Skip to main content

Common Knowledge and the Knowledge Account of Assertion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Structural Analysis of Non-Classical Logics

Part of the book series: Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library ((LIAA))

  • 357 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I present the assertion account of common knowledge in the framework of a multi-agent system for the epistemic logic of knowledge and assertion: the propositional content of a formula \(\upvarphi \) is common knowledge to a group of agents G iff everyone in G knows that \(\upvarphi \) is true and that \(\upvarphi \) is asserted. Three current accounts of common knowledge, including the iterated account, the fixed-point account, and shared environment approach, will be examined. I argue that common knowledge arises from communication which results from overtly observable interactions among agents in a group. I then propose that assertion plays a substantial role in communication, and a fortiori, in the acquisition of common knowledge, given the knowledge account of assertion—one must assert \(\upvarphi \) only if one knows \(\upvarphi \). I point out some semantic implications of the knowledge account of assertion in multi-agent systems, specifically, the transmission of individual knowledge to others, the transition of individual knowledge to common knowledge, and the luminosity of common knowledge. The assertion account of common knowledge is then proposed and justified by a class of Kripke models (referred to as TWC-models) appropriate for a multi-agent system of epistemic logic of common knowledge and assertion. The construction of TWC-models will be specified, and the related semantic rules will be given.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Sometimes, the notation ‘’ can be introduced as an abbreviation of ‘’; by convention, ‘’ is just ‘\(\upvarphi \)’.

  2. 2.

    Several logic systems of knowledge and common knowledge based on this equivalence have been proposed, e.g., Halpern and Moses [13], Mertens and Zamir [21], Fagin et al. [9]. In particular, Baltag et al. [2] construct an epistemic logic containing infinitary operators used in the standard modeling of common knowledge. It is worth mentioning that Lismont and Mongin ([20]: 129, footnote 1) briefly note that some logicians prefer to take certain infinitary logic as the required underlying system for a desired logic of common knowledge, such as Kaneko and Nagashima’s works in 1991 and 1993, and a paper of Heifetz in 1994.

  3. 3.

    It is noteworthy that the characterization of common knowledge based on S5-models would validate negative introspection—. However, as far as multi-human-agent systems of epistemic logic is concerned, it seems rather problematic to claim that to a group of agents G, that \(\upvarphi \) is not common knowledge is common knowledge, provided that \(\upvarphi \) is not common knowledge.

  4. 4.

    For the details of the construction of a logic system of knowledge (S5)\(_{C,}\) by taking ‘’ as primitive, and (FP) as an axiom schema, see Fagin et al. [9]; van Ditmarsch et al. [26].

  5. 5.

    In fact, Yang [29] presented a class of TW-models for an epistemic logic of knowledge and belief which satisfy the main theses of Timothy Williamson’s knowledge-first epistemology, proposed in his Knowledge and its Limits, which can be summarized in what follows:

    • Knowing is a state of mind

    • Knowing is factive

    • The broadness of knowing(Externalist approach)

    • The primeness of knowing (Knowledge first!)

    • Take knowledge as central to our understanding of belief.

    • Cognitive-homeless thesis

    • The knowledge account of assertion—Assert p only if one knows that p

    • The knowledge account of evidence—One’s knowledge is just one’s evidence.

    Note that TWA-models are essentially extensions of TW-models and can be used to justify the knowledge account of assertion. A justification of the knowledge account of evidence needs some other kind of models, which will be proposed somewhere else.

  6. 6.

    As Davidson ([8]: 90) rightly remarked, there are no such conventions governing the formation of intentions. So I can only put forth a primitive function here.

  7. 7.

    Davidson ([8]: 91) notes that ‘It is a mistake to suppose that if an agent is doing something intentionally, he must know that he is doing it.’ This indicates that may not hold. But it seems beyond reasonable doubt to claim that the agent must know that she knows what she asserts, otherwise, it would be difficult to show how she could do this intentionally.

  8. 8.

    I am indebted to an anonymous referee for reminding me of making this remark to show explicitly the implication of the normative character of the knowledge rule of assertion, and its impact on the acquisition of common knowledge. Bearing this in mind, misgivings over could be put aside.

