Keywords

Footnote 1

1 Introduction

In this paper I will offer an interpretation of Henri Poincaré’s views on the foundations of mathematics, revolving around a revised assessment of his understanding of geometry. My interpretation of Poincaré on the foundations of geometry departs from the established view, according to which he held that axioms implicitly define geometric terms. In the following section I will present the established view and briefly summarize the textual evidence for it. Subsequently I will explain and provide evidence for my revised view. According to the established view, Poincaré regarded the axioms of geometry as uninterpreted schemata, providing implicit definitions of geometrical terms. I will contend that Poincaré in fact maintained that the axioms of geometry are properly understood as assertions about invariants of geometric groups.

This paper extends and clarifies the interpretation of Poincaré’s philosophy of geometry that has recently been articulated by David Stump and Gerhard Heinzmann. In particular, I disagree with part of Stump and Heinzmann’s Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on Poincaré; viz., the claim that “concerning pure and applied geometry, Poincaré holds the modernist-sounding view that we have no pre-axiomatic understanding of geometric primitives” (Heinzmann and Stump 2014, §3.2).Footnote 2 I will argue that according to Poincaré we do indeed have a pre-axiomatic understanding of geometric primitives. The revised view that I will defend aligns well with Michael Friedman’s interpretation of Poincaré’s conventionalism, which emphasizes the group theoretical perspective that is key to comprehending Poincaré’s comments on geometry (Friedman 1997). The paper contributes to the literature primarily by directly addressing the established view, articulating an alternative, and showing how that alternative is better supported; secondarily, I will clarify the relationship of Poincaré’s views to those of his contemporaries by showing that, contrary to Russell’s perception, the Poincaré-Russell polemics concerned not whether geometrical primitives should receive nominal definitions but rather what are the primitives, and also by emphasizing the differences between Poincaré and Hilbert.

2 The Established View

According to the established view, Poincaré understood geometric axioms to be uninterpreted schemata that define mathematical concepts without reference to intuited objects. Accordingly, many have thought that Poincaré held that geometrical concepts are to be defined by implicit definition. This view of Poincaré can be found expressed by the logical positivists, and it influenced their understanding of his conventionalism. Moritz Schlick wrote:

To define a concept implicitly is to determine it by means of its relations to other concepts. But to apply such a concept to reality is to choose, out of the infinite wealth of relations in the world, a certain group or complex and to embrace this complex as a unit by designating it with a name. By suitable choice it is always possible under certain circumstances to obtain an unambiguous designation of the real by means of the concept. Conceptual definitions and coordinations that come into being in this fashion we call conventions (using this term in the narrower sense, because in the broader sense, of course, all definitions are agreements). It was Henri Poincaré who introduced the term convention in this narrower sense into natural philosophy; and one of the most important tasks of that discipline is to investigate the nature and meaning of the various conventions found in natural science (Schlick and Blumberg 1974, p. 71).

Rudolf Carnap, too, mentioned Poincaré’s philosophy of science in the context of his discussion of “structural definite descriptions,” which he relates to Hilbert’s implicit definitions, suggesting that he too viewed Poincaré’s conception of geometry as aligned with the idea of implicit definitions (Carnap 1969, p. 27–30).Footnote 3 According to the established view, convention enters into science through the coordination of axiom schema to reality.

More recently, Shaprio, in his book defending in re structuralism, situates Poincaré as a proponent of implicit definitions of geometrical concepts by uninterpreted axiom schemata (Shapiro 2000, p. 154–156). Shapiro draws his interpretation from the influential work of Alberto Coffa, who parallels the Poincaré-Russell polemics on the foundations of geometry with the Hilbert-Frege correspondence, by aligning Poincaré and Hilbert on the satisfactoriness of implicit definitions and Russell and Frege on the demand for nominal definitions (Coffa 1993). While it is true that Russell understood Poincaré to be rejecting the need for nominal definitions of geometric primitives, on my view this is a misunderstanding on Russell’s part: Poincaré was arguing that Russell had the wrong primitives and not that there wasn’t any need for primitives. Here is how Coffa presented the basic issue at stake in that debate:

[Russell’s] reasoning [against Poincare] involved an appeal to a principle that may be called the thesis of semantic atomism... This principle says that if a sentence S is to convey information (or, as Russell or Frege would put it, to express a proposition), then its grammatical units must have a meaning before they join their partners in S (Coffa 1993, p. 131)…

Poincare’s conventionalism was based on the idea that in order to understand geometry, one must stand Russell’s argument on its head: Since geometric primitives do not acquire their meaning prior to their incorporation into the axiomatic claims, such axioms do not express propositions in Frege’s or Russell’s sense (Coffa 1993, p. 133).

To put a fine point on it, I will show that according to Poincaré the geometric “primitives” in question do in fact acquire meaning prior to their incorporation in typical axiomatizations, precisely because they are not, after all, primitive.

Though I will be offering an alternative, there can be no doubt that there is a textual basis for following the positivists, Coffa, Shapiro, and others in accepting the established view. The established view is supported by three pillars:

  1. 1.

    The established view provides an appealing and direct explanation of Poincaré’s statement that axioms are definitions in disguise.

  2. 2.

    The established view also explains why Poincaré concurs with Hilbert’s claim that mathematics is constrained by consistency alone.

  3. 3.

    Following Schlick, the established view coheres with a common understanding of Poincaré’s conventionalism.

Defenders of the established view may lean upon Poincaré’s repeated insistence that axioms are definitions in disguise, constrained only by non-contradiction, and that they are conventions. How else can this be understood than in accordance with the established view? Accordingly, axioms are definitions in disguise in the sense that they implicitly define the concepts of point, line, plane, etc. by characterizing a relational structure among terms, which then must be coordinated with the world by appropriate conventions.

In Science and Value Poincaré argues that applied geometry concerns neither synthetic a priori judgments nor experimental facts. It does not concern synthetic a priori judgments because it is possible to imagine experiences that would lead us to deny some of the axioms of Euclidean geometry, and it does not concern experimental facts because it is an exact science. He concludes that the claims of applied geometry are conventional:

They are conventions. Our choice among all possible conventions is guided by experimental facts; but it remains free and is limited only by the necessity of avoiding all contradiction. Thus it is that the postulates can remain rigorously true even though the experimental laws which have determined their adoption are only approximate.

In other words, the axioms of geometry (I do not speak of those of arithmetic) are merely disguised definitions (Poincaré 1905, p. 65)

Understood in the following way, this characterization of the axioms of geometry accords with a view commonly associated with Hilbert. Axioms are possible conventions because they are schematic and are to be coordinated to empirical reality by conventional definitions. A “line” may be a rail track or a ray of light, and a “point” may be a rail station or a star.Footnote 4 Using the inferential relations encoded in the axioms, we form abstract mathematical concepts of point, line, etc. as places in an abstract structure, but there is no privileged, intuitive interpretation according to which the truth or falsity of the axioms is to be assessed. Accordingly, axioms provide implicit definitions of general concepts, and are only apparent assertions about objects.Footnote 5

In the context of the established view, good sense is made of the fact that Poincaré, like Hilbert in his correspondence with Frege, emphasized that consistency was the only constraint on mathematics, stating that “a mathematical entity exists, provided its definition implies no contradiction, either in itself, or with the propositions already accepted” (Poincaré 1905, p. 60). Such passages may incline one to assimilate Poincaré’s views on the foundations of geometry to Hilbert’s and to analogize the Hilbert-Frege and Poincaré-Russell polemics. For, the claim that mathematics is constrained only by consistency may seem naturally to be understood in a framework that prioritizes axiomatization over genetic intuitions, because a property naturally ascribed to sets of sentences or propositions, viz. consistency, is given priority over intuition as a criteria of existence.

Lastly, it may also be contended that Poincaré’s famous non-falsifiability arguments for geometrical conventionalism are only to be understood in the context of the established view. Any axiom system for geometry can be adopted and held to come what may, making compensating changes to other theories should anomalous observations occur. Accordingly, geometrical axioms must be conventions because of their non-falsifiability in practice. The relational structure encoded in the implicit definition is non-falsifiable for the system to which the definitions are coordinated, and hence it is conventional.

3 A Revised Interpretation

Notwithstanding the support available for the established view, I will argue in what follows that it leads us to neglect important distinguishing features of Poincaré’s view of the foundations of geometry: that the sense in which axioms are disguised definitions differs for Poincaré from Hilbert’s sense, that Poincaré’s conventionalism can only be restricted to geometry (rather than implying a more radical Duhem-Quine style holism) if the established view is rejected, and that Poincaré’s and Hilbert’s equal emphasis on consistency is circumstantial.

The central feature of the established view is the treatment of geometrical axioms as schematic rather than assertoric. According to the revised interpretation of Poincaré’s views on geometry that I wish to advance, geometric axioms are assertions about points and lines, which are defined prior to axiomatization by what Poincaré calls “invariant” sub-groups (in modern parlance: “normal” sub-groups). This interpretation allows us to see Poincaré’s views on the foundations of geometry as intimately related to his mathematical practice and to his emphasis on the importance of group theory. While the established view may be fully articulated without mention of group theory, the revised interpretation gives central place to Poincaré’s insistence that geometry is the study of the properties of certain groups.

