Skip to main content

Black Hole Coalescence: Observation and Model Validation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Working Toward Solutions in Fluid Dynamics and Astrophysics

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in History of Science and Technology ((BRIEFSHIST))

Abstract

This paper will discuss the recent LIGO-Virgo observations of gravitational waves and the binary black hole mergers that produce them. These observations rely on having prior knowledge of the dynamical behaviour of binary black hole systems, as governed by the Einstein Field Equations (EFEs). However, we currently lack any exact, analytic solutions to the EFEs describing such systems. In the absence of such solutions, a range of modelling approaches are used to mediate between the dynamical equations and the experimental data. Models based on post-Newtonian approximation, the effective one-body formalism, and numerical relativity simulations (and combinations of these) bridge the gap between theory and observations and make the LIGO-Virgo experiments possible. In particular, this paper will consider how such models are validated as accurate descriptions of real-world binary black hole mergers (and the resulting gravitational waves) in the face of an epistemic circularity problem: the validity of these models must be assumed to justify claims about gravitational wave sources, but this validity can only be established based on these same observations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Kennefick (2007, 46–47) for a very clear explanation of this point.

  2. 2.

    There are distinctions between solutions that are “exact”, “elementary”, “algebraic” etc., which I do not delve into here. For discussion of these issues, see Fillion and Bangu (2015).

  3. 3.

    For a detailed introduction to matched-filtering in gravitational-wave astrophysics, see (Maggiore 2008, Sect. 7.3).

  4. 4.

    This assumes that the eccentricity of the orbit can be neglected, since the emission of gravitational radiation is expected to circularise the orbit by the time the emitted gravitational waves enter the bandwidth of the detector (Peters 1964).

  5. 5.

    For a details, see Abbott et al. (2020, 36).

  6. 6.

    For details about LALInference analyses, see Veitch et al. (2015).

  7. 7.

    See, for example, Kennefick (2007, Chap. 8) and Havas (1989, 1993) for the history of this problem.

  8. 8.

    For a detailed discussion of the post-Newtonian approach, see Maggiore (2008, Chap. 5).

  9. 9.

    Since the nPN order refers to inclusions of terms \(\mathcal {O}(1/c^{2n})\), 4PN results include terms \(\mathcal {O}(1/c^{8})\).

  10. 10.

    Here, by convention, \(m_{1} > m_{2}\).

  11. 11.

    For detailed reviews of the history of numerical relativity simulations, see e.g., Holst et al. (2016) and Sperhake (2015).

  12. 12.

    I discuss reasons for this confidence in Sect. 5.3.3.

  13. 13.

    Here the compactness parameter is defined as as the ratio M/r where \( 0 < M/r \lesssim 1 \), and \(M = m_{1} + m_{2}\).

  14. 14.

    The mass ratio is defined as \( m_{2}/m_{1} \) where, by convention, \( m_{1} \) is always the larger mass and thus \( 0 < m_{2}/m_{1} \lesssim 1\).

  15. 15.

    In other work, including Elder (2020, in preparation), I provide an account of what is meant by these descriptors, drawing connections to recent work in the philosophy of measurement (e.g., Parker 2017; Tal 2012, 2013).

  16. 16.

    For the purposes of this paper, I will mainly focus on the models used for this initial detection. However, modelling these systems is an active area of research, with new iterations of these modelling approaches incorporating more physical effects.

  17. 17.

    My focus here is on binary black hole mergers, in part because I am focused on the case of GW150914 specifically, and in part because the case is arguably slightly different for binary neutron star mergers. I discuss how the epistemic situation is changed for “multi-messenger” sources like GW170817 in Elder (2020, Chap. 4 and in preparation).

  18. 18.

    O3 has recently reported one burst candidate, given the preliminary name “S200114f”, but this candidate has not yet been confirmed.

  19. 19.

    “BICEP” stands for “Background Imaging of Cosmic Extragalactic Polarization”. They initially reported the observation of signatures of primordial gravitational waves in 2014 but were forced to retract this claim, instead attributing the observation to cosmic dust (Collins 2017, 72).

  20. 20.

    Other notions of validity can be added here. For example, see Cronbach and Meehl (1955) for a discussion of the notion of “construct validity”.

  21. 21.

    For the purposes of this paper I will not explicitly discuss the IMRPhenom models. However, given that these hybrid models use the same ingredients as EOBNR models (PN, EOB, and NR), most if not all of what I say about EOBNR should also apply to IMRPhenom.

  22. 22.

    In general, convergence studies need not always involve increasing the resolution. For example, for Monte Carlo simulation convergence studies are performed for increasing sample sizes.

  23. 23.

    For more on these codes, see Duez and Zlochower (2018), especially section II, and the references therein).

  24. 24.

    The agreement across variations in the simulation methods forms the basis for a robustness argument: the simulation outputs are considered to be robust (and hence reliable) due to the agreement across independent methods. As with other robustness arguments, such reasoning relies on the methods being genuinely independent (see e.g., Staley (2004) and Dethier (2020)). Note that while robustness arguments of this kind have been considered controversial in the context of climate modelling, the present case appears to be one where robustness arguments are considered to be uncontroversial (if fallible). However, a comparative study of these cases is beyond the scope of this paper.

  25. 25.

    Of course, from the perspective of proponents of (relativistic extensions of) Modified Newtonian Dynamics (MOND), the empirical discrepancies that are usually attributed to dark matter in order to save general relativity are instead a motivation to modify general relativity. On this view, of course, general relativity has not stood up to all the empirical tests it has faced.

  26. 26.

    Nonetheless, insofar as the models are embedded in the experimental methodology, there is a sense in which this could be understood as a kind of experimenter’s regress, spelled out in terms of models rather than detectors. There are also clear similarities here to the related “simulationist’s regress” (Gelfert 2012; Meskhidze 2017).

  27. 27.

    See Bokulich (2020) for discussion of the distinction between consilience and coherence testing.

  28. 28.

    See also Patton (2020) for an excellent discussion of a different test, based on the parameterised post-Einsteinian framework developed by Yunes and Pretorius, including how this connects to the issue of “fundamental theoretical bias”.

  29. 29.

    For further discussion of theory testing in gravitational-wave astrophysics, see Elder (in preparation).

References

  • Abbott BP et al (2016a) Characterization of transient noise in advanced LIGO relevant to gravitational wave signal GW150914. Class Quantum Grav 33(13):134001. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/33/13/134001

  • Abbott BP et al (2016b) Observing Gravitational-Wave transient GW150914 with minimal assumptions. Phys Rev D 93(12):122004. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.93.122004

  • Abbott BP et al (2016c) Properties of the binary black hole merger GW150914. Phys Rev Lett 116(24):241102. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.116

  • Abbott BP et al. (2016d) Tests of general relativity with GW150914. Phys Rev Lett 116(22):221101. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.116.221101

  • Abbott BP et al (2020) A guide to LIGO-Virgo detector noise and extraction of transient gravitational-wave signals. Class Quantum Grav 37(5):055002. https://doi.org/10.1088/1361-6382/ab685e

  • Abedi J, Dykaar H, Afshordi N (2017) Echoes from the Abyss: tentative evidence for Planck-scale structure at black hole horizons. Phys Rev D 96(8):082004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker JG, Campanelli M, Pretorius F, Zlochower Y (2007) Comparisons of binary black hole merger waveforms. Class Quantum Grav 24(12):S25–S31. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/24/12/s03

  • Baker JG, Centrella J, Choi D-I, Koppitz M, van Meter J (2006) Gravitational-Wave extraction from an inspiraling configuration of merging black holes. Phys Rev Lett 96(11). https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.96.111102

  • Blanchet L, Damour T (1986) Radiative gravitational fields in general relativity I. General structure of the field outside the source. In: Philosophical transactions of the royal society of London. Series a, mathematical and physical sciences, vol 320(1555), pp 379–430

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchet L (1987) Radiative gravitation fields in general relativity II. Asymptotic behaviour at future null infinity. In: Proceedings of the royal society of London. Series a, mathematical and physical sciences, vol 409(1837), pp 383–399

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchet L (1998) On the multipole expansion of the gravitational field. Class Quantum Grav 15(7):1971–1999. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/15/7/013

  • Bokulich A (2020) Calibration, coherence, and consilience in radiometric measures of geologic time. Philos Sci 87(3):425–456

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buonanno A, Damour T (1999) Effective one-body approach to general relativistic two-body dynamics. Phys Rev D 59(8):084006. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.59.084006

  • Buonanno A, Damour T (2000) Transition from inspiral to plunge in binary black hole coalescences. Phys Rev D 62(6): 064015. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.62

  • Campanelli M, Lousto CO, Marronetti P, Zlochower Y (2006) Accurate evolutions of orbiting black-hole binaries without excision. Phys Rev Lett 96(11). https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.96.111101

  • Campbell D, Staley J (1966) Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for research. R. McNally, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins H (1985) Changing order: replication and induction in scientific practice. University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins H (2017) Gravity’s kiss: the detection of gravitational waves. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook TD (1979) Quasi-experimentation: design and analysis issues for field settings. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Cronbach L, Meehl P (1955) Construct validity in psychological tests. Psychol Bull (Washington, etc) 52

    Google Scholar 

  • Dethier C (2020) Multiple models, robustness, and the epistemology of climate science. Notre Dame, Indiana

    Google Scholar 

  • Duez MD, Zlochower Y (2018) Numerical relativity of compact binaries in the 21st century. Rep Prog Phys 82(1):016902. https://doi.org/10.1088/1361-6633/aadb16

  • Elder J (2020) The epistemology of gravitational-wave astrophysics. PhD diss, University of Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder J (in preparation) Independent evidence in multi-messenger astrophysics

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder J (in preparation) On the ‘Direct Detection’ of gravitational waves

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder J (in preparation) Theory testing in gravitational-wave astrophysics

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillion N, Bangu S (2015) Numerical methods, complexity, and epistemic hierarchies. Philos Sci 82(5):941–955

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin A (1994) How to avoid the experimenters’ regress. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part A 25(3):463–491. https://doi.org/10.1016/0039-3681(94)90062-0. Black Hole Coalescence: Observation and Model Validation 25

  • Franklin A (2015) The theory-ladenness of experiment. J Gen Philos Sci 46(1):155–166. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-015-9285-9

  • Gelfert A (2012) Scientific models, simulation, and the experimenter’sregress. In: Imbert C, Humphreys P (eds) Models, simulations, and representations. Routledge studies in the philosophy of science, vol 9, pp 145–167. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour C (1975) Relevant evidence. J Philos 72(14):403–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannam M, Husa S, Baker JG, Boyle M, Brügmann B, Chu T, Dorband N et al (2009) Samurai project: verifying the consistency of black-hole-binary waveforms for gravitational-wave detection. Phys Rev D 79 (8):084025. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.79.084025

  • Havas P (1989) The early history of the problem of motion in general relativity. In: Howard D, Stachel J (eds) Einstein and the history of general relativity: based on the proceedings of the 1986 Osgood Hill Conference, North Andover, MA, 8–11 May 1986. Einstein Studies, vol 1. Birkhäuser, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Havas P (1993) The two-body problem and the Einstein-Silberstein controversy. In: Earman J, Janssen M, Norton J (eds) The attraction of gravitation: new studies in the history of general relativity. Einstein studies, vol 5. Birkhäuser, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Holst M, Sarbach O, Tiglio M, Vallisneri M (2016) The emergence of gravitational wave science: 100 years of development of mathematical theory, detectors, numerical algorithms, and data analysis tools. Bull Am Math Soc 53:513–554. https://doi.org/10.1090/bull/1544

  • Kennefick D (2007) Travelling at the speed of thought. Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Tiec A (2014) The overlap of numerical relativity, perturbation theory and post-Newtonian theory in the binary black hole problem. Int J Mod Phys D 23(10):1430022. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0218271814300225

  • Lovelace G, Lousto CO, Healy J, Scheel MA, Garcia A, O’Shaughnessy R, Boyle M et al (2016) Modeling the source of GW150914 with targeted numerical-relativity simulations. Class Quantum Grav 33(24):244002. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/33/24/244002

  • Maggiore M (2008) Gravitational waves. Theory and experiments, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Meskhidze H (2017) Simulationist’s Regress in Laboratory Astrophysics

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M, Morrison M (1999) Models as mediating instruments. In: Morgan M, Morrison M (eds) Models as mediators: perspectives on natural and social science, pp 10–37. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker WS (2017) Computer simulation, measurement, and data assimilation. Br J Philos Sci 68(1):273–304. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv037

  • Pati ME, Will CM (2000) Post-Newtonian gravitational radiation and equations of motion via direct integration of the relaxed Einstein equations: foundations. Phys Rev D 62(12):124015. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.62.124015

  • Patton L (2020) Expanding theory testing in general relativity: LIGO and parametrized theories. In: Studies in history and philosophy of science. Part B: studies in history and philosophy of modern physics, vol 69, pp 142–153. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsb.2020.01.001

  • Peters PC (1964) Gravitational radiation and the motion of two point masses. Phys Rev 136(4B). https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRev.136.B1224

  • Pretorius F (2005) Evolution of binary black-hole spacetimes. Phys Rev Lett 95(12). https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.95.121101

  • Shapere D (1982) The concept of observation in science and philosophy. Philosop Sci 49(4). https://doi.org/10.1086/289075

  • Sperhake U (2015) The numerical relativity breakthrough for binary black holes. Class Quantum Grav 32(12):124011. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/32/12/124011

  • Staley KW (2004) Robust evidence and secure evidence claims. Philosop Sci 71(4):467–488. https://doi.org/10.1086/423748

  • Suppes P (1962) Models of data. In: Nagel E, Suppes P, Tarski A (eds) Logic, methodology and philosophy of science: proceedings of the 1960 international congress, pp 252–261. Stanford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Tal E (2012) The epistemology of measurement: a model-based account. http://search.proquest.com/docview/1346194511/

  • Tal E (2013) Old and new problems in philosophy of measurement. Philosop Compass 8(12):1159–1173. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12089

  • Veitch J et al (2015) Parameter estimation for compact binaries with groundbased gravitational-wave observations using the LAL inference software library. Phys Rev D 91(4):042003. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.91.042003

  • Will CM, Alan GW (1996) Gravitational radiation from compact binary systems: gravitational waveforms and energy loss to second post-newtonian order. Phys Rev D 54(8):4813–4848. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.54.4813

  • Winsberg E (2019) Computer simulations in science. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2019. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University

    Google Scholar 

  • Yunes N, Pretorius F (2009) Fundamental theoretical bias in gravitational wave astrophysics and the parametrized post-Einsteinian framework. Phys Rev D 80(12):122003. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.80.122003

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Don Howard, Nicholas Teh, Feraz Azhar, and Erik Curiel for their support and comments on an early version of this paper. I would similarly like to thank Dennis Lehmkuhl and the rest of the Lichtenberg Group at the University of Bonn—especially Juliusz Doboszewski, Niels Martens, and Christian Röken—for their helpful feedback on early drafts.

I would also like to thank audiences at SuperPAC, MS8, EPSA, the BHI and the (history and) philosophy of physics seminars at Bonn and Oxford for their questions and comments. Conversations with members of the LIGO Scientific Collaboration (especially Daniel Holz and Hsin-Yu Chen) at Seven Pines, BHI conferences, and a Sackler conference were also invaluable.

Special thanks are also due to Lydia Patton, a pioneer in the philosophy of gravitational-wave astrophysics, for ongoing support of my work in this area. And, of course, for thinking to connect this paper with the other excellent work in this volume.

This project/publication was funded in part by the Gordon and Betty Moore Foundation. It was also made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of these Foundations.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jamee Elder .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Elder, J. (2023). Black Hole Coalescence: Observation and Model Validation. In: Patton, L., Curiel, E. (eds) Working Toward Solutions in Fluid Dynamics and Astrophysics. SpringerBriefs in History of Science and Technology. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-25686-8_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics