Skip to main content

Basic Certainty and Morality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Moral Certainty and the Foundations of Morality

Abstract

This introductory chapter provides the background of the debate around the notion of basic moral certainty. Showing its roots in Wittgenstein’s On Certainty, I go on to talk about Nigel Pleasants’ seminal contribution to the debate, and justify relevant aspects of the Wittgensteinian framework I will work within.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. for example OC 56, 116 and 151.

  2. 2.

    This is not to disparage previous work on the subject, but only to say that Pleasants ’ treatment seems to have galvanized the discussion and set it in a particular direction. Previous attempts are rarely dealt with in detail now, except that of Timmons whose influence I will discuss below.

  3. 3.

    An exception can be found in recent work by Robert Schmidle (2016) who seems to accept the badness of death as a basic moral certainty , though under his revised understanding of the term (179–81).

  4. 4.

    This is not to say that a claim is always beyond the need for justification because it has been sufficiently checked (that is because we have sufficient reason to stop).

  5. 5.

    As Wittgenstein puts it ‘Giving ground, however, justifying the evidence, comes to an end…’ (ibid., 28, italics mine) and ‘[i]n certain circumstances, for example, we regard a calculation as sufficiently checked. What gives us a right to do so? Experience? May that not have deceived us? Somewhere we must be finished with justification …’ (ibid., 29).

  6. 6.

    The term ‘optimally’ here should not be taken to imply that some Wittgensteinian certainties are less than optimally certain. As a class all Wittgensteinian certainties are equally immune to doubt . It is here only meant to pick out the fact that, in the case of Wittgensteinian basic certainties, no evidence could be produce to make us more certain.

  7. 7.

    This is a more pointed version of G.E. Moore ’s example ‘…the earth had existed also for many years before my body was born…’ (1993, 106–7).

  8. 8.

    It is worth noting as an aside that many other philosophical attempts to doubt basic certainties fall foul of this type of argument. For example, the Eleatic arguments to the effect that motion is not possible. According to Zeno and others, the metaphysical Monism that they propose necessarily implies that motion (as a form of change) is impossible. Zeno’s famous arguments against the impossibility of motion aim to further support this Monist position. However, our belief that things move is so fundamental to our thought that it always seems more rational to doubt the philosophical argument than to doubt our belief in motion, of which I am optimally certain. That is to say, it always seems better to conclude that there is something wrong (perhaps as yet undiagnosed) with Zeno’s argument, than to conclude that nothing ever moves (and the same could also be said of philosophical arguments aimed at throwing doubt on beliefs like ‘I have hands’ or ‘I have a body’). Of course one cannot go too far with such a method, as we should be open to radically revising our views based on convincing philosophical arguments. But if there are things about which we can be optimally certain, then there will be limits to the reach of such revisions.

  9. 9.

    Of course one may be unsure as to what gender they are, or even what sex they should be. But this is not the same as being unsure what sex one currently is, physiologically speaking. Indeed, doubt as to whether or not one is the right sex relies upon the certain belief in what sex one actually is at present. Also, cases of ambiguous sex do not figure here. I am imagining, for the sake of clarity, cases where no such ambiguity pertains.

  10. 10.

    A few examples of such foundationalist passages should serve to highlight Wittgenstein ’s foundationalism. ‘I have a world-picture. Is it true or false? Above all it is the substratum of all my enquiring and asserting.’ (OC 162); mentioning Lavoisier’s experiments he says ‘He has got hold of a definite world-picture… I say world-picture and not hypothesis, because it is the matter-of-course foundation for his research and as such goes unmentioned.’ (OC 167); ‘At the foundation of well-founded belief lies belief that is not founded.’ (OC 253); ‘I might go on: ‘Nothing in the world will convince me of the opposite!’ For me this fact is at the bottom of all knowledge. I shall give up other things but not this.’ (OC 380); ‘To say of man, in Moore ’s sense, that he knows something; that what he says is therefore unconditionally the truth, seems wrong to me. – It is the truth only inasmuch as it is an unmoving foundation of his language-games.’ (OC 403); ‘Something must be taught us as a foundation’ (OC 449).

    And Wittgenstein speaks elsewhere of ‘hard rock’ (OC 99), ‘bedrock ’ (OC 498); ‘the rock bottom of all my convictions’ (OC 248). Though some have doubted the presence of foundationalism in On Certainty it is beyond the scope of this chapter to enter into detailed refutations of those positions. But see the brief reply to Michael Williams in Moyal-Sharrock (2013, 443, note 5). See also Moyal-Sharrock (2005, 75–80). The arguments there, mainly involving showing how foundationalist images can sit alongside the coherentist or holist images Wittgenstein also uses, are I think decisive.

  11. 11.

    Of course this may cease to be a basic belief , but only where pathology is involved, for example when an elderly person forgets their child’s name, or someone with brain damage loses the ability to make new memories.

  12. 12.

    Although in the case of local moral certainties such contradictions may occur where moral traditions come into conflict, a phenomenon I will discuss at Sect. 5.5.

  13. 13.

    For a fuller discussion of the non-propositionality of basic beliefs see Moyal-Sharrock (2005, 31–51). I will assume the possibility of non-propositional beliefs , or non-propositional attitudes, in what follows.

  14. 14.

    These examples are derived from the text of On Certainty, and cited in Moyal-Sharrock (2005, 102).

  15. 15.

    Of course some may not agree with this formulation, thinking it imprecise. Plato for instance held the human soul to be immortal and not subject to death, so to say that human beings die is not quite correct. But even Plato will not disagree that we die physically, and that is all that is meant here.

  16. 16.

    This is discussed as an example of a universal moral certainty at Sect. 4.2.1.

References

  • Arrington, Robert L. 2002. A Wittgensteinian Approach to Ethical Intuitionism. In Ethical Intuitionism: Re-evaluations, ed. Philip Stratton-Lake. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brice, Robert Greenleaf. 2013. Mistakes and Mental Disturbances: Pleasants, Wittgenstein, and Basic Moral Certainty. Philosophia 41 (2): 477–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ––––––. 2014. Exploring Certainty: Wittgenstein and Wide Fields of Thought. Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burley, Mikel. 2010. Epicurus, Death and the Wrongness of Killing. Inquiry 53 (1): 68–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Mesel, Benjamin. 2016. How Morality Can Be Absent from Moral Arguments. Argumentation 30 (4): 443–463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Russell B. 1982. Wittgenstein and Ethics. Metaphilosophy 13 (2): 138–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, Rom. 2010. Are There Moral Hinges? Praxis: Revista de Psicologia 18: 11–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hermann, Julia. 2015. On Moral Certainty, Justification and Practice: A Wittgensteinian Perspective. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kober, Michael. 1997. On Epistemic and Moral Certainty: A Wittgensteinian Approach. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (3): 365–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenberg, Judith. 1994. Moral Certainty. Philosophy 69 (268): 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1993. Selected Writings, ed. Thomas Baldwin. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle. 2005. Understanding Wittgenstein’s on Certainty. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ––––––. 2013. Hinge Certainty. In Wittgenstein, ed. C. Romano, 439–473. Paris: Les Editions du Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pleasants, Nigel. 2008. Wittgenstein, Ethics and Basic Moral Certainty. Inquiry 51: 241–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ––––––. 2009. Wittgenstein and Basic Moral Certainty. Philosophia 37 (4): 669–679.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, Duncan. 2011. Wittgenstein on Skepticism. In Oxford Handbook to Wittgenstein, ed. M. McGinn and O. Kuusela, 523–549. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rummens, Stefan. 2013. On the Possibility of a Wittgensteinian Account of Moral Certainty. Philosophical Forum 44 (2): 125–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidle, Robert. 2016. The Power of Context in Shaping Moral Choices. PhD thesis, Georgetown University, Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroll, Avrum. 1994. Moore and Wittgenstein on Certainty. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, Mark. 1996. Outline of a Contextualist Moral Epistemology. In Moral Knowledge: New Readings in Moral Epistemology, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong and M. Timmons, 293–325. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ––––––. 1999. Morality Without Foundations: A Defense of Ethical Contextualism. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1967. Philosophical Investigations (PI), 3rd ed., trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford, UK and Cambridge, USA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ––––––. 1969. On Certainty (OC), trans. D. Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neil O’Hara .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

O’Hara, N. (2018). Basic Certainty and Morality. In: Moral Certainty and the Foundations of Morality. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-75444-4_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics