Skip to main content

Changing Expectations of Experts: The Symbolic Role of Ethics Committees

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Symbolic Legislation Theory and Developments in Biolaw

Part of the book series: Legisprudence Library ((LEGIS,volume 4))

  • 636 Accesses

Abstract

Complex policy issues pose a conundrum for liberal democratic governments. Disagreement about complex policy issues can often be traced back to fundamental value differences and governments aim to avoid heavy political conflicts based on these, while at the same time they face the need for expedient decision making. One solution is to seek advice of or even defer decisions to expert committees, in particular ethics committees. In this paper, we focus on the role of ethics committees by putting the role of ethicists as experts up for discussion. We argue that governments and the public foster wrong expectations regarding the role and mandate of ethics committees. Normative expertise is essentially different from scientific expertise. Lumping them together has resulted in false expectations and an overvaluation of the role of various types of experts. It is therefore necessary to explicate the roles the various players have and to define what is to be expected from them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For example, the creation of in vitro meat could drastically change the way we produce our protein. http://nos.nl/artikel/536816-veestapel-weg-door-kweekvlees.html, last accessed 5 August 2013. See also Van der Weele (2014).

  2. 2.

    M.R. Capecchi, M.J. Evans, and Oliver Smitties, nobel prize for medicine 2007, http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/medicine/laureates/2007/index.html, last accessed July 2013.

  3. 3.

    For example the Dutch Committee on Animal Biotechnology, see Bovenkerk and Poort (2008).

  4. 4.

    Another example can be found in the analysis of the development of standards in the areas of global food safety. Alessandra Arcuri (2014) describes that decision making in this field is mainly left up to technocratic regime by relying too much on scientific experts only.

  5. 5.

    Scientific reasoning can often not even do without it, because there is always a risk of error in different stages of research and what error one is willing to accept in the end depends on a non-epistemic value choice. Douglas (2000) argues that there are many stages in scientific endeavour where there is ‘inductive risk’, in other words the possibility of false positive or false negative outcomes, or the possibility that the outcomes lead the researcher to accept his/her hypothesis while the hypothesis is in reality false, or the other way around, that he/she rejects a hypothesis that is in reality right. The consequences of false positives are often overregulation (for example when the toxic properties of a chemical are measured) and the consequence of false negatives underregulation (and a possible health risk to the population) and thus they have a consequence in the real world. This means that the scientist in question will have to make a value judgment about what is an acceptable outcome in the case of inductive risk. In other words, non-epistemic values do and should enter the internal scientific domain.

  6. 6.

    While Sarewitz’ writing could be subsumed under the critical stream of the modern model, as he attacks the fact/value distinction, the implications of his work in our view do not fit within the modern model, but belong instead in the model that we want to propose.

  7. 7.

    See M Slob and J Staman (2012) Policy and the evidence beast. The Hague: Rathenau Institute.

  8. 8.

    Another problem, as Verweij et al. (2000, p. 347) suggest is that ‘the possibility of a negative judgment about a research project often pits scientists and committees toward a struggle for power – which is the death sentence for any moral deliberation’.

  9. 9.

    Now subsumed under the Ministry for Economic Affairs.

  10. 10.

    It should be noted, however, that Baggini appears to be thinking about ethics committees completely composed of ethical experts, which is generally not the case in practice.

References

  • Arcuri, Alessandra. 2014. The coproduction of the global regulatory regime for food safety standards and the limits of a technocratic ethos. EUI Working Papers, RSCAS 97: 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baggini, Julian. 2010. No one is an ethical expert. Long live ethical expertise. In Ethiek in discussie. Praktijkvoorbeelden van ethische expertise, ed. M. Van den Hoven, L. Van der Scheer, and D. Willems, 15–30. Gorcum: Van Assen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barke, Richard, and Hank Jenkins-Smith. 1993. Politics and scientific expertise. Scientists, risk perception, and nuclear waste policy. Risk Analysis 13(4): 425–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovenkerk, Bernice. 2012. The biotechnology debate. Democracy in the face of intractable disagreement. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovenkerk, Bernice, and Lonneke M. Poort. 2008. The role of ethics committees in public debate. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 22(10): 19–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castle, David, and Keith Culver. 2013. Getting to ‘No’. The method of contested exchange. Science and Public Policy 40: 34–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry, and Robert Evans. 2002. The third wave of science studies. Social Studies of Science 32: 235–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crosthwaithe, Jan. 2005. Moral expertise. A problem in the professional ethics of professional ethicists. Bioethics 9: 361–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, Heather. 2000. Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science 67(4): 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, Sheila. 2003. Accountability. (No?) Accounting of expertise. Science and Public Policy 30: 157–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joss, Simon. 1999. Public participation in science and technology policy- and decision-making – Empheral phenomen or lasting change? Science and Public Policy 26(5): 290–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen. 1990. Science as social knowledge. Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, Jonathan D. 2009. Ethics committees and ethics consultants. A companion to bioethics. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell 2009: 475–484.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowotny, Helga. 2003. Dilemma of expertise. Democratising expertise and socially robust knowledge. Science and Public Policy 30: 151–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowotny, Helga, Peter Scott, and Michael T. Gibbons. 2001. Rethinking science, knowledge and the public in an age of uncertainty. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2002. Moral expertise? Constitutional narratives and philosophical argument. Metaphilosophy 33(5): 502–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paula, Lino E. 2008. Ethics committees, public debate and regulation. An evaluation of policy instrument in bioethics governance. Amsterdam: Athena Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poort, Lonneke. 2013. Consensus & controversies in animal biotechnology. An interactive legislative approach to animal biotechnology in Denmark, Switzerland, and the Netherlands. Den Haag: Eleven International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poort, Lonneke M., Tora Holmberg, and Malin Ideland. 2013. Bringing in the controversy. Re-politicizing the de-politicized strategy of ethics committees. Life Sciences, Society and Policy 9(11): 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 1993. Objectivity of the science-ethics distinction. In The quality of life, ed. M. Nussbaum and A.K. Sen, 143–157. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sarewitz, Daniel. 2004. How science makes environmental controversies worse. Environmental Science & Policy 7: 385–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slob, Marjan, and Jan Staman. 2012. Policy and the evidence beast. The Hague: Rathenau Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stafleu, Frans. 1994. The ethical acceptability of animal experiments as judged by researchers. Faculty of Animal Science: Utrecht University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swart, Jac A.A., H. Hub Zwart, and Wolters Jan (eds.). 2004. DEC’s in discussie. De beoordeling van dierproeven in Nederland. Budel: Damon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tickner, Joel A., and Sarah Wright. 2003. US perspective. The precautionary principle and democratizing expertise. A US perspective. Science and Public Policy 30: 213–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulrich, Beck. 1992. Risk society. Towards a new modernity. New Delhi: Sage. (Translated from the German Risikogesellschaft 1986.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Van der Weele, C. 2014. In vitro meat. In Encyclopedia of food and agricultural ethics, ed. P.B. Thompson and D.M. Kaplan, 1219–1225. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Klink, Bart. 1998. De wet als symbool. Over wettelijke communicatie en de Wet gelijke behandeling van mannen en vrouwen bij de arbeid. Deventer: W.E.J. Tjeenk Willink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verweij, Marcel, Frans W.A. Brom, and Alex Huibers. 2000. Do’s and don’ts for ethics committees. Practical lessons learned in the Netherlands. International Perspectives 12(4): 344–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, Brian. 1996. Misunderstood misunderstandings. Social identities and public uptake of science. In Misunderstanding science? The public reconstruction of science and technology, ed. A. Irwin and B. Wynne, 19–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lonneke Poort .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Poort, L., Bovenkerk, B. (2016). Changing Expectations of Experts: The Symbolic Role of Ethics Committees. In: van Klink, B., van Beers, B., Poort, L. (eds) Symbolic Legislation Theory and Developments in Biolaw. Legisprudence Library, vol 4. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33365-6_16

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33365-6_16

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-33363-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-33365-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics