }+\dfrac{{9/10\hbox{--} 1/90}}{9/10+1/90 }}}{2}=.97561. \end{array}$$

(CR) does well with Samurai Sword. In Situation I:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{12}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {j,o} \right)\,a\left( {o,j} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\frac{{\Pr \left( {j\left| o \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {o\left| j \right.} \right)}}{2}=\frac{9/1059+9/1059 }{2}=.008. \end{array}$$

In Situation II:

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{12}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {f\left( {j,o} \right)\,f\left( {o,j} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\frac{{\Pr \left( {j\left| o \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {o\left| j \right.} \right)}}{2}=\frac{9/10+9/10 }{2}=.9. \end{array}$$

(CR) thus implies that S 12 has a much greater coherence value in Situation II than in Situation I, and that S 12 is very far from being maximally coherent in Situation I.

The table below compares the various accounts with respect to Samurai Sword:

 

Samurai Sword

 

Situation I

Situation II

C S(S 12)

80.251

9

C O(S 12)

0.004

0.818

C DM(S 12)

0.008

0.8

CF(S 12)

0.97559

0.97561

C R(S 12)

0.008

0.9

(CO) and (CDM) agree with (CR) in implying that S 12 has a much greater coherence value in Situation II than in Situation I, and that S 12 is very far from being maximally coherent in Situation I. (CS), contra (CR) and each of the other accounts, implies that S 12 has a lesser coherence value in Situation II than in Situation I.

3.4.3 Some Additional Test Cases

I now want to consider two additional test cases: “Tweety” and “Tweety*.”

Luc Bovens and Stephan Hartmann (2003a, b, 44–45, 50) argue that (CO) is counterintuitive. Let S 13 = {b, g} and S 14 = {b, g, p}, where:

  • b = Tweety is a bird;

  • g = Tweety is a ground dweller;

  • p = Tweety is a penguin.

Suppose the probability distribution:

b

g

p

Pr

b

g

p

Pr

T

T

T

0.01

F

T

T

0

T

T

F

0

F

T

F

0.49

T

F

T

0

F

F

T

0

T

F

F

0.49

F

F

F

0.01

This case is Tweety. Intuitively, S 14’s coherence value is greater than S 13’s coherence value. (CO), however, implies that S 14’s coherence value is equal to S 13’s coherence value:

$$ \begin{aligned} {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_{13}}} \right) & =\frac{{\Pr \left( {b\wedge g} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {b \vee \mathrm{g}} \right)}}=\frac{.01 }{.99 }; \\ {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_{14}}} \right) & =\frac{{\Pr \left( {b\wedge g\wedge p} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {b\vee \mathrm{g}\vee \mathrm{p}} \right)}}=\frac{.01 }{.99 }. \end{aligned} $$

Douven and Meijs (2007, 416–417) argue that things are even worse for (CO). Suppose a slightly different probability distribution (on which the probability that Tweety is a ground-dwelling bird but not a penguin, for example, an ostrich, is greater than 0 but very small):

b

g

p

Pr

b

g

p

Pr

T

T

T

0.01

F

T

T

0

T

T

F

0.000001

F

T

F

0.49

T

F

T

0

F

F

T

0

T

F

F

0.49

F

F

F

0.009999

This case is Tweety*. Intuitively, S 14’s coherence value is greater than S 13’s coherence value. But, if (CO) is correct, it follows that S 14’s coherence value is less than S 13’s coherence value:

$$ \begin{array}{llll} {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_{13}}} \right)&=\frac{{\Pr \left( {b\wedge g} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {b\vee \mathrm{g}} \right)}}=\frac{.010001 }{.990001 }; \\ {C_{\mathrm{O}}}\left( {{S_{14}}} \right)&=\frac{{\Pr \left( {b\wedge g\wedge p} \right)}}{{\Pr \left( {b\vee \mathrm{g}\vee \mathrm{p}} \right)}}=\frac{.01 }{.990001 }. \end{array}$$

(CR) does well with Tweety and Tweety*. In Tweety, C R(S 13) < C R(S 14):

$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{13}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {b,g} \right)\,a\left( {g,b} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\frac{{\Pr \left( {b\left| g \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {g\left| {} \right.b} \right)}}{2}=\frac{.02+.02 }{2}=.02;\end{array} $$
$$ \begin{array}{llll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left({{S_{14}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( \{ {a\left( {b,g} \right)+a\left( {b,p} \right)+a\left( {g,b} \right)+a\left( {g,p} \right)+a\left( {p,b} \right)}\right.\\ & \quad \left.{ +a\left( {p,g} \right)+a\left( {b,g\wedge p} \right)+a\left( {g,b\wedge p} \right)+a\left( {p,b\wedge g} \right)+a\left( {b\wedge g,p} \right)}\right.\\ & \quad \left.{+a\left( {b\wedge p,g} \right)+a\left( {g\wedge p,b} \right)} \} \right)\\ &=\frac{\begin{array}{llllllllll} \quad \quad \Pr \left( {b\left| g \right.} \right)+1+\Pr \left( {g\left| b \right.} \right)+1 \hfill \\ \quad + \Pr \left( {p\left| b \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {p\left| g \right.} \right)+1+1 \hfill \\ {+}1{+}1{+}\Pr \left( {b\wedge p\left| g \right.} \right){+}\Pr \left( {g\wedge p\left| b \right.} \right) \hfill \\ \end{array}}{12 }=\frac{\begin{array}{llllllllll} \quad.02{+}1{+}.02{+}1 \\ {+}.02{+}.02{+}1{+}1 \hfill \\ {+}1{+}1{+}.02{+}.02 \hfill \\ \end{array}}{12 }=.51. \end{array}$$

In Tweety*, C R(S 13) < C R(S 14):

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll}{C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{13}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( {\left\{ {a\left( {b,g} \right)\,a\left( {g,b} \right)} \right\}} \right)\\ &=\frac{{\Pr \left( {b\left| g \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {g\left| b \right.} \right)}}{2}=\frac{.020002+.020002 }{2} =.020002;\end{array} $$
$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_{14}}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( \{ {a\left( {b,g} \right)+a\left( {b,p} \right)+a\left( {g,b} \right)+a\left( {g,p} \right)+a\left( {p,b} \right) }\right.\\ & \quad \left.{ +a\left( {p,g} \right) +a\left( {b,g\wedge p} \right)+a\left( {g,b\wedge p} \right)+a\left( {p,b\wedge g} \right)}\right.\\ & \quad \left.{+a\left( {b\wedge g,p} \right)+a\left( {b\wedge p,g} \right)+a\left( {g\wedge p,b} \right)} \} \right) \hfill \\ &=\frac{\begin{array}{llllllllll} {}& \quad \Pr \left( {b\left| g \right.} \right)+1+\Pr \left( {g\left| b \right.} \right)+1 \hfill \\ {}& \quad +\Pr \left( {p\left| b \right.} \right)+\Pr \left( {p\left| g \right.} \right)+1+1 \hfill \\ {}& \quad +\Pr \left( {p|b\wedge g} \right)+1+\Pr \left( {b\wedge p|g} \right)+\Pr \left( {g\wedge p|b} \right) \hfill \\ \end{array}}{12 }\\ &=\frac{\begin{array}{llllllllll} {}&.020002+1+.020002+1 \hfill \\ {}&+.02+.02+1+1 \hfill \\ {}&+.9999+1+.02+.02 \hfill \\ \end{array}}{12 }=.509992. \end{array} $$

The table below compares the various accounts with respect to Tweety and Tweety*:

 

Tweety

Tweety*

C S(S 13)

0.04

0.040004

C S(S 14)

4

3.99998

C O(S 13)

\( \dfrac{.01 }{.99 } \)

\( \dfrac{.010001 }{.990001 } \)

C O(S 14)

\( \dfrac{.01 }{.99 } \)

\( \dfrac{.01 }{.990001 } \)

C DM(S 14)

−0.48

−0.479999

C DM(S 14)

0.255

0.254991

CF(S 13)

−0.96

−0.959996

CF(S 14)

0.4526126

0.4526128

C R(S 13)

0.02

0.020002

C R(S 14)

0.51

0.509992

(CS), (CDM), and (CF) all agree with (CR) that S 14’s coherence value is greater than S 13’s coherence value both in Tweety and in Tweety*.

3.4.4 Summary

In Sect. 3.4.1, I gave some problem cases for (CS), (CO), and (CDM), where each of the cases is unproblematic for (CR). In Sect. 3.4.2, I gave some problem cases for (CF), where each of the cases is unproblematic for (CR). In Sect. 3.4.3, I gave two additional test cases neither of which is problematic for (CR). It does not follow, of course, that (CR) is correct or even likely to be correct; more test cases need to be examined. But the results are at least suggestive.Footnote 38

3.5 (CR) and the Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs

I began the paper with the question of whether coherence is necessary for (epistemic) justification, in that one’s beliefs are justified only if one’s belief system is coherent. Standard varieties of coherentism imply that the answer is affirmative. In this section I relate (CR) to an argument for rejecting this answer and, in turn, for rejecting standard varieties of coherentism.

3.5.1 Coherentism

Coherentism is distinct from foundationalism, social contextualism, and infinitism in that, inter alia, coherentism requires (for justification) a “circular” chain of implication (or evidential support):

Circular Chain of Implication (CCI): S’s belief in p is justified only if (i) S’s belief in p is implied (deductively or inductively) by certain of her other beliefs, which themselves are implied by certain of her other beliefs, and so on, and (ii) this chain of evidential support circles back around at some point and does not continue on ad infinitum with new belief after new belief.

(CCI) should be understood so that (ii) does not require that the chain of implication in question literally take the shape of a circle, where, say, S’s belief in p is implied by her belief in q, which is implied by her belief in r, which is implied by her belief in p. It would be enough if, say, (a) S’s belief in p were implied by her belief in q together with her belief in r, (b) S’s belief in q were implied by her belief in p together with her belief in r, and (c) S’s belief in r were implied by her belief in p together with her belief in q.Footnote 39

Coherentism comes in many varieties. Here is a fairly simple variety:

  1. (C1)

    S’s belief in p is justified if and only if (i) S’s belief in p is implied by certain of her other beliefs, which themselves are implied by certain of her other beliefs, and so on, (ii) this chain of implication circles back around at some point and does not continue on ad infinitum, and (iii) S’s belief system is coherent.

(C1) should be understood so that whether S’s belief system is coherent is determined by whether the set of claims believed by S is coherent, and so that S’s belief in p, if justified, is justified by (that is, is made justified by) not certain of her other beliefs, but by the fact that (i)–(iii) are satisfied.Footnote 40

The argument set out in the next subsection is spelled out in terms of (C1). But the argument can be generalized so that it applies to other varieties of coherentism. For example, the argument can be generalized so that it applies to varieties of coherentism on which what needs to be coherent is S’s system of beliefs and perceptual experiences.Footnote 41

3.5.2 The Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs

The Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs (see Foley 1979) can be put as follows. (C1) implies:

  1. (A)

    S’s belief in p is justified only if S’s belief system is coherent.

It seems obvious that:

  1. (B)

    S’s belief system is coherent only if S’s belief system is consistent.Footnote 42

(A) and (B) together imply:

  1. (C)

    S’s belief in p is justified only if S’s belief system is consistent.

(C) implies that if S’s belief system is inconsistent, then all of S’s beliefs are unjustified.Footnote 43 But surely this implication is false. Consider, again, S 8 = {p 1,..., p n } and S 9 = {p 1,..., p n , p n+1}, where S 8 is very large and highly coherent (on any account of coherence), and where p n+1 is the necessary falsehood that 38 is greater than 6,562. Suppose Smith believes (all and only) the claims in S 8. Smith is listening to his math professor, who, as it turns out, is quite tired. Smith’s math professor utters p n+1. Smith knows his math professor to be highly reliable on matters mathematical, and so comes to believe p n+1. Smith thus comes to believe the claims in S 9. Let’s call this case “Tired Math Professor.” Smith’s belief system (when he believes the claims in S 9) is inconsistent, hence by (C) it follows that all of Smith’s beliefs are unjustified. And yet, on certain ways of filling in the details, at least some of Smith’s beliefs, e.g., at least some of Smith’s perceptual beliefs, are justified. So, (C) is false. Therefore, given (B), it follows that (A) is false, hence (C1) is false. Or so the argument goes.Footnote 44

Coherentists, let’s suppose, should want to reject (C) and so should want to reject (A) or (B). The question is whether coherentists have a principled means of doing so.

3.5.3 (CR) and Inconsistency

I showed above (Sect. 3.4.1.3) that (CR) allows that S 9 can have a coherence value greater than the minimum value of 0. Perhaps (CR) also allows that S 9 can have a coherence value greater than 0.5. If so, coherentists can reject (B) on the grounds that (CR) is correct and (CR) implies that (B) is false. Further, coherentists can agree that at least some of Smith’s beliefs, e.g., at least some of his perceptual beliefs, are justified. Does (CR) allow that S 9 can have a coherence value greater than 0.5?

The answer, unfortunately for proponents of views such as (C1), is negative. Suppose C R(S 8) has the maximum value of 1, so each of the confirmation values in S 8**** is equal to 1. Then, since (i) \( a\left( {\wedge S^{\prime},\wedge S^{\prime\prime}} \right)=0 \) for any \( a\left( {\wedge S^{\prime},\wedge S^{\prime\prime}} \right) \) such that (a) \( a\left( {\wedge S^{\prime},\wedge S^{\prime\prime}} \right) \) is a member of S 9**** and (b) \( \wedge S^{\prime} \) or \( \wedge S^{\prime\prime} \) involves p n+1,Footnote 45 (ii) C R(S 9) is the mean of \( {3^n}^{+1}\hbox{--} {2^n}^{+2 }+1 \) confirmation values,Footnote 46 (iii) each of the confirmation values in S 9**** but not in S 8**** is equal to 0, and (iv) there are \( {3^n}\hbox{--} {2^n}^{+1 }+1 \) remaining confirmation values in S 9**** and each one is equal to 1, it follows that:

$$ {C_R}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{{{3^n}-{2^{n+1 }}+1}}{{{3^{n+1 }}-{2^{n+2 }}+1}}. $$

\( \frac{{{3^n}-{2^{n+1 }}+1}}{{{3^{n+1 }}-{2^{n+2 }}+1}} \) approaches \( \frac{1}{3} \) very quickly as n increases. Let n = 2, so S 8 = {p 1, p 2} and S 9 = {p 1, p 2, p 3}. Then:

$$ {C_R}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{{{3^2}-{2^3}+1}}{{{3^3}-{2^4}+1}}=\frac{9-8+1 }{27-16+1 }=\frac{2}{12}\approx.167. $$

This can also be seen by verifying that:

$$ \begin{array}{llllllllll} {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right) &=\mathrm{mean}\left( \{ {a\left( {{p_1},{p_2}} \right)+a\left( {{p_1},{p_3}} \right)+a\left( {{p_2},{p_1}} \right)+a\left( {{p_2},{p_3}} \right)+a\left( {{p_3},{p_1}} \right)}\right.\\ & \quad \left.{+a\left( {{p_3},{p_2}} \right)+a\left( {{p_1},{p_2} \wedge {p_3}} \right)+a\left( {{p_2},{p_1} \wedge {p_3}} \right)+a\left( {{p_3},{p_1} \wedge {p_2}} \right)} \right. \\ & \quad \left.{+a\left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_2},{p_3}} \right)+a\left( {{p_1} \wedge {p_3},{p_2}} \right)+a\left( {{p_2} \wedge {p_3},{p_1}} \right)} \} \right) \hfill \\ &=\frac{1+0+1+0+0+0+0+0+0+0+0+0 }{12 } = \frac{2}{12}\approx.167. \hfill \\ \end{array} $$

When n = 3, \( {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{12 }{50 }=.24 \). When n = 4, \( {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{50 }{180}\approx.278 \). When n = 5, \( {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{180 }{602}\approx.299... \). When n = 10, \( {C_{\mathrm{R}}}\left( {{S_9}} \right)=\frac{57002 }{173052}\approx.329 \). But, regardless of the size of n (though given the constraint that 2 ≤n< ∞ where n \( \in \mathbb{N} \)), \( \frac{{{3^n}-{2^{n+1 }}+1}}{{{3^{n+1 }}-{2^{n+2 }}+1}}<\frac{1}{3}<.5 \).Footnote 47 So, regardless of the size of n, it follows that C R(S 9) < 0.5. Thus, since C R(S 9) < 0.5 in the best case where C R(S 8) = 1, it follows that C R(S 9) < 0.5 in lesser cases where C R(S 8) < 1.

The lesson is that, though (CR) allows that S 9 can have a coherence value greater than the minimum value of 0, (CR) does not allow that S 9 can have a coherence value greater than 0.5. (CR), thus, does not provide coherentists with a principled means of answering the Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs.

I leave it for further inquiry whether one can accept a probabilistic account of coherence and yet avoid (C) by rejecting (B).Footnote 48 I want to consider whether coherentists can accept (CR) and, still, avoid (C) by rejecting (A). I aim to show that the answer is affirmative.

3.5.4 Nonglobal Coherentism

Proponents of (C1) are “globalist” coherentists, in that they require that S’s belief system as a whole be coherent. Coherentists per se, however, need not be globalists. Coherentists can be “nonglobalists” and hold that justification requires not that S’s belief system as a whole be coherent, but that a certain perhaps proper subset of S’s belief system be coherent.Footnote 49 Consider the view:

  1. (C2)

    S’s belief in p is justified if and only if (i) S’s belief in p is implied by certain of her other beliefs, which themselves are implied by certain of her other beliefs, and so on, (ii) this chain of implication circles back around at some point and does not continue on ad infinitum, and (iii) the p-subset of S’s belief system is coherent.

The “p-subset” of S’s belief system is the subset of his belief system relevant to the justification of his belief in p. If not all of S’s belief system is relevant to the justification of his belief in p, then the p-subset of S’s belief system is a proper subset of his belief system, and so (iii) in (C2) can be satisfied even if S’s belief system as a whole is not coherent. (C2) thus opens the way for coherentists to reject (C), along with (A), and allow for cases in which S’s belief system as a whole is inconsistent, and incoherent, and yet certain of S’s beliefs are justified.Footnote 50

Let’s return to Tired Math Professor. Suppose Smith’s belief in p 1 is a perceptual belief. Suppose, as seems plausible, Smith’s belief in p n+1 is not a member of the p 1-subset of Smith’s belief system. Suppose (CR) is correct, and by (CR) the p 1-subset of Smith’s belief system is coherent. Suppose, finally, (i) and (ii) in (C2) are satisfied. Then, even though Smith’s belief system as a whole is inconsistent, (C2) implies that Smith’s belief in p 1 is justified.

A difficult question for proponents of a view such as (C2) is of which of S’s beliefs are in the p-subset of his belief system. Here I will not try to answer that question.Footnote 51 The main point is just that, by accepting a view such as (C2), coherentists can accept (CR) and still allow that in cases such as Tired Math Professor certain of the subject’s beliefs are justified.

3.6 Conclusion

I have developed a probabilistic account of coherence, (CR), and argued that at least in certain respects it is preferable to Douven and Meijs’s account, (CDM), Fitelson’s account, (CF), Olsson’s account, (CO), and Shogenji’s account, (CS). Further, I have argued that (CR) does not provide coherentists with a principled means of answering the Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs, and that nonetheless coherentists can accept (CR) and potentially answer the Problem of Justified Inconsistent Beliefs by rejecting globalist varieties of coherentism such as (C1) in favor of nonglobalist varieties such as (C2).