Skip to main content

Two Dogmas of Enlightenment Scholarship

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Pluralizing Philosophy’s Past

Abstract

A central theme in the scholarly literature on Enlightenment Europe concerns the increased focus on the role of reason in the development of European thought, especially in the development of the new science by the natural philosophers. As a consequence, there is a tendency in both philosophical scholarship and teaching to bind philosophy and science tightly together. While there is certainly much that is correct in this approach, one motivation for pluralizing philosophy’s past is that this story leaves out a great deal that is important in Enlightenment views of reason. We argue, using as an example the work of figures like Margaret Cavendish, that reason was significantly broader in scope—and that developments in science were paralleled by equally important advances in music, art, literature, medicine, philosophy, and other areas. In recognizing the lack of a sharp boundary between these areas, an inclusive canon of Enlightenment philosophy gives us this richer notion of reason. Integrating figures such as Cavendish into the canon helps us to see that the narrow focus on the scientific version of reason within Enlightenment scholarship creates a false distinction between science and the humanities and misses out on the humanistic ends for which we engage in philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For contemporary challenges to this narrative, see O’Neill (2005) and Shapiro (2016).

  2. 2.

    See Phillips (2017).

  3. 3.

    While this seems to be a compelling passage in favor of RN, in Section 10.4 we offer a way to interpret this passage that cuts against RN.

  4. 4.

    It is worth noting that there are good philosophical, historical, and pedagogical reasons for this. For a thorough treatment of Descartes’ relation to late scholasticism, see Ariew (2014).

  5. 5.

    See Schliesser (2007) and Wright (2009, esp. Chapter 2).

  6. 6.

    For the clearest example, see the first three sections of Cavendish (2001).

  7. 7.

    See Cavendish (2001, 215). While this discussion seems to cut against the idea that Cavendish was an “empiricist,” one of the goals of incorporating figures like Cavendish into our study of early modern philosophy is to apply pressure to the rationalist/empiricist aspect of RN and show that the distinction is ultimately unstable and unhelpful.

  8. 8.

    See also Cavendish (2001, 53, 144, 149–154, 196–197, and 241–242).

  9. 9.

    See Cavendish (2001, 202, 214, and 226). Because the sensation happens locally, when we use the microscope, for example, what we are seeing is the lens, and the lens is “seeing” the object. What we actually perceive, then, is not the object itself magnified, but rather the lens’ version of the object, which is necessarily different from the object itself.

  10. 10.

    See Cavendish (2001, 50 and 140).

  11. 11.

    See Cavendish (2001, 218–219 and 221). This is especially true concerning the knowability of God (215).

  12. 12.

    See also Descartes’ suggestion to Elisabeth that one not engage in serious philosophy but for a few hours per year (Descartes 1991, 227).

  13. 13.

    For a similar reading of the therapeutic and socially transformative role of fancies and imagination in Cavendish, see Cunning (2016, 2018) and Sarasohn (2010).

  14. 14.

    This point is made clearly in Cunning (2016, 199). While there are, for Cavendish, decided differences between reason and fancy, those differences are not in the metaphysical makeup of these cognitive mechanisms. See also Sarasohn (2010, 77–79 and 172).

  15. 15.

    To this we might add that false accounts in philosophy and science often are pragmatically useful in our search for truth; we should thereby expect precisely the same outcome from the humanities.

  16. 16.

    Cf. Lloyd (1979). In Lloyd’s influential paper, she argues that the development of reason in the works of Enlightenment thinkers is a direct cause of the separation of reason from imagination and emotion in contemporary philosophy. Although we agree with Lloyd about the way in which RN has influenced contemporary philosophy, where we differ is in suggesting that the problem with the contemporary distinction lies with RN itself and not with the view of reason held by early modern thinkers.

  17. 17.

    See Cunning (2016), Marshall (2014), O’Neill (2005), and Cavendish (2001, Ed. Introduction).

  18. 18.

    See Cavendish (2001, xvi, 74, and 251).

  19. 19.

    Cavendish (2001, 52–53 and 234). The above passages are only a sample of the places where Cavendish is directly engaged with RN’s version of the philosophical canon.

  20. 20.

    Her Philosophical Letters is simply a direct correspondence with an imagined “Madam” concerning her philosophical contemporaries.

  21. 21.

    For example, Shapiro suggests that we should pursue the philosophy of education in the modern period (Shapiro 2016, 380).

References

  • Ariew, Roger. 2014. Descartes and the First Cartesians. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, Roger, and Eric Watkins. 2009. Modern Philosophy: an Anthology of Primary Sources. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bristow, William. 2010. “Enlightenment.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Last modified August 29, 2017. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/enlightenment/.

  • Cavendish, Margaret. 2001. In Observations upon Experimental Philosophy, ed. Eileen O’Neill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. The Description of a New World, Called the Blazing World. In Margaret Cavendish: Political Writings, ed. Susan James, 1–110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cottingham, John, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny, eds. 1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunning, David. 2016. Cavendish. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Cavendish on the Metaphysics of Imagination and the Dramatic Force of the Imaginary World. In Early Modern Women on Metaphysics, ed. Emily Thomas, 188–210. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, Rene. 1985a. Discourse on the Method. In The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Vol. I). Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch, 111–151. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985b. Principles of Philosophy. In The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Vol. I). Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch, 179–292. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Vol. III). Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, Genevieve. 1979. The Man of Reason. Metaphilosophy 10 (1): 18–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, Eugene. 2014. How to Teach Modern Philosophy. Teaching Philosophy 37 (1): 73–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martinich, A.P., Fritz Allhoff, and Anand Jayprakash Vaidya, eds. 2007. Early Modern Philosophy: Essential Readings with Commentary. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadler, Steven. 2014. History of Modern Philosophy: What is it Good For? Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association: 38–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, Eileen. 2005. Early Modern Women Philosophers and the History of Philosophy. Hypatia 20 (3): 185–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Kristopher G. 2017. Is Philosophy Impractical? Yes and No, but that’s Precisely Why We Need it. In Why the Humanities Matter Today: In Defense of Liberal Education, ed. Lee Trepanier, 37–64. Lanham: Lexington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarasohn, Lisa T. 2010. The Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish: Reason and Fancy during the Scientific Revolution. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, Eric. 2007. “Hume’s Newtonianism and Anti-Newtonianism.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2008/entries/hume-newton/.

  • Shapiro, Lisa. 2016. Revisiting the Early Modern Philosophical Canon. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2 (3): 365–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, John. 2009. Hume’s “A Treatise of Human Nature”: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Jones, S.A., Phillips, K.G. (2023). Two Dogmas of Enlightenment Scholarship. In: Griffioen, A.L., Backmann, M. (eds) Pluralizing Philosophy’s Past. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13405-0_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics