Keywords

1 Introduction

The recent debate on the indispensability argument (henceforth, IA) in the philosophy of mathematics features an impressive number of versions of the argument, all somehow pointing back to what is referred to as ‘the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument’, that is to Quine’s several scattered remarks on the subject and to Putnam’s (1971) first proper formulation of a version of IA. It is thus legitimate to wonder whether all (or, at least, most of) the versions available on the market can be really traced back to some minimal shared structure.

After rehearsing the most common stances towards IA, the main aim of this paper is to offer four minimal versions of IA, minimal in so far as they feature, according to classifications that will be explained below, the fewest or least controversial premises needed to gain the desired conclusion(s). We will submit that different formulations of IA on the market, related to the common stances to be discussed, could be retrieved from the minimal arguments to be offered.Footnote 1

Despite its methodological character, the following inquiry will have as a substantive conclusion that, in order to obtain the desired conclusions, some commonly required assumptions—namely, confirmational holism and naturalism—will prove dispensable.

Since it is not our intention in this occasion to take a stance in the debate on indispensability, many of the criticisms or defences of IA will not be discussed.

The structure of the paper is as follows. Section 13.2 introduces the issue by reference to the debate by considering some representative versions of the argument. Section 13.3 offers a taxonomy of four minimal versions of IA. Section 13.4 focuses on the notion of (in)dispensability. Section 13.5 considers in details which assumptions and notions are really needed if one wishes to endorse the minimal arguments. Section 13.6 indicates how the representative versions considered in Sect. 13.2 can be retrieved from the minimal arguments. Section 13.7 offers concluding remarks on the bearing of the present inquiries for the philosophical significance of IA.

2 The Indispensability Argument: Four Common Stances

A few expository remarks will help us to single out four common stances concerning the structure and significance of IA that we take as representative of the ongoing debate.

Putnam’s (1971) well-known passage is commonly assumed as the reference formulation:

So far I have been developing an argument for realism roughly along the following lines: quantification over mathematical entities is indispensable for science, both formal and physical, therefore we should accept such quantification; but this commits us to accepting the existence of the mathematical entities in question. This type of argument stems, of course, from Quine… (Putnam 1971, p. 347)

Putnam wavers, at different places, between considering the conclusion of the argument to be a form of platonism and rather a conclusion in favour of mathematical realism.Footnote 2 For our present purpose, it suffices that the two theses are acknowledged as distinct and both plausible: by platonism we mean the thesis that there exist objects of a certain sort, namely, such that our current mathematical theories can be taken to be about them, in short that there exist mathematical objectsFootnote 3; by mathematical realism we mean a particular form of semantic realism, i.e. the thesis that the statements encompassed by our current mathematical theories, or better its theorems or consequences, are true (without specific commitment to what makes them true).Footnote 4

Putnam’s own views apart, his quotation above is commonly seen as a paradigmatic example of an argument for platonism. Prima facie, the Putnam’s version of the argument appeals only to two notions, indispensability and quantification. However, many believe that beside these notions, IA relies on some additional theses of Quinean provenance: confirmational holism and naturalism.Footnote 5 The most debated formulation of IA that is faithful to this conception has been advanced by Mark ColyvanFootnote 6:

  1. i)

    We ought to have ontological commitment to all and only those entities that are indispensable to our best scientific theories;

  2. ii)

    Mathematical entities are indispensable to our best scientific theories;

    ------------------------------

  3. iii)

    We ought to have ontological commitment to mathematical entities

According to Colyvan, ‘the crucial first premise follows from the doctrines of naturalism and holism’.Footnote 7 Naturalism would be required in order to justify the only-direction of the implication, which, as Colyvan himself acknowledges,Footnote 8 is, in fact, redundant for drawing the conclusion, and confirmational holism to justify the all-direction. Whether this is so hinges on how the notions involved are defined.

So far, we are confronted with representatives of two different stances on IA. On the one hand, Putnam is concerned with logico-syntactical features of scientific theories and their expressive power: what is at stake is whether some particular vocabulary is necessary in order to state some given scientific laws.Footnote 9 On the other hand, Colyvan’s formulation widens the scope by taking into account general concerns in the philosophy of science, especially as regards the relation between philosophy and science and the way in which empirical evidence is meant to confirm scientific theories.

There is yet a third stance on IA. Hartry Field first suggested that a particular version of IA involves indispensability ‘for explanations’ (1989, p. 14): if we have a theory that we take to be our best explanation of a given set of (arguably empirical) phenomena, and this theory includes some statements to the extent that certain (sorts of) objects exist, then we ‘have a strong reason to believe’ (ibid., p. 15) in the truth of the statements in question and consequently (pending a clarification of the ontological import of existential statements) in the existence of the relevant (sorts of) objects. This requires that inference to the best explanation (IBE) is considered a reliable principle. This third stance on IA thus equates (faithful to some of Quine’s remarks, as well as to Putnam’s overall picture) arguments for mathematical (ontological) realism and arguments for scientific realism about unobservable entities, where IBE is often appealed to. As a result of the recent vast debate on explanation, and mathematical explanation in particular,Footnote 10 Alan Baker (2009, p. 613) has claimed that ‘for the purposes of establishing platonism […] it needs to be shown that reference to mathematical objects sometimes plays an explanatory role in science’. He has thus offered the following ‘Enhanced Indispensability Argument’ (ibid.):

  1. i)

    We ought rationally to believe in the existence of any entity which plays an indispensable explanatory role in our best scientific theories;

  2. ii)

    Mathematical objects play an indispensable explanatory role in science;

    ------------------------------

  3. iii)

    Hence, we ought rationally to believe in the existence of to mathematical objects.

Finally, we have a fourth stance, represented by arguments that build on pragmatic considerations, or generally considerations concerned with scientific practice and its needs. The most representative argument in this case has been presented by Resnik (1995, pp. 169–171, 1997, pp. 46–47)Footnote 11:

  1. i)

    In stating its laws and conducting its derivations science assumes the existence of many mathematical objects and the truth of much mathematics.

  2. ii)

    These assumptions are indispensable to the pursuit of science; moreover, many of the important conclusions drawn from and within science could not be drawn without taking mathematical claims to be true.

    ------------------------------

  3. iii)

    So we are justified in drawing conclusions from and within science only if we are justified in taking the mathematics used in science to be true.

  4. iv)

    We are justified in doing science.

  5. v)

    The only way we know of doing science involves drawing conclusions from and within it.

    ------------------------------

  6. vi)

    So, we are justified in taking that mathematics to be true.

    ------------------------------

  7. vii)

    So, mathematics is true.

Setting apart any consideration about the validity of this version of IA, let us just notice that it differs from the previous versions to the extent that, as Resnik himself claims, it does not depend on the claim that ‘the evidence for science (one body of statements) is also evidence for its mathematical components (another body of statements)’, but merely requires that ‘the justification for doing science (one act) also justifies our accepting as true such mathematics as science uses (another act)’.Footnote 12

More recently, Azzouni (2009) has offered a reading of IA that is also based, though in rather different terms, on pragmatic considerations. More specifically, in a vein similar to ours (cf. footnote 17 below), Azzouni offers the following enthymematic ‘blueprint’ for IA:

Premise::

Certain statements that quantify over mathematical entities are indispensable to science.

Conclusion::

Those statements are true.

as underlying a family of arguments usually referred to as ‘Quine-Putnam indispensability argument’. He then proposes to expand on this blueprint in order to offer what he labels the ‘Assertoric-use QP’, a version of IA based on the fact that what he calls the ‘assertoric use’ of mathematical statements is indispensable to science and that this use commits speakers to the truth of the statements in question. We will consider Azzouni’s proposal, together with what we take to be a plausible reconstruction of his Assertoric-use QP, in more details below in Sect. 13.6.

For the time being, it is important to acknowledge that four major stances emerge when looking at the different versions of IA actually on the market, hinging, respectively, on logico-syntactic considerations related to expressive power (as in Putnam), on general views on science and confirmation (as in Colyvan), on the notion of explanation (as in Baker) and on features of scientific practice (as in Resnik or Azzouni). It is relevant to emphasize this point, since if minimal versions of IA are to be offered, they should at least be compatible with these common stances. It is not our intention to offer a minimal formulation corresponding to each argument representative of these stances. However, we will discuss to which extent and how it is possible, from the minimal versions to be offered, to retrieve something very close to them, or at least as close as to fit with the same stances.

3 The Minimal Indispensability Argument(s)

Since our aim is to establish, with respect to available versions of IA, what a minimal argument needs retain and what it can let go, we better start by considering the features of Colyvan’s argument, which appears to be the most theoretically loaded version among the ones reviewed above. Here are some of its essential features. Firstly and obviously, it appeals to some notion of indispensability. Secondly, it is an argument for platonism, and not just for semantic realism. Thirdly, it is an argument stated in epistemic terms on two scores: on the one side, its premises and conclusions deal with what we ‘ought to’ believe, or what entities we ‘ought to’ be ontologically committed to; on the other side, it deals with the notion of justification, since ‘best’, in ‘best scientific theories’, should be understood as ‘best justified’.Footnote 13 Fourthly, it appeals to the notion of ontological commitment; here, as in most cases, Quine’s criterion ([QC]) is the relevant one.Footnote 14 Fifthly, it is claimed to rely, for the justification of its first premise, on naturalism and, sixthly and finally, on confirmational holism.

Are all of these features essential in order to obtain a version of IA? Obviously, any such version needs to retain the first feature: it requires appeal to some notion of indispensability. But things are different with the other features.

Clearly, some criterion is needed for selecting those scientific theories to which the argument is meant to apply. One can, however, either appeal here to epistemic notions or to non-epistemic notions, such as truth. We thus get a first broad distinction between arguments stated in epistemic or in non-epistemic terms.

Further, as already remarked, IA can be an argument for mathematical realism, rather than platonism, and we need to keep the two possibilities apart.

We thus end up with four possible varieties of IA: as an epistemic argument for mathematical realism, as an epistemic argument for platonism and, respectively, as a non-epistemic variety of each.

Let us begin with epistemic versions of IA for mathematical realism. As regards the selection criterion for theories, the most natural choice is for a criterion based on justification.Footnote 15 Justification, however, comes in many forms. For the time being, our appeal to it will be independent of any particular theory of justification. We could even not assume that justification for a theory is justification in believing the theory true: having justification for a scientific theory could be understood as simply having reasons, even only pragmatic ones, for adopting a scientific theory in ordinary scientific practice—e.g. because it is instrumentally helpful, or predictively accurate, or the like. This would lead to an argument along the following lines: we have a justification for some scientific theories; among them, some are such that some mathematical theories are indispensable to them; we have a justification for these scientific theories only if we a have a justification for the mathematical theories that are indispensable to them; therefore, we have a justification for the mathematical theories indispensable to these scientific theories.

No mention of truth is made here. This is prima facie consistent with Colyvan’s argument, where no mention of truth is made either. Admittedly, however, in the debate on IA—and in Colyvan’s discussion too—justification is understood as justification for the truth of a theory. We can, then, specify the argument accordingly and get the following version of IA:

Realism, epistemic [RE]

  1. i)

    We are justified in believing some scientific theories to be true;

    [We are justified in believing t is true]

  2. ii)

    Among them, some are such that some mathematical theories are indispensable to them;

    [m is indispensable to t]

  3. iii)

    We are justified in believing true these scientific theories only if we are justified in believing true the mathematical theories that are indispensable to them;

    [We are justified in believing t true only if we are justified in believing m true]

    [RE]------------------------------

  4. iv)

    We are justified in believing true the mathematical theories indispensable to these scientific theories.

    [We are justified in believing m true]

In what follows, we will take [RE] as the reference formulation for a minimal epistemic version of IA for semantic realism. [RE] is nothing but a specification of the more general argument sketched above, in which justification need not be justification for truth. Should we rest content with that more general argument, however, we could hardly obtain an argument for mathematical realism, for we would lack, unless further premises are added, any link between the justification of a theory and its truth (this is why we do not consider that version of the argument as one of our minimal versions of IA).

Since no mention of mathematical objects is made in [RE], [QC]—as any alternative criterion—is needed neither in the formulation nor in the justification of its premises. [RE] is neutral as to whether it is the existence of mathematical objects that makes the relevant mathematical theories true. [RE] would be a desirable version of IA for all those who believe in the objectivity and truth of mathematics, but would not by this fact alone qualify themselves as platonists.Footnote 16

Despite this, from [RE], an epistemic version of IA for platonism can be easily obtained by adding a premise introducing some appropriate criterion of ontological commitment:

Platonism, epistemic [PE]

  1. i)

    We are justified in believing some scientific theories to be true;

    [We are justified in believing t is true]

  2. ii)

    Among them, some are such that some mathematical theories are indispensable to them;

    [m is indispensable to t]

  3. iii)

    We are justified in believing true these scientific theories only if we are justified in believing true the mathematical theories that are indispensable to them;

    [We are justified in believing t true only if we are justified in believing m true]

  4. iv)

    We are justified in believing true a mathematical theory only if we are justified in believing the objects it is about to exist;

    [We are justified in believing m true only if we are justified in believing the objects it is about to exist]

    [PE]------------------------------

  5. v)

    We are justified in believing the objects which the indispensable mathematical theories are about to exist

    [We are justified in believing the objects m is about to exist]

Indispensability arguments are most of the time cast in epistemic terms. As Colyvan himself stresses, this epistemic character is due to a conception of ontology as a prescriptive and normative discipline: it tells us what we ought to believe to exist, or, in other terms, what we are justified in believing to exist.Footnote 17 However, one might rather conceive of ontology as a descriptive discipline and ask for arguments whose conclusions tell us that certain (sorts of) objects do exist, not just that we are justified in believing them to exist. Let us then formulate the arguments in a non-epistemic fashion:

Realism, non-epistemic [RnE]

  1. i)

    There are true scientific theories;

    [t is true]

  2. i)

    Among them, some are such that some mathematical theories are indispensable to them;

    [m is indispensable to t]

  3. iii)

    These scientific theories are true only if their indispensable mathematical theories are themselves true;

    [t is true only if m is true]

    [RnE]------------------------------

  4. iv)

    The mathematical theories indispensable to these scientific theories are trueFootnote 18

    [m is true]

Platonism, non-epistemic [PnE]

  1. i)

    There are true scientific theories;

    [t is true]

  2. ii)

    Among them, some are such that some mathematical theories are indispensable to them;

    [m is indispensable to t]

  3. iii)

    These scientific theories are true only if their indispensable mathematical theories are themselves true;

    [t is true only if m is true]

  4. iv)

    A mathematical theory is true only if the objects it is about exist;

    [m is true only if the objects m is about exist]

    [PnE]------------------------------

  5. v)

    The objects which the indispensable mathematical theories are about exist

    [The objects m is about exist]

All these four minimal versions of IA are schematic, in more than one sense. First of all, ‘t’ and ‘m’, in the bracketed version of each premise, can be substituted, respectively, with names of particular scientific and mathematical theories. Furthermore, the meaning of ‘indispensable’, ‘justification’ and ‘true’ in all four arguments can be specified in different ways, so as to get strictly different arguments according to which specification is chosen. What is relevant is that the notions of justification and truth, however specified, must be such that justification in believing a theory true and truth itself are preserved under indispensability, however the latter is specified on its turn. In arguments for platonism, moreover, premise (iv) can be further qualified according to any preferred specification of the intuitive notion of aboutness (in Quinean terms, that premise would be specified, according to [QC], by reference to quantifiers and their domain).Footnote 19

Prima facie, no such theses as naturalism and confirmational holism (or other) seem to be explicitly involved in the minimal arguments. But it remains open whether these (or other) theses are required, even as background assumptions, for the soundness of these arguments; this must be discussed in more details, especially if the relations between the minimal versions and the four arguments representative of the stances discussed in Sect. 13.2 must be spelled out. We will first pause to discuss the notion of (in)dispensability in the next section and then consider which assumptions and notions are really involved in the minimal arguments. The following discussion concerning both (in)dispensability and other relevant notions will also help clarifying how several versions of IA can be retrieved from our suggested minimal versions (cf. Sect. 13.6 below).

4 The Relational Character of (In)dispensability

Despite its obvious relevance for IA, the notion of (in)dispensability has undergone little specific analysis in the debate. What is exactly taken to be indispensable? And to what? And what does it mean to be indispensable?

As regards the first question, different aspects or ingredients of mathematics can and are taken into account in formulations of IA: the quantification over mathematical ‘entities’ or (putative) ‘objects’ (like in Putnam (1971)); mathematical entities or objects themselves, like in Colyvan (2001, p. 11) or Baker (2005) or many others; the apparent reference to such entities or objects, like in Colyvan (2001, p. 7); the assumption of the truth of some mathematical statements (viz., statements involving mathematical vocabulary), like in Resnik (1995, pp. 169–171, 1997, pp. 46–48); mathematical vocabulary (which we take to be what is often implicitly intended when authors use ‘apparent reference’), like in Colyvan (2001, p. 16); some appropriate use of mathematical statements, like in Azzouni (2009); or finally, mathematical theories.

It is possible to maintain that there are significant differences stemming from these allegedly alternative choices. Those who believe so should also consider minimal schematic versions of IA in which what is taken to be indispensable is left unspecificed. We will not dwell here on this matter, as well as on other possible parameters that fully schematic version of IA can involve (for instance, parameters specifying whether indispensability is constrained by certain goals we want our scientific theories to achieve), since we consider this at length elsewhere (cf. Panza and Sereni forthcoming). Here, we rather assume that there is a common idea underlying all the mentioned options regarding what is to be taken as indispensable, namely, that the relevant scientific theories have an essential recourse to a vocabulary fixed by some mathematical theories and then to the notions that this vocabulary is supposed to convey. As far as what is taken to be indispensable is some appropriate use of mathematical statements, we take it that what is relevant is that of the statements of a mathematical theory, or statements involving the mathematical vocabulary fixed by this theory, it is possible to make this appropriate use—while (appropriately) using (the statements of) a scientific theory. So also this option seems to reduce, with this proviso, to the option according to which it is the use of theories to be indispensable (to other theories; see below the answer to the second question).Footnote 20 Moreover, it seems to us that by literally accepting the option that what is indispensable are mathematical entities or objects themselves, one is open to an obvious risk of circularity (unless one is ready to concede that these entities or objects could be indispensable as such without existing). Here, thus, we will rest content with taking mathematical theories as what is said to be indispensable in IA, though leaving open the possibility of understanding this, when more details are given, in different ways.

Parallel considerations also apply to the second question. We will thus rest content with taking other theories, typically scientific ones, to be that for which mathematical theories are said to be indispensable in IA, although we leave open, again, the possibility of understanding this, when more details are given, in different ways.Footnote 21

The third question seems to us much more relevant. Let us focus on that, then. As will be clear, this will also help explain how some common versions of IA can be retrieved from the minimal versions through appropriate specifications of this notion.

What does it really mean that a theory is indispensable to another? Let t be a scientific theory and m a mathematical theory employed in the formulation of t. Let us call, for short, a statement employing the vocabulary of a theory m an ‘m-loaded statement’. It seems to us obvious to take m to be indispensable to t if it is not possible to obtain from t a theory t′, equivalent to t according to some specified equivalence relation, in which m-loaded statements do not occur. But, then, given any version of IA, in order to specify the indispensability condition involved in it, one has to choose the appropriate equivalence relation according to which t′ is to be taken as equivalent to t. In most cases, it seems to be tacitly admitted that the relevant equivalence relation is such that if t′ is equivalent to t according to it, then t′ preserves the descriptive and predictive power of t. This suggests taking this relation to be something like the relation of having the same empirical adequacy or that of having the same observational consequences. Still, other choices could be pertinent.

Making this choice will not be enough, however, since it is also important to make sure that the equivalence between t and t′ is not obtained by merely formal gerrymandering. This requirement captures Field’s suggestion that t′ has to be ‘reasonably attractive’ (1980, p. 8) or Colyvan’s suggestion that it must be ‘preferable’ to t (2001, p. 77). Craig’s Theorem is, for example, a well-known example of a purely formal method for obtaining from any (recursively enumerable theory) theory t involving m-loaded statements a (recursively axiomatizable theory) theory t′ that involves no such statement and has the same observational content.Footnote 22

Attractiveness and preferability are aim-specific notions, to be decided on broadly scientific criteria case by case. We can express this point in full generality by saying that t′ has to be equally or even more scientifically virtuous than t, where the appropriate criterion of virtuosity will be fixed considering common scientific virtues, according to our specific purpose.

We can thus offer the following general clarification of the notion of (in)dispensability:

[IND] (In)dispensability

A theory m is dispensable from a given scientific theory t if and only if there is a scientific theory t′ that does not include m-loaded statements and that:

  1. a)

    is ε-equivalent to t, where ε is an appropriate equivalence relation;

  2. b)

    is equally or more virtuous than t according to an appropriate criterion of virtuosity α.

If t includes m-loaded statements, and there is no scientific theory t′ satisfying the above conditions, then m is indispensable to t.

A noteworthy consequence of this definition is that common talk of (in)dispensability is partly inaccurate. No theory is (in)dispensable tout court to another theory, but only relative to a certain equivalence relation and a criterion of virtuosity. We should better speak of ε-α-(in)dispensability, rather than (in)dispensability simpliciter. (In)dispensability is an essentially relational notion.Footnote 23

According to which equivalence relation is selected, IA can have different philosophical significance. Some minimal notion of indispensability can be thought of, if the equivalence relation ε is chosen on logico-syntactical grounds (e.g. if it is taken to be the relation of having the same expressive power, i.e. of including either the same theorems or definitional paraphrases of them). But more demanding notions can be thought of. For instance, one could suggest using an equivalence relation such as that of having the same explanatory power, or cognate ones. Should theorists such as Field and Baker, building on the third of the four stances mentioned in Sect. 13.2, be willing to endorse any of the minimal IA suggested above, they could easily obtain a specification of them based on the notion of explanatory power: once ε is appropriately specified in this way, it will straightforwardly follow that m is indispensable to t only if it plays an indispensable explanatory role in t. We will come back to this below.Footnote 24

5 What Does It Takes to Be an Indispensability Argument?

In this section we explore which assumptions or theoretical ingredients generally, beyond the notion of (in)dispensability, are required in order either to formulate or to endorse one of the minimal versions of IA presented above. We begin by considering the role of doctrines such as naturalism and confirmational holism. On a fairly common understanding—and in accordance with working definitions to be given below—these doctrines are only relevant for epistemic argument, being concerned as they are with the justification of scientific theories. Other assumptions will turn out as involved in non-epistemic arguments too.

5.1 Confirmational Holism and Naturalism

Nothing—and a fortiori naturalism and holism—is required, in [RE] or [PE], to justify an all-and-only clause like that in Colyvan’s argument, simply because there is no such clause to be justified at all. However, these doctrines may still be thought to be necessary conditions for justifying some of the premises of those arguments. A related concern is whether either doctrines might represent sufficient conditions.

Apart from some aspects to be considered shortly, we will take for granted a general understanding of the notions involved (and of the vast debate concerning their proper characterization) and will merely state them in a convenient form for future reference, taking it that these formulations are those that philosophers concerned with IA have most commonly in mind:

[CH] Confirmational Holism::

[Since the appreciation of empirical evidence is in no way a matter of comparing a single fact with a single hypothesis,] the confirmation of a single hypothesis or of a system of hypotheses comes together with (or entails) the confirmation of a larger net of hypotheses (possibly of the whole net of hypotheses that our knowledge consists in).

[NAT] Naturalism::

[Since scientific theories are the only source of genuine knowledge,] we are justified in believing to be true only scientific theories, or other theories (or statements) whose truth follows from the truth of some scientific theories.

In what follows, we assume that it is legitimate to talk about the justification of mathematical and scientific theories independently of whether [CH] or [NAT] turns out to be necessary or unnecessary assumptions for the justification of any premise in the minimal arguments: [NAT], by itself, tells us only which sort of theories can be true, but is not taken as constitutive of the notion of justification; and whereas confirmation could be seen as constitutive of the justification of empirical theories, the way in which confirmation is accrued need not be such: even if confirmation is holistic, the claim that a scientific theory is justified does not presuppose by itself [CH].

If one wishes, [CH] and [NAT] could be specified further in order to have a distinctive focus on ontology and would thus state, respectively, that the confirmation of a single hypothesis or of a system of hypotheses comes together with (or entails) the confirmation of the existence of all the entities that are quantified over in a larger net of hypotheses (possibly in the whole net of hypotheses that our knowledge consists in) and that we are justified in acknowledging the existence only of those entities that are quantified over in our scientific theories. In these particular formulations, naturalism and holism could be taken to be explicitly stated—not just posited as background assumptions—in the first premise of Colyvan’s argument.

As stated, [NAT] entails the thesis that our scientific theories are our only source of genuine knowledge about the world. Many versions of naturalism are available, but in order to make it both plausible and relevant to IA, one should steer clear from at least two readings.

On the one reading, naturalism is the too strong thesis, almost indistinguishable from nominalism, that only non-abstract entities can be acknowledged to exist. Both what Colyvan (2001, Chap. 3) calls ‘Eleatic Principle’ and the version of naturalism endorsed by, for example, Weir (2005) and Armstrong (1997, p. 5) are cases in point. We agree with Colyvan that if naturalism is involved in IA at all, it cannot be of this kind, since it stands in clear contradiction with the latter’s conclusion.

On another reading, naturalism can be too weak to be relevant to IA. In discussing Quinean naturalism, Colyvan (2001, pp. 23–24) distinguishes two strands: the ‘No First Philosophy Thesis’, this being the (normative) thesis that in approaching ‘certain fundamental questions about our knowledge of the world’ we should ‘look to science (and nowhere else) for the answers’, and the ‘Continuity Thesis’, this being the (descriptive) thesis that ‘philosophy is continuous with science and that together they aim to investigate and explain the world around us’. Colyvan himself argues that these two theses are intimately related in a complex way. One thing, however, should be clear, beyond Quinean exegesis. If the Continuity Thesis is meant to claim that both science and philosophy, where this involves a priori methods of inquiry, are our only legitimate sources of knowledge about the world, the ensuing version of naturalism will not be suitable to the formulation of any empiricist argument. It can be suitable only in so far as one also adds that philosophy should abandon its traditional a priori methods and become a genuinely scientific (in the sense of empirical sciences) enterprise. But once this is added, empirical science and philosophy become utterly indistinguishable, and we come back to [NAT], with the only difference that in this new framework there is no philosophy left to be opposed to empirical sciences. The claim expressed in [NAT] seems to us to represent the most plausible reading of naturalism adequate for the formulation of an empiricist argument, as IA has been traditionally understood by Quine and his heirs. Notice, in passing, that we do believe that the ‘only’ in the formulation of [NAT] is crucial in order to distinguish naturalism from scientific realism (more on this below).

It now remains to be seen whether [CH] or [NAT] is either necessary or sufficient in order to justify any of the premises in [RE] and [PE]. Premises (ii) of each argument, as well as [PE]’s premise (iv), are beyond any suspect of guilty here.Footnote 25 So we better concentrate on premises (i) and (iii), common to both arguments. Premise (i) is liable to the charge of surreptitiously appealing to naturalism, whereas premise (iii) is liable to the charge of surreptitiously appealing to holism. Let us consider the latter first.

5.2 Can We Dispense with Confirmational Holism?

One could maybe advance a simple way to settle the question whether endorsing holism is necessary for endorsing premise (iii) of [RE] or [PE]. It would consist in suggesting that the relevant form of holism we are to consider in connection with [RE] or [PE] is not, properly speaking, confirmational holism, but some sort of holism concerning justification, and that this form of holism just consists in the claim that justification of a theory t whatsoever transmits to any other theory indispensable to t. In this case, the very claim that the justification of a scientific theory s transmits to a mathematical theory m indispensable to s would reduce to a mere instance of such a version of holism, so that the latter would be sufficient, yet not necessary, for endorsing this claim and, then, premise (iii) of [RE] or [PE].

Moreover, such a form of holism would not only be different from that which is usually at stake when the relation between holism and IA is discussed, which is confirmational holism proper, that is, a form of holism specifically concerned with confirmation, rather than with justification in general; it would also be a quite Pickwickian form of holism, since it would merely require that justification transmits from a theory t to another theory so intimately connected to it as the indispensability of the latter for the former implies. Of course, in order to admit that this is so, one should maintain that indispensability is so specified as to warrant this transmission. Still, this is not the point here. What is relevant is rather that such a form of holism would restrict the transmission of justification from theory to theory to a case in which the relevant theories are related by a certain sort of intimate connection. But, if a proper form of holism of justification should be defended, it should rather consist in claiming that justification transmits much more widely, along a larger net of theories or hypotheses (possibly along the whole web of hypotheses that our knowledge consists in), without constraints such as indispensability.

The situation would be even more outlandish if one argued that the relevant form of holism consists in the claim that justification of a scientific theory s transmits to a mathematical theory m indispensable to s (since it would be odd to maintain that a sort of holism concerned with justification, in general, is restricted to the consideration of scientific and mathematical theories), or that confirmational holism, as such, consists in the claim that justification of a scientific theory s transmits to a mathematical theory m indispensable to s (since it would be odd to maintain that confirmational holism generally concerns justification, rather than confirmation). In this latter case, premise (iii) of [RE] or [PE] would just be the same as confirmational holism, and it would be beyond doubt that endorsing the latter is necessary for endorsing the former. It seems however plain to us that confirmational holism is a different and wider thesis: not only it is concerned with confirmation rather than with justification, but also it is not merely limited to the case in which confirmation is transferred from a scientific theory s to a mathematical theory m that is indispensable to s.

All these considerations lead us to discard from the very beginning the simple possibilities just evoked and to focus on confirmational holism proper, conceived as the very claim [CH].

A first, preliminary, difficulty is the following. Apparently, there is a striking asymmetry between the condition expressed in premise (iii) and that expressed in [CH]: the latter seems to express an inference from a part to the whole, whereas premise (iii) seems to express an inference from the whole to a part. We need therefore to understand how the two might be related in any way relevant (either sufficiently or necessarily) for lending support to premise (iii).

Under a quite weak reading of it, [CH] states that when a single hypothesis h of a theory s is confirmed, the whole s is confirmed, which we express in symbols by ‘C(h) → C(s)’, where ‘C(x)’ stands for ‘x is confirmed’. If we admit that a mathematical theory m involved in a scientific theory s counts as a cluster of hypotheses of s, one can replace here ‘C(h)’ with ‘C(m)’, so as to get the new implication ‘C(m) → C(s)’. It is however clear that this implication (be it admissible or not) is hardly useful in an argument whose purpose is that of building on considerations about some scientific theories in order to draw conclusions about some mathematical theories appropriately connected to the former. At most, the reciprocal implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ could be relevant. But if a mathematical theory m involved in a scientific theory s counts as a cluster of hypotheses of s, and we take confirmation to be cumulative, i.e. to be such that a conjunction of hypothesis (or of other items susceptible of confirmation) can only be confirmed by confirming all its conjuncts (which entails, of course, that confirmation is d’emblée also distributive: if a conjunction of hypothesis is confirmed, its conjuncts are so), this implication is trivial, since, whatever confirmation might come to in details, it is immediate to see that under this conception a theory cannot count as confirmed as a whole if some of its hypothesis are not so. Hence, in this case, arguing for this implication requires no appeal to any strong and/or controversial thesis, as confirmational holism appears to be.

Things change, however, if a mathematical theory m involved in a scientific theory s is rather taken to count as an auxiliary theory that s appeals to, without encompassing it, or if confirmation is not taken to be cumulative (so that it cannot be granted that it is distributive, d’emblée), namely, if it is admitted that a conjunction of hypothesis (or of other items susceptible of confirmation) can be directly confirmed as a whole (i.e. without going through a confirmation of all its conjuncts). Under both scenarios the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ becomes far from trivial: it asserts that confirming (in one way or another) a scientific theory s goes with (or is sufficient for) confirming either an auxiliary mathematical theory m, which s appeals to, but that is not included in s (under the former scenario), or a mathematical theory m that s encompasses, even if the confirmation of m is not, as such, involved in that of s (under the latter scenario). It seems to us that it is only under one of these scenarios that there is room for plausibly considering the possibility that [RE] and [PE] be somehow related with [CH], provided, of course, that a reading of [CH] be adopted, according to which this thesis entails that confirming a scientific theory s goes with (or is sufficient for) confirming an auxiliary mathematical theory m, which s appeals to, but that is not included in s, or a mathematical theory m that s encompasses, within a framework in which confirmation is not taken to be cumulative.

It is not our purpose here to argue in favour either of one of these two possible scenarios or of this reading of [CH]. We merely suppose, for the sake of the argument, that both one of the former and the latter are admitted, while contending that if this is not so (i.e. either both of the former or the latter are rejected), there is no plausible reason for connecting [RE] and [PE] with [CH]. In other terms, we admit, for the sake of the argument, that [CH] entails ‘C(s) → C(m)’, provided that s and m are, respectively, a scientific and a mathematical theory and that either s appeals to m, without encompassing it, or s encompasses m but confirmation is not taken to be cumulative. For short, in what follow we shall call ‘weak condition’ (for reasons that will become clear below) the condition involved in this supposition, namely, that either s appeals to m, without encompassing it, or s encompasses m, provided that confirmation is not taken to be cumulative.

Now, also admitting, under this same condition, that ‘C(s) → C(m)’ entails [CH] would be quite implausible, since, however it might be conceived, confirmational holism can certainly not be reduced to a thesis about the confirmational relation between scientific and mathematical theories under some condition whatsoever. The possibility still remains open, however, of admitting—for the sake of the argument, again, but without falling into an evident oddity—that, when confronted with a scientific theory s and a mathematical theory m, under the weak condition, one has no other ground than [CH] for arguing that C(s) → C(m). This is just what we admit. For the purpose of our following discussion, we can then suppose that, under the weak condition, endorsing [CH] is necessary for endorsing premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE] if endorsing the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ is necessary for this. As regards the issue whether [CH] is sufficient for endorsing this same premise, things are much simpler. Since, if [CH] entails ‘C(s) → C(m)’ and ‘C(s) → C(m)’ entails this premises, then [CH] entails this premise. We can then limit our enquiry to this question: is endorsing the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’, under the weak condition, necessary or sufficient for endorsing premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE]?

Let us come back, then, to this premise. It states that justification to believe a mathematical theory m, indispensable to a scientific theory s, to be true is a necessary condition for having justification to believe that s is true. Let us call this the ‘s-m justificatory connection under indispensability’. We can express it in symbols by: ‘Ind(m, s) → [J(s) → J(m)]’, where ‘J(x)’ stands for ‘we are justified in believing x true’. What we have to investigate is, then, whether the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ (which, for the sake of the argument, we take as a consequence of [CH]) is either necessary or sufficient to motivate the s-m justificatory connection under indispensability, under the weak condition.

5.2.1 Is Confirmational Holism Necessary for Premise (iii)?

That confirmational holism might be unnecessary for IA has been already suggested, on different grounds, by several authors (e.g. Resnik 1995; Dieveney 2007; Azzouni 2009), including Colyvan himself.Footnote 26 Taking much of this discussion for granted, what we are interested here is, as we have said, simply whether the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ needs to be assumed in order to defend our minimal (epistemic) versions of IA, especially whether it is required for upholding premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE]. In order for this to be the case, there must be no way of supporting the s-m justificatory connection without appealing to this implication. We shall argue that it is not so.

A first problem arises straightaway. Both our admissions that [CH] entails the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ and that one has no other ground than [CH] for arguing that C(s) → C(m) have been conditioned by the weak condition. This last condition is, however, much weaker than that involved in the s-m justificatory connection under indispensability, namely, that m is indispensable to s. Hence, one could contend that, in the case where the latter condition obtains, i.e. when m is indispensable to s, one should rely on grounds other than [CH] for arguing that C(s) → C(m). Insofar as we are not at all willing to discard this possibility (that we rather consider favourably, as we shall see later), we suggest to abstract from the supposition that m is indispensable to s, by resting content with the weaker supposition that s and m are, respectively, a scientific and a mathematical theory and that the weak condition obtains. We want then, firstly, to argue against the view that, under this condition, endorsing the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’—and then [CH]—is necessary for endorsing that justification to believe m is a necessary condition for having justification to believe that s is true. Let us call this last claim the ‘s-m justificatory connection’, tout court. We can express it in symbols by: ‘J(s) → J(m)’. We shall come back later to the question whether, under the weak condition, the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ (taken as a consequence of [CH]) is necessary to motivate the s-m justificatory connection under indispensability.

Our first point is as follows. Under some conceptions of science, like falsificationism, the link between the confirmation of a scientific theory and its justification is severed. In such conceptions, empirical confirmation of the (testable) hypotheses of a scientific theory s, whatever advantages it may deliver and whatever it might be considered to consist in, will not essentially contribute to the justification of s. Still, even if one endorsed such views, one may of course still maintain, under the weak condition, the s-m justificatory connection and, a fortiori, the s-m justificatory connection under indispensability. Even if it is conceded that confirmation is holistic, i.e. that [CH] is true, the fact that C(s) → C(m) will simply play no role, in these views, to support the claim that J(s) → J(m), under whatever supplementary condition.

Another way of showing that endorsing the implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ is unnecessary for endorsing that the s-m justificatory connection, under the weak condition, consists in noticing that this connection could be (vacuously) endorsed by anyone considered to have reasons for taking m to be justified independently of any consideration about its role in or with respect to s (and, then, a fortiori, of m’s being indispensable to s). This would be the case, for example, for anyone that maintained to have a priori reasons for believing in the necessary truth of m (and would then, at most, take its indispensability to s together with s’s being justified as a welcome by-product): the s-m justificatory connection (and, a fortiori, the s-m justificatory connection under indispensability) will be motivated without appealing to holism, nor to confirmation at all. This would make whatever empirical confirmation we can have for s (be its nature holistic or not) immaterial to the justification of m. Such an option will certainly not be welcomed by many supporters of IA. On the one hand, many of them also adopt a form of naturalism that ban a priori arguments. On the other hand, and most importantly, such an option seems to make IA pointless. Still nothing prevents one from accepting IA even under these circumstances.Footnote 27 In any case, what all this shows is that the s-m justificatory connection is, in general, conceptually independent of the notion of confirmation (and a fortiori of [CH]) and is then so also under the weak condition. More generally, one of the basic idea underlying IA (cf. e.g. Putnam 1975a, p. 74) that one cannot be a realist about science and at the same time an antirealist about mathematics needs not be supported by confirmational holism.Footnote 28

Le us concede, now, both that (against the first point) empirical confirmation is an essential ingredient to the justification of a scientific theory (i.e. that J(s) → C(s)) and that (against the second point) we are after a defence of the s-m justificatory connection, under the weak condition, which is not based on having reasons independent of m’s role in, or with respect to, s (possibly a priori ones) to believe in the necessary truth of m. Since the s-m justificatory connection only consists in the implication ‘J(s) → J(m)’, for the other implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’ to be necessary for this connection, it must be the case that (J(s) → J(m)) → (C(s) → C(m)). But once one explores ways of defending this implication, it becomes apparent that it is unmotivated.

Insofar as we have conceded that confirmation of s is a necessary ingredient of its justification, what we have to consider is whether, under the weak condition, [(J(s) → C(s)) & (J(s) → J(m))] → (C(s) → C(m)). Suppose that s is justified. Then, for the premise of this implication, it follows that s is also confirmed and that also m is justified. If this were enough for concluding that m is confirmed, under the weak condition, our implication would be verified. But, why should be so? It would be so if, once s is justified and then confirmed, the only way in which its justification could be transferred to m, under the weak condition, were that s’s confirmation transferred to m and that m’s confirmation were sufficient for its justification. But this is clearly unmotivated. Why should the only way in which justification of s transfers to m, under the weak condition, be through the transfer of s’s confirmation to m? We have assumed that confirmation of s is necessary for its justification, not that it is also sufficient; so it could well be the case that m’s justification be due, under the weak condition, to ingredients of s’s justification other than its confirmation. Moreover, why (both under the weak condition or not) should m’s confirmation be sufficient for its justification? And why, anyway, should one be forced to admit that a mathematical theory is open to confirmation, in order to conclude that m is justified provided that s is so and the weak condition obtains?

The situation does not change essentially if the supposition that the confirmation of s is a necessary ingredient of its justification is replaced by the other supposition that the confirmation of s is sufficient of its justification. In this case, what we would have to consider is whether, under the weak condition, [(C(s) → J(s)) & (J(s) → J(m))] → (C(s) → C(m)). Suppose that s is confirmed; then, for the premise of this implication, it follows that m is justified. Again, if this were enough for concluding that m is confirmed, under the weak condition, our implication would be verified. But, again, this is unjustified, and equally unjustified is the claim that from these suppositions it follows that a mathematical theory is open to confirmation (both under the weak condition or not).

All in all, the only way of claiming that [CH] is necessary for the justification of the s-m justificatory connection under the weak condition is to assume that, under this condition, the confirmation of s and the justification of m are sufficient for the justification of s and for the confirmation of m, that is, that C(s) → J(s) and J(m) → C(m), since it is easy to see that ‘[(C(s) → J(s)) & (J(m) → C(m)) & (J(s) → J(m))] → (C(s) → C(m))’ is a tautology. Still, supposing that the confirmation of s is sufficient for its justification is utterly implausible, since it results in disregarding the well-known issue that empirical confirmation will not distinguish between incompatible and still empirically equivalent theories, and that in most cases what bestows justification on a theory is, besides confirmation, a combination of many other virtues (some of which being even a priori), such as simplicity, unificatory power, explicatory power, ontological parsimony and fruitfulness. Moreover, supposing that the justification of m is sufficient for its confirmation requires admitting that a mathematical theory is open to confirmation, which is something that does seem to be required neither by the weak condition nor by the s-m justificatory connection under this same condition. Of course, if this were admitted and were also admitted that the justification of m is sufficient for its confirmation, one could add a supplementary conclusion to [RE] to the effect that the relevant mathematical theories are not merely justified but also confirmed, but this is far from mandatory for [RE] to work.

Up to here, we have avoided considering m as indispensable to s, by merely supposing that the weak condition obtains and investigating whether endorsing [CH] could be taken as necessary for endorsing the s-m justificatory connection under this condition. Let us now suppose that m is indispensable to s, as any version of AI requires, and investigate whether endorsing [CH] could be taken as necessary for endorsing the s-m justificatory connection under indispensability, that is, the premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE]. It seems to us that, in this case, even if one accepts that confirmation is relevant, necessary or even sufficient for the justification of m, it becomes still more evident that [CH] is not required for the purpose. Indeed, if we take m as indispensable to s, it is reasonable to expect that the grounds for arguing that C(s) → C(m) should be sought in that very fact, i.e. in whatever intimate connection is established between s and m by the very fact that the latter is indispensable to the former. This is not to take for granted that the notion of indispensability, under whatever specification, together with the admission that m is indispensable to s (under the relevant specification), will be able by itself to deliver these grounds. As a matter of fact, arguing that it is so does should be one of the main tasks of a supporter of IA. The point is just that, once the indispensability of m to s is assumed, it is reasonable to expect that it, and it alone, would allow one to claim that C(s) → C(m), without requiring the help of [CH], which is, in fact, a much wider claim not constrained by an indispensability condition.Footnote 29

The unpalatable consequences of the assumption of [CH] in IA when compared to actual mathematical practice—especially with the conscious use by scientists of false assumptions and idealizations—has been stressed by Maddy (1992).Footnote 30 Apart from this, the main point, for us, is that [CH] is either irrelevant for AI (in the case in which no clear appropriate connection between justification and confirmation is admitted) or it is an overkill (in the case in which this appropriate connection is admitted), since it delivers much more than it is actually required to defend IA, thus being an unnecessarily strong thesis.Footnote 31

Indeed, the mere fact that an appeal to indispensability is thought to be relevant—which is already emphasised by the very expression ‘indispensability argument’ usually chosen to denote the argument under consideration—seems to be an indicator that such an argument is essentially grounded on that notion, and not on the much wider one of confirmational holism.

True, holism is usually required to rule out the possibility that statements about theoretical or mathematical objects might be confirmation resistant, as opposed to observational statements. However, if in [PE] one endorses, following Quine, a criterion for ontological commitment that is uniform across statements—i.e. based on the logical form of statements and content neutral—one will have as a consequences that all entities whose existence is entailed by one’s criterion will be said to exist, observational and theoretical alike. If one believes in the truth of premises (i)–(iii) of [PE] and has a uniform criterion of ontological commitment, confirmational holism, again, is not needed, for this purpose.Footnote 32

5.2.2 Is Confirmational Holism Sufficient for Premise (iii)?

As regards the sufficiency of endorsing [CH] for endorsing premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE], things are by far simpler. Since, if one supposes both that m is indispensable to s and, merely, that the weak condition obtains, in order to draw the implication ‘J(s) → J(m)’ from the other implication ‘C(s) → C(m)’, it is then necessary and sufficient to admit that J(s) → C(s) and C(m) → J(m). Hence, for premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE] to follow from [CH] it is sufficient that confirmation for the relevant scientific theories is taken to be necessary for their justification, and confirmation for the relevant mathematical theories is taken to be sufficient for their justification. Moreover, if we suppose that, when confronted with the relevant theories s and m, one has no other ground than [CH] for arguing that C(s) → C(m), these two conditions (taken together) are also necessary. Under this supposition, wondering whether endorsing [CH] is sufficient for endorsing premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE] reduces to wondering whether confirmation for the relevant scientific theories is necessary for their justification and confirmation for the relevant mathematical theories is sufficient for their justification.

The former of these conditions could be questioned, but it seems to us to be safely admissible in general, that is, for most of our scientific theories.Footnote 33 For it is plausible to grant that, in general, any virtue a scientific theory may have will not confer justification to it in absence of confirmation.

The latter condition is more questionable, instead. One reason for this has already been mentioned: consenting to it requires admitting that mathematical theories are open to confirmation, which could be plausibly questioned (and is, in any case, nor required for endorsing IA). Another reason is that contending that confirmation of a mathematical theory, whatever it might be taken to be, is sufficient for its justification results in disregarding any a priori virtue that such a theory could have as a necessary ingredient of its justification. Finally, even someone, presumably endorsing a proto-empiricist view on mathematics, who is ready to admit that mathematical theories are open to confirmation and that no a priori virtue of a mathematical theory is required for it to be justified (when it is well supported by a posteriori or empirical evidences) could face that the same difficulty raised above (Sect. 13.5.2.1) for the thesis that confirmation of a scientific theory is sufficient for its justification, since this thesis also applies, mutatis mutandis, in the case of mathematical theories.

5.3 Can We Dispense with Naturalism?

What about now premise (i) of [RE] and [PE]? Do we need to assume naturalism, in any form, in order to claim that we are justified in believing some scientific theory to be true? What seems clear is that some form of scientific realism will have to be assumed. For a fairly standard characterization, we can describe scientific realism as the thesis that our mature scientific theories are true or, at least, approximately true descriptions of an external, mind-independent reality, that their statements should be interpreted at face value (both when they speak of observable entities and when they speak of theoretical ones) and that the objects of which they speak do inhabit the world (cf. Psillos (1999, p. xix) for a more extended definition on these lines). In order to defend premise (i) in [RnE] and [PnE], we need to maintain that there are true scientific theories, and this implies a form of scientific realism. Moreover, some arguably milder form of scientific realism will be needed also for defending premise (i) in [RE] and [PE]. This milder form of realism should at least accept that we are justified in believing that there are true scientific theories (without necessarily taking the further step of claiming that there are, or were, or will be some).Footnote 34

Now, scientific realism, in one form or other, is likely to be a basic assumption underlying naturalism. Quine himself listed ‘unregenerate realism’ among the sources of naturalism (Quine 1975, p. 72). But in order to justify premise (i) of [RE] and [PE], only some form of scientific realism is needed, and whereas naturalism implies (or might imply, depending on the chosen formulation) scientific realism, the latter does not imply the former. Where naturalism hinges on endorsing that scientific theories are the only source of genuine knowledge, with the result that we are justified in believing to be true only these theories or those whose truth follows from the latter’s truth, scientific realism only implies that scientific theories are a kind of theories in whose truth we are allowed to be justified. This is not to deny that realism can be fruitfully combined with a naturalist position. It can even be maintained that the adoption of naturalism facilitates—since it implies it—the adoption of scientific realism. However, nothing prevents someone who believes, for example, that genuinely philosophical a priori arguments are a reliable source of knowledge, from believing, provided that conflicting results are avoided and that (mature, predictively successful, well-confirmed, etc.) scientific theories are sufficiently reliable sources too. It is not difficult to think of scientific realists that are not naturalists. For an illustrious case, consider Frege, who had realistic views about scientific inquiry but surely was not a naturalist, as his views on mathematics show.

It then seems that insofar as endorsing [NAT] requires (entails) endorsing scientific realism, the former could thus well be a sufficient for endorsing premise (i) of [RE] and [PE], but clearly it is not necessary.Footnote 35

This being established, one could still wonder whether endorsing [NAT] is necessary or sufficient for endorsing any other premise of [RE] and [PE]. The only plausible candidate for this is premise (iii), which plays in these arguments the role that premise (i) of Colyvan’s argument plays in this latter argument. As we have mentioned in Sect. 13.2, Colyvan indeed argues that naturalism is required in order to justify the only-direction of this latter premise. Still, we have also already observed that this direction is, in fact, useless for drawing the argument’s conclusion and has, accordingly, no correlate in premise (iii) of [RE] and [PE].

At most, then, one can argue that the endorsement of [NAT] is necessary for endorsing a strengthened variant of this premise that would state that we are justified in believing true all and only the mathematical theories that are indispensable to scientific theories that we are justified in believing to be true. This variant would still be involved only in variants of [RE] and [PE] whose conclusions are, in turn, strengthened variants of the conclusions of these arguments, giving conditions which are also necessary and not merely sufficient for our being justified, respectively, in believing true the relevant mathematical theories and in believing the objects which these are about to exist.

6 Retrieving Common Arguments from the Minimal Arguments

It is easy to see how the suggested minimal versions of IA could serve as a basis for the stances on IA represented by Putnam’s, Colyvan’s and Baker’s arguments, respectively (cf. Sect. 13.2). Putnam’s argument is nothing but a variant of [PnE] (or, depending on the reading of Putnam’s text, [PE]). Colyvan’s argument is a variant of the epistemic version of IA that results from adding to premise (iii) of [PE] the redundant assumption that we are justified in believing true only the mathematical theories that are indispensable to scientific theories that we are justified in believing to be true.Footnote 36 Finally, as anticipated at the end of Sect. 13.4, Baker’s Enhanced Indispensability Argument, can be retrieved from [PE] once an appropriate equivalence relation ε is selected in the specification of the notion of (in)dispensability, e.g. the relation of having the same explanatory power.Footnote 37

Things are more complex with arguments in the pragmatic stance.

Let us begin with Resnik’s. This is very different in form from all other representative versions of IA that we have reviewed. It seems clear that it dispenses with confirmational holism.Footnote 38 It is instead not clear whether it also dispenses with naturalism. According to Resnik himself the passage from its premise (vi) to (vii) is justified by naturalism, which he briefly defines as the thesis that ‘natural science is our ultimate arbiter of truth and existence’,Footnote 39 and considers as suitable for ruling out scepticism about the justification and truth of our scientific theories. Still, it is not clear how naturalism can warrant the passage from the justification of some theories, and particularly of mathematical ones, to their truth, a passage which is surely hard to secure. More generally, it is far from clear that Resnik’s argument is valid (or admit, at least, a valid rephrasing). It is thus not surprising that it is hard to retrieve it from our minimal versions, which are clearly valid. This remains, however, a unicum with respect to the ongoing debate.

Notice, on the other hand, that it is not clear whether the role played by the notion of justification in Resnik’s argument is in any sense cognate to that played by it in our minimal arguments. We take justification as applying to statements or bodies of statements and as being justification for their truth, and not just for their adoption for whatever practical reasons. Resnik does firstly conceive justification as applying (if not uniquely, also) to acts, rather than bodies of statements; and secondly he bases our ‘accepting as true such mathematics as science uses’ on the pragmatic ground that ‘we are justified in doing science’ and that science, when considered in its practice, proceeds through various mathematical assumptions—and not rather on the fact that any scientific theory is even approximately true. If Resnik’s argument were (valid and) sound, this could be seen as an advantage, since it would make the argument independent of the supposition that some scientific theories are true. If (valid and) sound, this argument would thus dispense with scientific realism, as Resnik (1997, pp. 46–47) suggests (and this should be so despite Resnik’s quite doubtful claim that the passage from conclusion (vi) to conclusion (vii) depends on naturalism, understood as the thesis that ‘natural science is our ultimate arbiter of truth and existence’, a thesis which could hardly be taken as independent from a form of scientific realism).

Let us consider now Azzouni’s argument, namely, his Assertoric-use QP.Footnote 40 This deserves more careful consideration, since it is the one that comes closest to resembling, at least in spirit, some of our suggested minimal versions, at least insofar as it is, as we said in Sect. 13.2, explicitly meant to avoid presupposition of either holism or naturalism.Footnote 41 Also the distinction between arguments for mathematical realism and for platonism is suggested by Azzouni (2004), who questions [QC] and argues at length that IA can at most be an argument for the truth of mathematical theories, but that it falls short of supporting platonism.Footnote 42

The first thing to be noticed is that Azzouni’s Assertoric-use QP stems from an interpretation of the ‘enthymematic blueprint’ quoted above in Sect. 13.2, but is not regimented in the form of a codified non-enthymematic (valid) argument with enumerated and explicitly stated premises and conclusion(s). Enquiring whether it can be retrieved from one of our minimal versions of IA requires, then, some reinterpretation of Azzouni’s proposals.

Prima facie, given that there is no mention of epistemic notions like justification in Azzouni’s blueprint, the relevant minimal version of IA with which his argument should be compared seems to be [RnE]. However, the way in which Azzouni motivates the passage from the blueprint to the Assertoric-use QP suggests another option.

Azzouni’s strategy for obtaining the Assertoric-use QP depends, firstly, on the specification of the single premise of the former, i.e. ‘certain statements that quantify over mathematical entities are indispensable to science’, as the claim that the ‘assertoric use’ of the relevant statements, which quantify over mathematical entities, is indispensable to science. According to Azzouni,Footnote 43 it is an empirical fact that people use certain statements assertorically while doing science, for the two aims of presenting statements as following from other statements previously made (‘deductive use’) and of describing state of affairs (‘representational use’). A second empirical fact is said to beFootnote 44 that given our ordinary understanding of the word ‘true’, the assertoric use of a statement p entails, via Tarksi’s biconditionals, the commitment of those who assertorically use p to the truth of p. From this second empirical fact, it follows that the conclusion of the blueprint should be intended as the claim that we are committed to the truth of those statements whose assertoric use is indispensable to science. Although different readings can be given to the expression ‘we are committed to the truth of p’, we take it that the more plausible one, consistent with Azzouni’s discussion, is as ‘we are justified in believing p true’.Footnote 45 Assuming that this is so, it follows that the most appropriate among our minimal versions of IA to be compared with Azzouni’s Assertoric-use QP is [RE].

Two questions arise here: whether Azzouni’s version of IA is eventually to be considered more minimal than [RE] and whether his version can indeed be retrieved from [RE].

As to the first question, a clue for a positive answer could come from the fact that [RE] appeals to the notion of truth (thought of as a schematic notion, variously specifiable), whereas Azzouni’s argument doesn’t explicitly appear to do so. Still, the latter relies on the fact that assertoric use of mathematical statements is indispensable to scientific practice, and this is taken to entail commitment to the truth of these statements just in virtue of the Tarskian biconditionals which ‘transform assertoric uses into truth commitments’.Footnote 46 Moreover, Azzouni arguesFootnote 47 that ‘if I assertorically use a sentence,Footnote 48 I recognize myself as bound by implication to the original sentence prefixed by ‘It’s true that … ”, which results in maintaining that there is a rather intimate connection between assertion and truth. But if this is so, then truth, if not explicitly used in the premises of the argument, is presupposed by the very notions of assertion and assertoric use by means of which the argument is built up. It may even well be explicitly mentioned in a premise of the argument once all its underlying assumptions are brought to the fore.Footnote 49 Hence, if the issue is the appeal to some notion of truth, then, it is far from clear that Azzouni’s argument is in any sense more minimal than [RE].

A second related clue for a positive answer to the first question is that the conclusion of Azzouni’s Assertoric-use QP appears to be derived without explicitly assuming that we are justified in believing some scientific theories to be true. However, as Azzouni himself acknowledges,Footnote 50 his argument has as accompanying premise: ‘the au-indispensability of the scientific sentences themselves (given a commitment to the scientific project)’, where the term ‘au-indispensability’ is a shortened form of ‘indispensability of the assertoric use’. It seems, moreover, plausible, in the light of our previous discussion, to understand the commitment to the scientific project as a justification in the truth of these scientific statements and then, presumably, in some scientific theories.

Be that as it may, these considerations suggest that Azzouni’s argument is possibly not to be considered more minimal than [RE], but rather very close to it, at least in spirit. We should then move to our second question.

What we have said so far suggests that both the single premise and the conclusion of Azzouni’s blueprint should be specified by making explicit the assumption of our commitment to the scientific project intended as a commitment to (the truth) of those statements whose assortoric use is indispensable to this project, and by stating the conclusion in an epistemic form. The ensuing formulation will thus be this:

Assertoric-use QP (I)

  1. i)

    We are committed to (the truth of) those statements that are au-indispensable to the scientific project;

  2. ii)

    Some statements that quantify over mathematical entities are au-indispensable to the scientific project;

    ------------------------------

  3. iii)

    We are committed to (the truth of) these statements.

Above we have mentioned the accompanying premise of Azzouni’s argument concerning the ‘au-indispensability of the scientific sentences themselves’. The whole passage where this premises is put forward seems to suggest that the indispensability of the assertoric use of the relevant statements that quantify over mathematical entities is to be, as it were, split into the au-indispensability of both some scientific and some mathematical statements. It goes as followsFootnote 51: ‘I […] read the premise of the ethymemic blueprint of the QP as stating that many sentences of mathematics are au-indispensable to science. Accompanying this premise is the assumption of the au-indispensability of the scientific sentences themselves (given a committed to the scientific project)’. The statements that quantify over mathematical entities and are au-indispensable to the scientific project mentioned in Assertoric-use QP (I) seem here to be those that in this passage are referred to as ‘sentences of mathematics [that] are au-indispensable to science’.Footnote 52 This suggests that the statements here referred to as ‘the scientific sentences themselves’ do not quantify over mathematical entities, but are such that they can be assertorically used only if some mathematical statements (which rather do) are so used (e.g. insofar as the former involve individual or predicate constants defined through the latter). It would follow that the au-indispensability to the scientific project of the mathematical statements mentioned in Assertoric-use QP (I) just depends on this, namely, on their being such that those scientific statements whose assertoric use is indispensable to the scientific project are such that they can be assertorically used only if these mathematical statements are so used. If we express this condition by saying that the latter statements are au-indispensable to the former, Assertoric-use QP (I) can then be restated and further expanded as follows:

Assertoric-use QP (II)

  1. i)

    We are committed to (the truth of) those statements that are au-indispensable to the scientific project;

  2. ii)

    Some mathematical statements are au-indispensable to some statements that are au-indispensable to the scientific project;

  3. iii)

    We are committed to the truth of those statements that are au-indispensable to the scientific project only if we are committed to the truth of those mathematical statements that are au-indispensable to them;

    ------------------------------

  4. iv)

    We are committed to (the truth of) these mathematical statements.

This latter version of IA is clearly similar, in structure and content, to [RE]. Once it is conceded that ‘being committed to the scientific project’ can be interpreted as ‘being justified in believing some scientific theories to be true’, premise (i) of Assertoric-use QP (II) can, indeed, be conceived as a specification of premise (i) of [RE]. Following Azzouni, one may say that the former is justified by the empirical fact that when we assertorically use a statement p, we are committed (via Tarski biconditionals) to the truth of it. If premise (ii) of [RE] is then specified by employing the notion of assertoric use in the specification of the ε equivalence relation involved in the schematic notion of indispensability—so that the assertoric use of certain mathematical statements turns out to be indispensable to the assertoric use of those scientific statements that we must assertorically use if we are committed to the scientific project—what one gets is just premise (ii) of Assertoric-use QP (II). As regards premise (iii), it is easy to see that the s-m justificatory connection can be specified by considering that the commitment to the truth of the statements of s, following via Tarski biconditionals from their assertoric use, can be granted only in presence of a similar commitment, via the same route, for the mathematical statements of m that are au-indispensable to s: this does not seem to add nothing that Azzouni would not consider as implicit in his own argument.Footnote 53 Premise (iii) of Assertoric-use QP (II) just results from this specification of premise (iii) of [RE], with the implicit assumption that assertoric use of p entails commitment to the truth of p. Once [RE] is appropriately specified, then, the conclusion of Assertoric-use QP (II) is nothing by an alternative though equivalent formulation of the conclusion of [RE], as one may expect by alternative versions of an argument that are meant to support a common conclusion.

If we are correct, and Assertoric-use QP (II) is a plausible reconstruction, in explicit non-enthymematic form, of the version of IA that Azzouni has in mind, then it seems susceptible of being retrieved from [RE] through appropriate specifications of the notions involved.Footnote 54

7 The Philosophical Significance of the Indispensability Argument

Much of the recent discussion on IA has focused on holism and naturalism. Many authors have either criticized IA, taking Colyvan’s as the most relevant formulation, or offered alternative versions of it. Both supporters and critics, with few exceptions we have mentioned above, take naturalism and holism to be essential to this argument or, more generally, to what is usually referred to as ‘the Quine-Putnam Indispensability Argument’ and discuss the alleged dependence of the argument on these doctrines. For example, Maddy (1992, 2007) claims that IA fails because of inescapable clashes between the notions of holism and naturalism (as Quine conceived of it) and essential features of mathematical and scientific practice and methodology; relying on a non-holistic notion of confirmation, Sober (1993) argues that empirical evidence cannot even indirectly justify mathematical theories.

As it turns out, minimal versions of IA can be devised that are far less demanding than the so-called Quine-Putnam Indispensability Argument. Only scientific realism (beyond, obviously, a proper characterization of (in)dispensability) will be an essential ingredient in justifying premise (i) in [RE] and [RnE]. In order to obtain a platonist conclusion, thus to support [PE] and [PnE], only an appropriate criterion for ontological commitment—arguably, Quine’sFootnote 55—needs to be further assumed (together with what is needed to justify the remaining premises).

It is often thought that IA is especially suited for those mathematical (semantical or ontological) realists working in a broadly empiricist framework. As Shapiro claims:

Indispensability arguments are anathema to those, like the logicists, logical positivists, and neologicists, who maintain the traditional views that mathematics is absolutely necessary and/or analytic and/or knowable a priori.Footnote 56

This is an obvious philosophical outcome for versions of IA that proceed under the assumption of naturalism and deliver necessary conditions for their conclusions (cf. the end of Sect. 13.5.3). But this need not be so: when naturalism is left out of the picture, the argument only gives sufficient conditions for either semantic realism or platonism.

Clearly, if we espouse a naturalist ideology, we will better make our argument for mathematical (semantic or ontological) realism rely, more or less explicitly, on naturalism and thus secure (semantic or ontological) realism in a way that is consistent with our naturalist viewpoint. But it is not, as it were, in the very nature of IA to give sufficient and necessary conditions for its conclusions. It might just be our particular interest to have a version of it giving both.

IA is not a naturalist argument per se. We see no ban in principle, for those who believe in the a priori character of mathematical truths, against the acceptance of indispensability arguments.Footnote 57 Modest antinaturalists of this sortFootnote 58 will claim at most that IA is superfluous, or ancillary, since they can offer reasons for the same conclusion(s) that are by far more certain than the contingent grounds on which IA hinges. But this is definitely different from rejecting the argument.

The point is that the real anathema for all those philosophers listed by Shapiro in his quotation is not IA itself: it is naturalism. Any argument relying on naturalism will be anathema for them: IA can, but need not, be a good candidate.

On this respect, it is remarkable that, after long time, Putnam himself recently felt the need of making his voice heard again in this debate. Commenting on Colyvan’s argument, Putnam clearly remarks that the ‘only’ direction of premise (i) of this argument—the one committing a supporter of the argument to naturalism—expresses a thesis he ‘never subscribed to in [his] life’.Footnote 59 He stresses that his adoption of IA was meant to show—as already suggested in Putnam (1971, 1975b)—that it is incoherent to adopt scientific realism and at the same time reject (semantic) realism about mathematics. Moreover, he is explicit in claiming that:

nevertheless, there was a common premise in my argument and Quine’s […] That premise was “scientific realism”, by which I meant the rejection of operationalism and kindred forms of “instrumentalism”. I believed (and in a sense Quine also believed) that fundamental physical theories are intended to tell the truth about physical reality, and not merely to imply true observation sentences.Footnote 60

At the very least, our conclusions can be seen as a way of setting the debate straight to its origin and showing that the minimal versions of IA are more closely related than others to Putnam’s argument.

If IA is meant as delivering only sufficient conditions for its conclusions, there is a clear sense in which it is being revisionary with respect to Quine’s original views. In a number of different passages Quine makes controversial claims about parts of mathematics (e.g. higher set theory) that have no applications in empirical sciences and are a fortiori not indispensable to scientific theories. Quine denies that the mathematical objects to which those parts of mathematics are committed to deserve any ontological rights (he famously spoke of ‘mathematical recreation’Footnote 61). This attitude has engendered quite a wide debate.Footnote 62 If indispensability (in versions of IA for platonism) is, as it were, the mark of existence for mathematical objects, then the objects of unapplied mathematics are banned from our ontology.

It is indeed possible to maintain a version of IA for which naturalism is necessary. This argument delivers the sort of platonism that Quine endorsed. But this argument is in tension with many forms of platonism, which would not distinguish among the ontological rights of different parts of mathematics, not at least on grounds of applicability and indispensability (Maddy has long insisted on this; see e.g. Maddy (2005)). It could even be argued that such an argument is not an argument for platonism (as standardly conceived), but rather for the proto-empirical (or ‘quasi-empirical’, to borrow from Putnam (1975b, p. 62)Footnote 63) character of mathematics.

Versions of IA giving only sufficient conditions leave open the possibility that we are justified in believing that unapplied mathematical theories are true or that the objects they are about exist, wholly independently of IA: IA is understood as an argument for mathematical (semantic or ontological) realism among others, not as the only argument.

If Quine suggests that a proper indispensability argument hinges on naturalism, then, it is only because he was a naturalist on independent grounds in the first place. Nothing in the argument mandates that this is so. That is just an example of the philosophical use of the argument (in a non-minimal version) that can be made in an empiricist framework. It is not a philosophical outcome that the argument can secure by itself.