Poincaré’s claim that geometry is the study of a group makes its first appearance in his reputation-making mathematical work on Fuchsian functions, produced in 1880. In a supplement to the prize essay submitted to the Académie des Sciences in Paris he states:

It [geometry] is the study of the group of operations formed by the displacements to which one can subject a body without deforming it. In Euclidean geometry the group reduces to the rotations and translations. In the pseudogeometry of Lobachevski it is more complicated (Poincaré 1997, p. 14).

The primary concern of this work is differential equations rather than geometry and its foundations, and these early comments do not receive full philosophical articulation. Geometry arises in the course of studying and classifying functions that are solutions to second-order differential equations having specified properties.Footnote 6 The key to Poincaré’s discoveries in the field of Fuchsian functions was his realization that the transformations employed in the definition of Fuchsian functions form a group that is isomorphic to the group employed in the definition of the hyperbolic geometry of Lobachevsky, leading him to the analogy “the Fuchsian function is to the geometry of Lobachevsky what the doubly periodic function is to that of Euclid” (Poincaré 1997, 15). In a text originally composed in 1901 and later published in Acta Analytica in 1921, Poincaré emphasizes the fundamental role of group theory by asserting an analogy between his work on solutions to classes of differential equations and Galois’ work on the solution of polynomials by radicals (Poincaré 1983, 259). According to the interpretation that I am arguing for, Poincaré’s philosophical commitments in the foundations of geometry are intimately related to his formative mathematical experience and to a broader view of mathematics.

Groups play a fundamental role in Poincaré’s more philosophical account of the conventions we employ in order to categorize and control the changes that occur in our perceptual stimulus, presented in his 1898 article “On the Foundations of Geometry” published in The Monist. The form of a group of operations that is imposed in categorizing sensible changes as displacements does not, in Poincaré’s view, depend in any way on the qualitative character of the sensible changes. It is, rather, strictly formal and its properties can be studied formally. Poincaré writes:

We have now to study the properties of the group. These properties are purely formal. They are independent of any quality whatever, and in particular of the qualitative character of the phenomena which constitute the change to which we have given the name displacement. We remarked above that we could regard two changes as representing the same displacement, although the phenomena were quite different in qualitative nature. The properties of this displacement remain the same in the two cases; or rather the only ones which concern us, the only ones which are susceptible of being studied, are those in which quality is no wise concerned (Poincaré 1898, p. 13).

Continuing, Poincaré defines and discusses the notion of isomorphism, and the idea that the formal properties of a group are what are studied by mathematics. For example, the group of permutations of five cards is isomorphic to the group of permutations of five marbles; the qualitative difference between cards and marbles is irrelevant to mathematics. Similarly, all that matters to mathematical geometry are the formal properties of the group of displacements.

The structure of a group affords the definitions of the straight line and of the point given in the Monist article. Poincaré arrives at the notions of “point” and “line” in an entirely group theoretically driven way. The rotative sub-group is prior in conception to the point, which is conceived only as that which is fixed by the rotation, and the rotative sheaf, defined by taking the common displacements of two rotative groups, is prior in conception to the line, which is conceived as the axis that is fixed by a rotation: “Here [with the rotative sheaf] is the origin of the notion of the straight line, as the rotative sub-group was the origin of the notion of the point.” (Poincaré 1898, p. 20). Poincaré insists that although the idea of a rotative group is suggested by sensation, it is conceived in a purely formal manner by the understanding, so that our reasoning may become precise.Footnote 7 There is a genuine ambiguity in the text. Poincaré refers to the rotative sub-group and sheaf as, respectively, the “origin” of our notions of point and line. I will not take a position on how to interpret this. On one interpretation the points and lines just are the sub-groups. According to another interpretation, points and lines are parts of an amorphous, continuous manifold, which are invariant under the action of the sub-groups in question.Footnote 8

4 Definitions in Disguise

This brings us to the first pillar of support for the established view. What sense can be made of Poincaré’s claim that geometrical axioms are “definitions in disguise” if the established view is abandoned? Is there a tension between the view of axioms as definitions in disguise and the definition of points and lines as group invariants? In fact, keeping in mind that Poincaré gives prior and independent definitions of the primitive terms occurring in geometric axioms can help us to better understand what he means when he says that axioms are definitions in disguise, and how his intended meaning differs from the view that has been attributed to him.

For Poincaré, the claim that axioms are definitions in disguise does not mean that the axioms are themselves definitions that are disguised as assertions. Rather, axioms are definitions in disguise because they disguise the definitions that imply them. One reason to adopt this interpretation is that it allows us to make the claims about axioms and definitions cohere with the plainly stated definitions of “point” and “line” given in “On the Foundations of Geometry” (the 1898 Monist article) and to make sense of the consistently insisted upon priority of group theory. However, the reasons for adopting this interpretation are not exclusively indirect, and in fact there is strong textual evidence for this way of viewing things. When read in full context it is clear that while Poincare does, of course, say that axioms are definitions in disguise, he does not mean that axioms implicitly define mathematical concepts; rather, he means that there are correct definitions that imply the axioms, which are disguised when we treat the axioms as primitive.

In Science and Hypothesis the claim that axioms are “disguised definitions” comes in the summation of Ch III, and is presented as an alternative way to state that the axioms of geometry “are neither synthetic a priori judgments nor experimental facts,” but rather are “conventions” (Poincaré 1905, p. 65). We shall return to the relevance of the revised interpretation that I am arguing for to the proper understanding of Poincaré’s conventionalism shortly, but for now I wish to focus attention on passages which precede these widely cited quotations, which I claim will help us better understand the statement that axioms are definitions in disguise.

In a section of Ch III titled “The Implicit Axioms” Poincaré begins with the question “Are the axioms explicitly enunciated in our treatises the sole foundations of geometry?” The answer implied by the ensuing discussion is plainly “no.” There are unenunciated “implicit axioms” that are implied by the correct definitions of geometrical entities. It is important to stress that Poincaré holds clearly that there are correct definitions of geometrical entities in this section of Science and Hypothesis and that these definitions, which entail the implicit axioms, are the same as those given in “On the Foundations of Geometry”:

“It may happen that the motion of a rigid figure is such that all the points of a line belonging to this figure remain motionless while all the points situated outside of this line move. Such a line will be called a straight line.” We have designedly, in this enunciation, separated the definition from the axiom it implies.

Many demonstrations, such as those of the cases of the equality of triangles, of the possibility of dropping a perpendicular from a point to a straight, presume propositions which are not enunciated, for they may require the admission that it is possible to transport a figure in a certain way in space (Poincaré 1905, p. 62).

Contrary to the view that Poincaré held that the usual axioms provide implicit definitions of geometric concepts, Poincaré is here articulating (less than perfectly clearly, it must be admitted) the same view that he holds in “On the Foundations of Geometry,” that we obtain concepts like “point” and “line” from invariant subgroups; these are what determine the possibility of transporting figures. He writes that affirming the existence of a certain group of operations “constitutes the axioms of Euclid” (Poincaré 1898, p. 18). Indeed, I do not think that these passages of Science and Hypothesis can support the claim that Poincaré rejects the traditional demand for nominal definitions. Poincaré is, rather, insisting that the nominal definitions that have traditionally been given are inadequate, and need to be replaced by definitions that constitute geometrical objects based on the conventional assumption of a chosen group; this “true definition” is not an implicit definition in the sense of Schlick.

5 Consistency

So much for the first pillar of support for the established view. We have seen that the revised interpretation of Poincaré’s foundation of geometry that axioms are definitions in disguise can equally well, if not better, account for the relevant texts. Accordingly, axioms are not definitions in disguise because they themselves implicitly define their terms, but rather because they disguise the definitions which imply them. We turn now to the second support for the established view: viz., that it makes the best sense of Poincaré’s concurrence with Hilbert that mathematics is constrained only by non-contradiction. To better understand Poincaré’s view on this, we should situate his thinking on the foundations of geometry in relation to Kant’s.

A clear agenda of Poincaré’s Monist article is to vitiate Kant’s account of the origin of geometry in a single synthetic a priori form of sensibility and to replace that account with a theory of the origin of geometry in the understanding. Importantly, Poincaré’s proposal for doing this conceives of forms of the understanding as groups of operations rather than discursive concepts. That Poincaré opposes the account of geometric notions as originating in sensibility, either empirically or transcendentally, is clear from page 1 of the essay:

Our sensations cannot give us the notion of space. That notion is built up by the mind from elements which pre-exist in it, and external experience is simply the occasion for its exercising this power, or at most a means of determining the best mode of exercising it. Sensations by themselves have no spatial character (Poincaré 1898, p. 1).

The remainder of the essay is devoted to articulating an alternative, based on the claim that “we have within us, in a potential form, a certain number of models of groups, and experience merely assists us in discovering which of these models departs least from reality” (Poincaré 1898, p. 13), which form “the common patrimony of all minds” (Poincaré 1898, p. 18).

Now, on the established view we can well understand how geometry could be founded in the understanding rather than sensibility. Accordingly, geometry concerns relations between what Kant called “discursive concepts,” which are constrained only by the law of non-contradiction but which, according to Kant, as empty linguistic forms thus lack “objective validity.”Footnote 9 Though it is a bit anachronistic, I think it is not entirely misleading to assimilate Kant’s “discursive concepts” or “forms of thought” to Schlick’s implicit definitions. Hilbert’s claim that the only constraint on mathematics is the law of non-contradiction, that in mathematics existence means non-contradiction, can be read in this context as rejecting the Kantian standard of objective validity and that any consistent axiomatization may have a corresponding model freely postulated. Recalling that Poincaré makes similar statements to Hilbert’s concerning consistency and existence, ought we not, as the second pillar of the established view has it, interpret him in the same way, and ought we to after all attribute to Poincaré a view that gives axiom schemata and implicit definition a central role?

An alternative, non-discursive, interpretation of Poincaré’s view of the role of non-contradiction is available, which better accords with his insistence on group theoretical foundations of geometry and with algebraic methods that Poincaré celebrated as fundamental to the advance of mathematics in the 19th century.Footnote 10 I wish to distinguish the question of the consistency of an extension of a system of operations from the question of the consistency of a set of propositions. On the one hand, if we understand the claim that mathematics is constrained only by non-contradiction as applied to consistency in the latter sense, then we are lead naturally to Hilbert’s view and to the axiomatic method as a mode of definition of mathematical concepts, which may be considered as discursive concepts in Kant’s sense; we just drop the constraint of objective validity and its association with transcendental conditions of sensory representation.

Alternatively, we may view consistency as restraining the freedom we have in postulating extensions of groups of operations. Treating consistency as a constraint on extending systems of operations, rather than on the acceptability of axiom schemata as implicit definitions, allows one to understand the consistency constraint in a way that harmonizes well with Poincaré’s description of the development of number systems beginning with basic arithmetic. Therein, we take for granted an understanding of the operation + 1 and use this understanding to define further operations by recursion, through a “monotonous series of reasonings” (Poincaré 1905, p. 36). It is in this context that Poincaré makes his controversial remarks regarding the non-reducibility of the principle of recursion to the principle of non-contradiction, a claim which he maintained would preclude a complete logicist reduction of mathematics. Our purpose is not to evaluate this claim, however, but to better understand Poincaré’s general way of thinking about the foundations of mathematics, and his remarks well accord with the view that he considered consistency to be the constraining factor on the process of extending systems of operations. For it is this constraint that we know to be unviolated by “the power of the mind which knows itself capable of conceiving the indefinite repetition of the same act when once this act is possible” (Poincaré 1905, p. 39).

We may bring this discussion of Poincaré’s view of the foundations of arithmetic into connection with his discussion of the operations that form the groups at the foundation of geometry by reflecting on the following passage, which introduces the section of “On the Foundations of Geometry” that is concerned with rotative sub-groups:

The number of sub-groups [of the group of all displacements] is infinite; but they may be divided into a rather limited number of classes of which I do not wish to give here a complete enumeration. But these sub-groups are not all perceived with the same facility. Some among them have been only recently discovered. Their existence is not an intuitive truth. Unquestionably it can be deduced from the fundamental properties of the group, from properties which are known to everybody, and which are, so to speak, the common patrimony of all minds. Unquestionably it is contained there in germ; yet those who have demonstrated their existence have justly felt that they had made a discovery and have frequently been obliged to write long memoirs to reach their results.

Other sub-groups, on the contrary, are known to us in much more immediate manner. Without much reflexion every one believes he has a direct intuition of them, and the affirmation of their existence constitutes the axioms of Euclid. Why is it that some sub-groups have directly attracted attention, whilst others have eluded all research for a much longer time? We shall explain it by a few examples (Poincaré 1898).

There are two ideas to draw from this passage that speak in favor of the revised interpretation. First, in general support of the revised interpretation, the conceptual priority of groups of operations is affirmed by the claim that the axioms of Euclid are constituted by the existence of a group. Second, in support of the present reflections on the consistency constraint, the passage strongly suggests the foundational importance of research into groups and their sub-group structure, which I would suggest is best understood on the model of Poincaré’s view of the foundations of arithmetic in the following way: a “germ” is developed through the repetition and combination of generating operationsFootnote 11 I elaborate on this idea, and the relationship the way groups may be defined and some of Poincaré’s broader commitments regarding proper definition below.

In the light of the role that the consistency constraint has for Poincaré that I have been developing, we can see how consistency can have been important for him without relying on the established view that he took axioms to be schemata and to function as implicit definitions. Specifically, consistency constrains the construction of forms of the understanding by restricting the introduction of generators or relations, either primitively or to extend existing groups.

6 Conventionalism

So much for the second pillar supporting the established view. I turn now to the third pillar: that the established view lends to a nice account of Poincaré’s conventionalism. Schlick’s interpretation of Poincaré, as we have detailed above, makes natural sense of his conventions in the following way: conventions coordinate terms in implicit definitions to real objects, properties, and relations. The main problem for the established view concerning the interpretation of Poincaré’s conventionalism is that it leads to a difficulty in saying why we should be, as Poincaré held, conventionalists about geometry in particular, rather than about other sciences. For, if our conventionalism derives from that fact that once terms occurring in axiom schemata are coordinated with reality, the schemata may be held to come what may then the same can be done for fields besides geometry, such as kinematics.

As Michael Friedman has argued, only an appeal to the priority of group theory in Poincaré’s hierarchy of sciences can make sense of why he was a conventionalist about spatial geometry and not kinematics:

Now Poincaré’s conception of geometry is also very similar to the Kantian conception of geometry. For Poincaré, as for Kant, geometry is synthetic, because it is based, like arithmetic, on the possibility of indefinitely repeating particular operations: namely, group-theoretical operations constituting a Lie group of free motions. Moreover, geometry is viewed as the presupposition of all empirical physical theories: neither for Poincaré nor for Kant can geometry itself be either empirically confirmed or empirically disconfirmed. The difference, of course, is that Poincaré, in contrast to Kant, is acquainted with alternative geometries. Poincaré is acquainted, in particular, with the Helmholtz-Lie theorem, according to which geometry is constrained, but by no means uniquely determined, by the idea of a Lie group of free motions. It then follows for Poincaré because three alternative possibilities are still left open, that we have here—in this very special situation—a conventional choice or free stipulation (Friedman 1997, p. 312).

There is a long story to be told about the relationship between Poincaré’s hierarchical view of science and his restricted conventionalist thesis. A full telling is beyond the scope of the present discussion, but it suffices to concur with Friedman that the revised interpretation is better situated than the established view to make sense of why Poincaré’s conventionalism is restricted to geometry and does not tend toward more radical versions of confirmational holism based on the contention that any proposition may be held onto in the face of apparently contradictory evidence, as endorsed, for example, by Quine (Quine 1951). According to the established view of Poincaré’s conventionalism, geometry is conventional because it is non-falsifiable. To block falsification one simply handles anomalies by altering the kinematics. However, the relationship between geometry and kinematics is symmetrical on this account. Should we choose to stubbornly adopt a theory in kinematics, we could resist falsification by making compensating changes to our geometry. On the revised interpretation, geometry is non-falsifiable because it is conventional, a choice of a group must be made before empirical science can proceed.

7 Defining Groups

I have argued that, as with arithmetic, Poincaré understood groups to be generated by potentially indefinite iteration of a generating element. In the case of discrete groups, this may be done by specifying generators and relations. In the case of continuous groups, we need infinitesimal generators. It may be objected that this approach, after all, leans on implicit definitions, given the formalist character of group presentations. However, even if it is granted that group theory in general rests on implicit definition, the definitions of the terms contained in the typical axioms of geometry would not be implicitly defined. In fact, there is good reason to think that Poincaré would want implicit definition to be restricted to the algebraic setting, given his comments on definition in his later works. In an essay contained in the collection Dernières Pensées, Poincaré distinguishes two cases of what he calls “definition by postulate,” which may plausibly be considered to be implicit definitions. The case which is objectionable to the “pragmatist” and accepted by the “Cantorian” occurs when an object is defined implicitly by a postulate which relates it to an infinity of elements in a supposedly given domain. However, this form of definition is acceptable to the pragmatist when an element is defined by its relation to objects in a finite domain (Poincaré 1963, p. 69–71). Katherine Dunlop has pointed to these passages to argue that Poincaré cannot succeed in founding geometry on group theory in a way that does not run afoul of his restrictions on definition, because “a group is characterized by the existence of an identity element that bears a specified relation to every object in the group” (Dunlop 2016, p. 303). However, when a group is presented by a finite set of generators and their relations, only the relation of the generators to the identity must be stipulated, and the universal generalization to all elements can be proven by an inductive argument. On the other hand, axioms of geometry, taken as implicit definitions, would run afoul of this constraint on definitions; for, they aim to simultaneously define infinitely many points and lines by simultaneously stipulating relations to other objects in the same infinite set.

Furthermore, I would contend that Poincaré’s account of indefinite repetition and continuity, both of which will be involved in constructions from infinitesimal generators, appeals only to a kind of intellectual intuition, and not, as Janet Folina has argued, to Kantian forms of sensible intuition (Folina 1992, p. 35–36, p. 134–135, p. 180–181). Poincaré’s views on these matters are, however, subtle and possibly shifted in his later texts in ways that are favorable to Folina’s reading. A competent and complete engagement with Folina’s thorough treatment of Poincaré’s views is beyond our present scope. If Folina’s view is correct, then there is an ineliminable appeal to forms of sensibility that is required to adequately define the groups and sub-groups that we have been discussing. While this would undermine the position that Poincaré rejects forms of sensibility and founds mathematics entirely on forms of the understanding, which is the strongest view I am inclined to endorse, it leaves untouched my core contention that group theory is prior in conception to the axioms of geometry.

8 Poincaré and His Contemporaries

A recurring theme of this paper has been the comparison of Poincaré’s and Hilbert’s images of mathematics. According to the established view there is little difference between the two on geometry, with the primary difference coming in Poincaré’s proto-intuitionist view of arithmetic and the irreducibility of arithmetic induction to logic.Footnote 12 According to the view espoused in this paper, Poincaré held that group theory was the foundation of both arithmetic and geometry. Arithmetic concerns the important special case: the infinite cyclic group, otherwise known as the integers. The groups that constitute the forms of the understanding, however, include continuous groups with the invariant sub-groups that constitute the points and lines about which axioms assert truths. In each case, the construction of these forms occurs through the mind’s power to adjoin and combine operations.

Poincaré, to be sure, well appreciated the power of the model theoretic methods employed by Hilbert in his Grundlagen der Geometrie, and praised them in his review. Poincaré especially praised the usefulness of Hilbert’s work for breaking down the bias of geometers toward thinking that there is a “general geometry,” with Euclidian, Lobachevskian, and Riemannian geometry as special cases. Hilbert’s early model theoretic approach effectively demonstrated that it was not only the parallel postulate that could be regarded as logically independent:

But why, among all the axioms of geometry, should [the parallel postulate] be the only one which could be denied without offense to logic? Whence should it derive this privilege? There seems to be no good reason for this, and many other conceptions are possible (Poincaré 1903, p. 2).

In particular, Hilbert’s approach to independence proofs demonstrates the existence of non-Pascalian and non-Desarguesian geometries. Throughout the review, Poincaré demonstrates a clear understanding of Hilbert’s methods and an admiration for the results obtained, but does this indicate agreement with the view that the supposedly basic terms of geometry are defined contextually by implicit definitions?

I think that the answer is clearly “no,” and this is shown by Poincaré’s concluding remarks from the review. There, Poincaré again emphasizes the group theoretical standpoint. First, he notes that, according to Hilbert, “The objects which he calls points, straight lines, or planes become thus purely logical entities which it is impossible to represent to ourselves,” but he does not endorse this view (Poincaré 1903, 22). Rather, he criticizes Hilbert for neglecting the group theoretic definition of these terms, and in particular for failing to note that the non-Pascalian geometries that Hilbert studies may be generated from geometric groups in a way that is analogous to the generation of metrical geometries. The passage culminates in the following criticism:

Professor Hilbert seems rather to slur over these inter-relations; I do not know why. The logical point of view alone appears to interest him. Being given a sequence of propositions, he finds that all follow logically from the first. With the foundation of this first proposition, with its psychological origin, he does not concern himself. And even if we have, for example, three propositions A, B, C, and if it is logically possible, by starting with any one among them, to deduce the other two from it, it will be immaterial to him whether we regard A as an axiom, and derive B and C from it, or whether, on the contrary, we regard C as an axiom, and derive A and B from it. The axioms are postulated; we do not know where they come from; it is then as easy to postulate A as C (Poincaré 1903, p. 22)

If Poincaré held the view that in geometry axioms are arbitrary postulates that implicitly define geometric terms, then this criticism would make no sense. The criticism only makes sense if, as I have argued, Poincaré holds that there is a correct account of where the axioms come from, and this account, as should by now be manifestly evident, requires that the terms contained in the axioms of geometry have proper definitions. According to Poincaré, there are non-logical criteria for the correct ordering of propositions in mathematics.

While the Poincaré-Russell polemics have been commonly interpreted as paralleling the Hilbert-Frege correspondence, the orthogonality between Poincaré and Hilbert is in fact previsioned in his review of Russell. Coffa in particular, regards Poincaré as having rejected the thesis of “semantic atomism,” according to which the terms contained in a sentence must have prior meanings that must be properly combined for the sentence to express a proposition (Coffa 1993, p. 131). If this is right, then there is indeed a parallel between Frege’s insistence that the axioms of geometry must be assertions about objects that are given in intuition and Russell’s supposed semantic atomism.Footnote 13 However, if Poincaré is rejecting semantic atomism, then there cannot be correct definitions of the terms “point” and “line,” as the 1898 Monist article articulates, that imply the axioms, as described in Science and Hypothesis.Footnote 14

In fact, Poincaré’s agenda in Des Fondaments de Geométrie, the review of Russell’s 1897 book An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry, is entirely consonant with his agenda in his review of Hilbert. Firstly, he wishes to disavow Russell of the view that there is a core geometry, based on the axioms of projective geometry, that is grounded in sensible intuition. This is precisely the sort of view that Poincaré praises Hilbert for disproving by demonstrating the logical possibility of non-Pascalian and non-Desarguesian geometries through model theoretical methods (though, again, Poincaré thought these methods were incomplete because they did not show the origin of these geometries in group theory). Russell’s contention, in the 1890s, was that projective geometry rested on a Kantian foundation in sensible intuition and consisted of synthetic a priori truths, but that metrical geometry was empirical.

It is true that Poincaré savagely criticizes Russell’s position that the basic terms of projective geometry refer to objects given in sensible intuition, by pointing out the vagueness and imprecision of Russell’s definitions and axioms (Poincaré 1899, §2–4), but this only shows that Poincaré rejected the foundation of geometry in sensibility. As I have argued, his alternative was not a foundation of geometry in discursive concepts defined implicitly by the axioms in which they occur, but rather in group theory as a form of the understanding. Indeed, the group theoretical perspective is what Poincaré insists on, and not the rejection of semantic atomism, in presenting his alternative to Russell (Poincaré 1899, §19). Poincaré wants to disavow Russell of the view he praises Hilbert for dislodging, that there is a universal geometry (for Russell, projective geometry), but he wants to do so by convincing Russell of the priority in conception of the form of the group, which he criticizes Hilbert for neglecting.

There is a clear affinity between Poincaré’s view and that of Klein and Lie, expressed in the Erlangen program. Indeed, there was interaction between Poincaré and Lie in 1882 when Lie was in Paris. Lie wrote to Klein that Poincaré held the concept of a group to be the fundamental concept for all of mathematics (Hawkins 2000, p. 182). Jeremy Gray notes that it is very likely that Poincaré’s use of groups in his analysis of Fuchsian functions was independent of Klein’s Erlangen program (Gray 2005, p. 551). It is not clear whether Klein or Lie ever indicated anything like Poincaré’s philosophical view that the group is prior in conception to the terms occurring in the axioms of geometry. Poincaré’s position is that group theory defines those terms, that the objects to which they refer are constituted by invariant sub-groups, but an alternative view would be that the objects of geometry are presented or constructed independently while groups afford a complete means of classification without necessarily constituting the objects that comprise the spaces thus classified. This view is consistent with a mathematical interest in the use of groups to classify geometries, but inconsistent with Poincaré’s fully developed philosophical position.

9 Conclusion

This paper has been focused on correctly articulating Poincaré’s views on the foundations of geometry. Accordingly, he held that geometry is founded on group theory, in such a way that the terms “point” and “line” receive proper definitions by reference to invariant sub-groups. This interpretation sheds light on Poincaré’s general philosophy of mathematics. For, group theory, as the study of forms of the understanding, has the same foundation as arithmetic. While Poincaré has sometimes been read as having a disjointed view of mathematics, a kind of quasi-logicist view of geometry as grounded in axiomatic implicit definitions together with a quasi-intuitionistic view of arithmetic, we can now see that there is a deep unity in his vision of mathematics.

Should this matter to contemporary philosophers of mathematics, or is getting Poincaré’s view right a matter of historical curiosity? I think that, for good reason, philosophers have been fascinated with the notion of mathematics as a science of structure, or logical form, which can be associated with the concepts that are articulated through axiomatic definitions. This has given rise to a very interesting literature in the metaphysics of mathematics, on whether structures must be understood as ante rem or in re, what the relationship between structures and sets might be, and many more questions. So it may seem that revisiting a neo-Kantian view from the turn of the 20th century holds limited interest. From this perspective, one may even find that my interpretation of Poincaré in fact diminishes his legacy as anticipating the structuralist turn, based on the axiomatic method, in his writings of the 1890s.

However, while the importance of the axiomatic point of view to the development of mathematics in the 20th century is undeniable, and the understanding of mathematics as advancing through the logical derivation of theorems from axioms, that is as a system of discursive reasoning, certainly has great philosophical importance, the focus on discursive reasoning limits our perspective on the nature of mathematical reasoning, on mathematical experience, and potentially on the very nature of the mind and intelligence. Poincaré’s unified image of mathematics, derived from his own mathematical experience, beginning with his work on Fuchsian functions, which produced germinal contributions to mathematical knowledge, begins with an account of non-discursive reasoning. Mathematicians are masters of more than the rules of logic, and a complete account of mathematics will involve accounting for both discursive and non-discursive reasoning, as well as the relationship between the two. Correctly understood, Poincaré’s account of the foundations of geometry offers a neglected contribution to this philosophical project.