References

  1. Aumann, R.J.: Agreeing to disagree. Annuals Stat. 4, 1236–1239 (1976)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Baltag, A., Moss, L.S., Solecki, S.: The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions. In: TARK’98: Proceedings of the 7th Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge, pp. 43–56. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, San Francisco (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Barwise, J.: Three views of common knowledge. In: TARK’88: Proceedings of the 2nd Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge, pp. 365-379. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, San Francisco (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Clark, H.H., Marshall, C.R.: Definite reference and mutual knowledge. In: Joshi, A.K., Webber, B.L., Sag, I.A. (Eds.) Elements of Discourse Understanding, pp. 10–63. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Davidson, D.: First person authority. In: Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective: Philosophical Essays Vol. 3, pp. 3-14. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1984/2001)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Davidson, D.: Knowing one’s own mind. In: Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective: Philosophical Essays Vol. 3, pp. 15-38. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1987/2001)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Davidson, D.: Three varieties of knowledge. In: Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective: Philosophical Essays Vol. 3, pp. 205-220. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1988/2001)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Davidson, D.: Subjective, intersubjective, objective—Philosophical essays, vol. 3. Clarendon Press, Oxford (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Fagin, R., Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.Y.: Reasoning about knowledge. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Fagin, R., Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.Y.: Common knowledge revisited. In: Hendricks, V.F., Jørgensen, K.F., Pedersen, S.A. (Eds.) Knowledge Contributors, pp. 87-104. Kluwer, Dordrecht (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Gullvåg, I.: The logic of assertion. Theoria 44, 75–116 (1978)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Gupta, A., Belnap, N.D.: The revision theory of truth. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y.: Knowledge and common knowledge in a distributed environment. J. Assoc. Comput. Mach. 37, 549–587 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y.: A guide to completeness and complexity for modal logics of knowledge and belief. Artif. Intell. 54, 319–379 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Hendricks, V.F., Jørgensen, K.F., Pedersen, S.A. (Eds.): Knowledge Contributors. Kluwer, Dordrecht (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Hendricks, V.F., Symons, J.: Where’s the bridge? Epistemology and epistemic logic. Philos. Stud. 128, 137–167 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Hintikka, J.: Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Cornell University Press, Ithaca (1962)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Lewis, D.: Convention: A philosophical study. Blackwell, Oxford (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Lismont, L., Mongin, P.: On the logic of common belief and common knowledge. Theor. Decis. 37, 75–106 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Lismont, L., Mongin, P.: Belief closure: A semantics of common knowledge for modal propositional logic. Math. Soc. Sci. 30, 127–153 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Mertens, J.-F., Zamir, S.: Formulation of Bayesian analysis for games with incomplete information. Int. J. Game Theor. 14, 1–29 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Milgrom, P.: An axiomatic characterization of common knowledge. Econometrica 49, 219–222 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Monderer, D., Samet, D.: Approximating common knowledge with common beliefs. Game Econ. Behav. 1, 170–190 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Rescher, N.: Topics in philosophical logic. Kluwer D. Reidel, Dordrecht (1968)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Tarski, A.: A lattice-theoretical fixpoint theorem and its applications. Pacific J. Math. 5, 285–309 (1955)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., Kooi, B.: Dynamic epistemic logic. Springer, Amsterdam (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Williamson, T.: Knowing and asserting. Philos. Rev. 105, 489–523 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Williamson, T.: Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Yang, S.C.-M.: TW-models for logic of knowledge-cum-belief. In: Downey, R., Brendle, J., Goldblatt, R., Kim, B. (Eds.) The Proceedings of 12th Asian Logic Conference, pp. 314–337. World Scientific Publishing Co., Singapore (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Yang, S.C.-M.: A defence of the knowledge account of assertion: From a model- theoretical perspective. In: Hung, T.-W. (Ed.) Communicative Action, pp. 33–50. Springer, Berlin (2014)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this chapter was presented at the Second Taiwan Philosophical Colloquium (TPLC-2014). I thank the participants and audience for valuable criticism and remarks. I am grateful to anonymous referees for their helpful comments and suggestions. This paper is one of a series of papers working on the construction of models to justify Williamson’s main theses in his knowledge-first epistemology. I am deeply indebted to Robert Goldblatt, Kok Yong Lee, Joshua Sack, and Tomoyuki Yamada for their discussion and comments on this paper and previous work. This paper is partly supported by a grant from the Ministry of Science and Technology (MOST), Taiwan, No.: MOST 103-2410-H-002-174-MY3

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Syraya Chin-Mu Yang .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Yang, S.CM. (2016). Common Knowledge and the Knowledge Account of Assertion. In: Yang, SM., Deng, DM., Lin, H. (eds) Structural Analysis of Non-Classical Logics. Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-48357-2_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics