Skip to main content

Geometric and Intuitive Space in Husserl

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Changing Faces of Space

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 39))

  • 388 Accesses

Abstract

Moving from the reformulation of the meaning of geometry, achieved in the first half of the Nineteenth Century (principally by Lobachevsky, Bolyai and Riemann) , which also implied a new definition of the relationship between formal and empirical understanding of the space (e.g. in the investigations of von Helmholtz) , Husserl starts, since the Philosophy of arithmetic, a deep reflection on the definition of space, which would have led to a new philosophical theory of Euclidean geometry (Hua XII, p. 8). Husserl took the view that the clarification of scientific concepts must be made back to the intuitive ground from whence they sprang. In what the author himself called the Raumbuch, the book of the space, Husserl makes a clear distinction between space and intuitive geometric space, believing that this was a conceptual construct, of which there is not an intuitive representation. In fact, peculiar to geometrical concepts is ideation. For this reason the setting of Husserlian problem differs markedly from that of Kant: for Kant , «the representation of space behind the geometry is an intuition, not a concept» (Hua XXI, 268). Despite this “freedom” of the products of idealization, geometry, for Husserl, is deep-rooted in intuition, because in his opinion, and following Gauss, there is a clear difference between arithmetic and geometry. Or within the experience they are structured all the possibilities of various geometric multiplicity. From the idea, here implied, that Euclidean geometry should be assumed, Husserl take distances as early as the Logical Investigations. But despite the changes of perspective, the reference to the intuition remains constant along the entire Husserlian research. The clarification of the relationship between geometry and intuitive space presupposes a long preparatory work related to the supply of light in space structures intuitive, because the processes of idealization not happen—this is the specificity of reflection Husserl—upon the intuitive world, but are prepared in it. In this context Husserl will confront for a long time with contemporary research about the psychology of the space, and in particular with those of Stumpf . For Stumpf, the space (intended as an extension) is an absolute content that inheres essentially to the quality of sensations, for example to color. From this setting Husserl definitely takes the distances, because its base is the confusion between field of view and representation of the surface. The central point is therefore that «the visual field is not some sort of objective surface in space» (TS, 141). In the constitution of three-dimensional thingness and of the deep space play also an essential role the kinesthetic sensations. There is in fact a definite correlation between the visual field and kinesthetic course, since even in the changing of the contents of the field of view, we can show. from the perspective of phenomenological-transcendental, a stable association between sensation kinesthetic and visual content. The manifold of places is never given without a kinaesthetic sensation, and neither is a kinaesthetic sensation given without the total manifold of places , which is merely fulfilled in a changing manner. All this is not yet sufficient to constitute three-dimensional space, as «the Objects here are still not things» (TS, 193). And this marks the end of the most problematic attempt to Husserl: to follow the strata in the constitution of the thing and the constitution of a «visual space for Euclidean space» and, therefore, of a Riemannian manifold (TS, 274).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Husserl (1994: 54).

  2. 2.

    «Daß Homogenität und Isotropie Grundeigenschaften des Raumes sind, (nämlich unseres Raumes, wie er uns gegeben ist) das waren die Brennpunkte meiner ganzen Überlegungen Ende der Achtziger- und Anfang der Neunzigerjahre» (Ms. F I 13 II/34a [1907]).

  3. 3.

    Husserl (1994: 83–84).

  4. 4.

    “Die Zeit als universale ontische Form, Form der realen Onta, ist ein ‚kontinuum‘ (noch nicht mathematisch zu verstehen) von Zeitstellen (Punkten)” (Ms. B I 5 IV/<2>).

  5. 5.

    «Die “anschauliche Welt”, die Welt der allgemeinen “alltäglichen” Erfahrung ist die gemäß der normalen Nahsphäre antizipierte und danach in “möglichen Erfahrungen” konstruierte Welt und im besonderen Natur. Da tritt uns also der anschauliche Raum als Raum der alltäglichen Lebenswelt entgegen. Er hat in sich anschauliche Limes-Gestalten, anschauliche Idealgrade etc.» (Ms. A VII 14/11a).

  6. 6.

    Husserl’s side note to p. 176 of his copy of Stumpf’s book, deposited in Husserl-Archiv, Louvain.

References

  • Helmholtz, H. (1868). On the facts underlying geometry. In Epistemological writings (pp. 39–71) (M. F. Lowe, Trans.) Boston: Reidel Publishing Company (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. (1870). On the origin and significance of the axioms of geometry. In Epistemological writings, cit. (pp. 1–38).

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. (1878). The facts in perception. In Epistemological writings, cit. (pp. 115–185).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1994). Briefwechsel in K. Schuhmann (by), Band V: Die Neurkantianer. Kluger: Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1902). Science and hypothesis. New York: The Walter Scott Publishing co. (1905).

    Google Scholar 

  • Riemann, B. (1854–1868) (2007). On the hypotheses that lie at the foundations of geometry (M. Spivak, Trans.) in P. Pesic (by), Beyond geometry. Classic papers from Riemann to Einstein. N.Y: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1897). The foundations of geometry. Cambridge: The University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1873). Über den psychologischen Ursprung der Raumvostellung, Verlag von S. Hirzel, Leipzig 1873.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vincenzo Costa .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Costa, V. (2017). Geometric and Intuitive Space in Husserl. In: Catena, M., Masi, F. (eds) The Changing Faces of Space. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 39. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66911-3_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics