Skip to main content

Reinterpreting Crucial Experiments

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Current Debates in Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 477))

  • 220 Accesses

Abstract

Crucial experiments have been largely neglected by philosophers of science. The main reason for this predicament is that Duhem’s criticism of that kind of experiment has been accepted as sound and definitive. In this article, I start by revisiting the main argument against the possibility of crucial experiments, which is based on epistemological holism. I contend that the argument rests on the confusion between crucial and decisive experiments. When crucial experiments are deprived of their supposed decisive character, the argument loses its bite. Epistemological holism applies to any experiment, whether crucial or not, but it does not imply that experiments are not possible or that they do not have any epistemological import. This variety of holism simply shows that any evidence has to be interpreted and assessed within a theoretical context that includes many auxiliary hypotheses and presupposed theories, which are regarded as accepted background knowledge. This knowledge is not put to the test in a given experiment, but it is rather employed in describing the experimental result and interpreting its theoretical consequences. The meaning of any crucial experiment has then to be extracted from the theoretical context in which the experimental result is interpreted. When the background of accepted knowledge undergoes a drastic change, a crucial experiment may be reinterpreted in such a way that confirms or refutes hypotheses or theories not available at the moment in which it was performed. I will illustrate this kind of reinterpretation with the historical cases of Fizeau’s 1851 experiment, the Michelson and Morley 1887 experiment, and Eddington’s 1919 experiment. I will conclude by vindicating crucial experiments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    A second augmented edition of the book was published in 1914 and reprinted in 1981. The book was translated into German in 1908 and, much later, into English in 1954. The section on crucial experiments was almost entirely that of the 1894 article. My quotations come from the 1981 reprinted edition.

  2. 2.

    For instance, Psillos (2007, p. 109) defines confirmational holism as “the view that theories are confirmed as wholes). In the foreword to the English translation of Duhem’s book, Louis de Broglie wrote that “according to Duhem, there are no genuine crucial experiments because it is the ensemble of a theory forming an indivisible whole which has to be compared to experiments” (de Broglie, 1954, p. XI).

  3. 3.

    See Gillies (1993), chapter 5, for a comparison between Duhem’s and Quine’s varieties of holism.

  4. 4.

    From now on, I will assume the classical conception of theories, according to which a theory is a logically closed set of propositions. All discussions of conformational holism are based on that account of theories, which was endorsed by Duhem and Quine themselves. Duhem and Quine also endorsed a deductivist conception of confirmation, according to which theories and hypotheses are tested exclusively by the evidence they imply. Formally, they subscribed to these two conditions: (a) E confirms HHE and (b) E refutes HH ⊨ not E (where H is a given hypothesis and E is any piece of evidence). These conceptions of theories and testing form the basis of the so-called hypothetico-deductive method. See Quine & Ullian (1978), chapter 8, for an explicit account of deductive confirmation.

  5. 5.

    See, for instance, Harding (1976) and the articles included in that work.

  6. 6.

    Standard dictionaries of those languages always mention the word “decisive” as synonymous with “crucial”, or as part of its definition.

  7. 7.

    I introduced this distinction in Cassini (2015), but I will elaborate on it in more detail here.

  8. 8.

    Kragh (1996) is a detailed study of this episode, which was presented here in a very simplified form. The original 1940s articles that predicted the existence of the cosmic microwave background are collected in Bernstein & Feinberg (1986).

  9. 9.

    Newton (1687, p. 224); Huygens (1690, p. 48). Newton’s and Huygens’ proofs rested on several auxiliary hypotheses concerning the existence of refractive forces and the microscopic structure of the ether, respectively.

  10. 10.

    Arago (1853) is the delayed publication of the experimental result. A discussion of the experiment can be found in Eisenstaedt (2005), chapter 10.

  11. 11.

    For a more detailed account of the experiment see Cassini & Levinas (2019).

  12. 12.

    Fizeau (1851) was a short qualitative report of his experiment. He later published his detailed calculations and his measured values in Fizeau (1859).

  13. 13.

    See Stachel (2005) for a brief account of the controversies.

  14. 14.

    Since 1910 Einstein regarded Fizeau’s experiment as a crucial experiment that confirmed his special theory of relativity (as well as Lorentz’s electrodynamics) and refuted the electrodynamical theories of Hertz and Ritz (besides Galilei mechanics). See an analysis of all the available sources in Cassini & Levinas (2019).

  15. 15.

    See Cassini & Levinas (2005) for a detailed account. See also the classic article by Holton (1969). Swenson (1972) is a comprehensive history of most ether-drift experiments. Michelson made a previous attempt in 1881, which was a failure because of a mistake in his calculations (see Michelson, 1881, 1882).

  16. 16.

    Given that the refractive index of the air is almost equal to the one of the void, in practice Fresnel’s coefficient could be set as null and, as a consequence, the ether could be regarded as being in relative motion with respect to the laboratory with the orbital speed of the Earth.

  17. 17.

    In 1950 Einstein himself told to Shankland (1963, p. 49) that he considered Tomaschek’s null results “really decisive in establishing the speed of light to be independent of the motion of the source”.

  18. 18.

    The details of the experiment are rather complicated and do not concern us here. See the comprehensive account by Kennefick (2019).

  19. 19.

    This point has been well argued by Crelinsten (2006). See also Kennefick (2019) for further reflections on the acceptance of the general theory of relativity.

References

  • Arago, F. (1810). Mémoire sur la vitesse de la lumière, lu à la prémière classe de l’Institut, le 10 décembre 1810. Compte Rendue des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences (Paris), 36(1853), 38–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arago, F. (1838). Sur un système d’experiences à l’aide duquel la théorie de l’émission et celle des ondes seront soumises à des épreuves décisives. Compte Rendue des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences (Paris), 23, 954–965.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, R. (1984). The Duhem thesis. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 35, 313–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, J., & Feinberg, G. (Eds.). (1986). Cosmological constants: Papers in modern cosmology. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassini, A. (2015). Una reivindicación de los experimentos cruciales. Revista de Filosofía, 40, 105–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassini, A., & Levinas, M. L. (2005). La reinterpretación radical del experimento de Michelson-Morley por la relatividad especial. Scientiae Studia, 3, 547–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassini, A., & Levinas, M. L. (2019). Einstein’s reinterpretation of the Fizeau experiment: How it turned out to be crucial for special relativity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 65, 55–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crelinsten, J. (2006). Einstein’s jury: The race to test relativity. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Broglie, L. (1954). Foreword. In Duhem (1954: V–XIII).

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1894). Quelques réflexions au sujet de la physique expérimentale. Revue des Questions Scientifiques, 36, 179–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1906). La théorie physique. Son objet et sa structure. Chevalier et Rivière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1914). La théorie physique, son objet-sa structure. Marcel Rivière & Cie. Deuxième édition, revue et augmentée. [Reprinted in Paris: Vrin, 1981].

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1954). The aim and structure of physical theory (Philip P. Wiener, Trans.). Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyson, F. W., Eddington, A. S., & Davidson, C. (1920). A Determination of the deflection of light by the Sun’s gravitational field, from observations made at the total eclipse of May 29, 1919. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series A, 220, 291–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1911). Über den Einfluß der Schwerkraft auf die Ausbreitung des Lichtes. Annalen der Physik, 35, 898–908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1916). Die Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie. Annalen der Physik, 49, 769–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenstaedt, J. (2005). Avant Einstein. Relativité, lumière, gravitation. Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (1999). The meaning of it all: Thoughts of a citizen-scientist. Perseus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fizeau, A. (1851). Sur les hypothèses relatives à l’éther lumineux, et sur une expérience qui paraît démontrer que le mouvement des corps change la vitesse avec laquelle la lumière se propage dans leur intérieur. Compte Rendue des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences (Paris), 33, 349–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fizeau, A. (1859). Sur les hypothèses relatives à l’éther lumineux. Et sur une expérience qui paraît démontrer que le mouvement des corps change la vitesse avec laquelle la lumière se propage dans leur intérieur. Annales de Chimie et de Physique. Troisième Série, 57, 385–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fizeau, A., & Breguet, L. (1850). Sur l’expérience relative à la vitesse comparative de la lumière dans l’air et dans l’eau. Compte Rendue des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences (Paris), 30, 771–774.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, L. (1850). Méthode générale pour mesurer la vitesse de la lumière dans l’air et les milieux transparents. Vitesses relatives de la lumière dans l’air et dans l’eau. Project d’expérience sur la vitesse de propagation du calorique rayonnant. Compte Rendue des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences (Paris), 30, 551–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, L. (1854). Sur les vitesses relatives de la lumière dans l’air et dans l’eau. Annales de Chimie et de Physique. Troisième Série, 41, 129–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fresnel, A. (1818). Lettre d’Augustin Fresnel à François Arago sur l’influence du mouvement terrestre dans quelques phénomènes d’optique. Annales de Chimie et de Physique, 9, 57–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1999). Science without laws. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (1993). Philosophy of science in the twentieth century: Four central themes. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. (Ed.). (1976). Can theories be refuted? Essays on the Duhem-Quine thesis. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton, G. (1969). Einstein, Michelson, and the “crucial” experiment. Isis, 60, 132–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huygens, C. (1690). Traité de la lumière. Pierre Vander Aa. [Reprinted in Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1920].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennefick, D. (2009). Testing relativity from the 1919 eclipse: A question of bias. Physics Today, 62, 37–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennefick, D. (2019). No shadow of a doubt: The 1919 eclipse that confirmed Einstein’s theory of relativity. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kragh, H. (1996). Cosmology and controversy: The historical development of two theories of the universe. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laue, M. (1907). Die Mitführung des Lichtes durch bewegte Körper nach dem Relativitätsprinzip. Annalen der Physik, 23, 989–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michelson, A. (1881). The relative motion of the earth and the luminiferous ether. American Journal of Science, 22, 120–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michelson, A. (1882). Sur le mouvement relatif de la Terre et de l’éther. Comptes Rendues de l’Académie des Sciences (Paris), 94, 520–523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michelson, A., & Morley, E. (1886). Influence of motion of the medium on the velocity of light. American Journal of Science, 3, 377–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michelson, A., & Morley, E. (1887). On the relative motion of the earth and the luminiferous ether. American Journal of Science, 34, 333–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1687). Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica. S. Pepys.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1902). La science et l’hypothèse. Flammarion. [Reprinted 1968].

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2007). Philosophy of science A-Z. Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1992). Pursuit of truth (Revised ed.). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shankland, R. (1963). Conversations with Albert Einstein. American Journal of Physics, 31, 47–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stachel, J. (2005). Fresnel’s (dragging) coefficient as a challenge to 19th century optics of moving bodies. In A. J. Knox & J. Eisenstaedt (Eds.), The universe of general relativity (pp. 1–13). Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, G. (1846). On the constitution of the luminiferous aether viewed with reference to the phenomenon of the aberration of light. Philosophical Magazine, 29, 6–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, G. (1848). On the constitution of the luminiferous aether. Philosophical Magazine, 32, 343–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, L. (1972). The ethereal aether: A history of the Michelson-Morley-Miller aether-drift experiments, 1880–1930. University of Texas Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomaschek, R. (1924). Über das Verhalten des Lichtes außerirdischer Lichtquellen. Annalen der Physik, 73, 105–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Soldner, J. (1801). Über die Ablenkung eines Lichtstrals von seiner geradlinigen Bewegung, durch die Attraktion eines Weltkörpers, an welchem er nahe vorbei geht. In Astronomische Jahrbuch Für das Jahr 1804 (pp. 161–172). G. A. Lange.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Cassini, A. (2023). Reinterpreting Crucial Experiments. In: Soto, C. (eds) Current Debates in Philosophy of Science. Synthese Library, vol 477. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-32375-1_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics