Skip to main content

The Elements of Sovereignty in Francisco de Vitoria’s Political Thought

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Empire, Humanism and Rights

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Law and Justice ((SHLJ,volume 21))

Abstract

This chapter outlines the concept of sovereignty in Francisco de Vitoria’s theological discourse. His thoughts on the matter emerge within the context of a growing imperial ethos spearheaded by both Emperor and Pope in their claims over the communities of the New World in the sixteenth century. As against the postulates set forth by both royal and ecclesiastical power, Vitoria’s lectures drew out a framework that served to establish the sovereign status of those communities on theological and juridical grounds. This brief overview addresses Vitoria’s line of reasoning in this respect and argues that his lectures on civil power, the laws of war and the Indies established an iusnaturalistic conception of sovereignty, which placed significant limits on empire and the use of force among states and communities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an overview of Reason of State in Spanish thought, see Fernández Santamaría (1980), pp. 355–379.

  2. 2.

    On the renovation of Catholic theology and the School of Salamanca, see Belda Plans (2000), Valenzuela-Vermehren (2013), pp. 99–125.

  3. 3.

    Dandelet (2014), p. 7.

  4. 4.

    Ibid., 8.

  5. 5.

    Pagden (1995), p. 11.

  6. 6.

    Dandelet (2014), p. 82.

  7. 7.

    Guicciardini (1857), p. 388, cited in Dandelet (2014), p. 74.

  8. 8.

    Haslam (2002), p. 31.

  9. 9.

    Ibid., 33.

  10. 10.

    Ibid., 40.

  11. 11.

    Ibid.

  12. 12.

    Ibid., 28.

  13. 13.

    Dandelet (2014), p. 86.

  14. 14.

    Lucena (1984), p. 163.

  15. 15.

    Ibid., 164. A compendium of Spanish-language texts on the ethical questions surrounding the Spanish conquest may be found in Pereña Vicente (1984).

  16. 16.

    Jackson (2007), p. 10.

  17. 17.

    Ibid., xi.

  18. 18.

    On this question, see, for example, Scott (1934).

  19. 19.

    Cited in Nys (1917), pp. 98–99.

  20. 20.

    For an interesting account of the Spanish writings and manuscripts centering on law and justice, see Folgado (1959), pp. 275–302.

  21. 21.

    Skinner (1980), p. 148.

  22. 22.

    Ibid.

  23. 23.

    Sánchez Agesta (1959), p. 15.

  24. 24.

    Brufau Prats (1957), p. 98.

  25. 25.

    Ibid., 112.

  26. 26.

    Ibid., 110.

  27. 27.

    See, for example, Aquinas’s discussion in his Summary of Theology (II-II, Q. 66, a.1).

  28. 28.

    Brett (1997), p. 129.

  29. 29.

    Naszalyi (1948), p. 78.

  30. 30.

    Brufau Prats (1957), p. 125.

  31. 31.

    Ibid.

  32. 32.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 7.

  33. 33.

    Barker (1951), p. xlix.

  34. 34.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), pp. 8–9.

  35. 35.

    Ibid., 9.

  36. 36.

    Sánchez Agesta (1959), p. 39.

  37. 37.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 18.

  38. 38.

    One alternative view may be found in Osiander (2001).

  39. 39.

    Sánchez Agesta (1959), p. 72.

  40. 40.

    Ibid.

  41. 41.

    Cited in ibid., 73.

  42. 42.

    Ibid., 73–74.

  43. 43.

    For a summary of this in Domingo de Soto, Martín de Azpilcueta, Gregorio López, Diego de Covarrubias, Juan Ginés de Sepúlveda, Fernando Vásquez de Menchaca, see ibid., 72–111.

  44. 44.

    Vitoria cited in Naszalyi (1948), pp. 134–1-35.

  45. 45.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 301.

  46. 46.

    Ibid., 107.

  47. 47.

    Ibid., 300.

  48. 48.

    Ibid., 94.

  49. 49.

    Pagden (1995), p. 94.

  50. 50.

    Naszalyi (1948), pp. 51–52.

  51. 51.

    Sánchez Agesta (1959), pp. 24–26.

  52. 52.

    A similar view is held by Fernández who emphasizes the “pyramidal” structure of the Vitorian system consisting, in this respect, of the individual and family, the state and society of mankind, all of which pertain to the ‘secular order’ of man. See Fernández Santamaría (1977), p. 100.

  53. 53.

    For a detailed examination of Vitoria’s line of reasoning, see Valenzuela-Vermehren (2013).

  54. 54.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 40.

  55. 55.

    Sepúlveda, J. G. d. (1544). Democrates Alter: Or, on the Just Causes for War against the Indians. http://www.columbia.edu/acis/ets/CCREAD/sepulved.htm. Accessed 27 March 2019.

  56. 56.

    Aquinas (ST I-II, 1-2).

  57. 57.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 249.

  58. 58.

    Ibid. It remains uncertain whether the English-language translation of “dominium est ius” as “dominion is a legal right” is entirely proper, if by this we are to deem the term “legal” as a positivist view of rights. The Spanish-language translation establishes, by contrast, that “el dominio es un derecho”, i.e. dominion is a right. On this, see Pereña (1967), p. 26. It is nonetheless clear that Vitoria is not referring to rights granted by positive law, but rather of rights and dominion as a natural attribute of rational creatures.

  59. 59.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 249.

  60. 60.

    Ibid., 251.

  61. 61.

    Ibid. In a passage preceding this one, Vitoria interestingly makes the following observation in respect of his own countrymen: “Thus if they [the Indians] seem too insensate and slow-witted, I put it down mainly to their [...] barbarous education. Even amongst ourselves we see many peasants who are little different from brute animals.” Ibid., 250.

  62. 62.

    Ibid., 251.

  63. 63.

    Ibid., 250.

  64. 64.

    Ibid., 250-51.

  65. 65.

    Urdánoz (1967).

  66. 66.

    Cited in Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 240.

  67. 67.

    Ibid.

  68. 68.

    Cited in Tuck (1999), p. 123.

  69. 69.

    Munro (1931), p. 330.

  70. 70.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 242.

  71. 71.

    Ibid.

  72. 72.

    Ibid., 243.

  73. 73.

    Carro (1947), p. 116.

  74. 74.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 243.

  75. 75.

    Indeed, Vitoria was pointing to the following passage in Aquinas’ Summary of Theology: “[…] we must observe that dominion and authority [in a political or legal sense, but not in its natural meaning] are institutions of human law, while the distinction between faithful and unbelievers arises from the Divine law. Now the Divine law which is the law of grace, does not do away with human law which is the law of natural reason. Wherefore the distinction between faithful and unbelievers, considered in itself, does not do away with dominion and authority of unbelievers over the faithful.”

  76. 76.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 244. The Spanish language version of De Indis includes an additional passage which holds “Furthermore, more grave than the sin of infidelity is hate of God; and nonetheless hate does not prevent one from being a true master; ergo, neither does infidelity.” The translation is mine. See Pereña (1967), p. 20.

  77. 77.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 244.

  78. 78.

    Urdánoz (1967), p. LXXXII.

  79. 79.

    Wight (1992), pp. 83–84.

  80. 80.

    Urdánoz (1967), p. LXXXIV.

  81. 81.

    Parry and Keith (1984), pp. 288–290.

  82. 82.

    Pagden and Lawrence (1991), p. 253.

  83. 83.

    Ibid., 254.

  84. 84.

    Ibid.

  85. 85.

    Ibid.

  86. 86.

    Ibid., 31–32.

  87. 87.

    Ibid., 254–255.

  88. 88.

    Ibid., 256.

  89. 89.

    Ibid., 258.

  90. 90.

    Ibid., 259.

  91. 91.

    Ibid., 259.

  92. 92.

    Ibid., 260.

  93. 93.

    Ibid., 261.

  94. 94.

    Ibid., 261–262.

  95. 95.

    Ibid., 261.

  96. 96.

    Truyol y Serra (1993), p. 24.

  97. 97.

    Brierly (1938), p. 75.

  98. 98.

    Hinsley (1966), p. 26. Cited in Jackson (2005), p. 75.

  99. 99.

    Jackson (2005).

  100. 100.

    Wight (1966), p. 103.

  101. 101.

    Bull (1984), p. 123.

References

  • Barker E (1951) Greek Political Theory: Plato and his Predecessors. London

    Google Scholar 

  • Belda Plans J (2000) La Escuela de Salamanca y la Renovación de la Teología en el Siglo, vol XVI. Biblioteca de Autores Cristianos, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Brett AS (1997) Liberty, right, and nature: individual rights in later scholastic thought. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brierly JL (1938) The law of nations. Oxford University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Brufau Prats J (1957) La Noción Analógica del Dominium en Santo Tomás, Francisco de Vitoria y Domingo de Soto. Salmanticensis 4:96–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bull H (1984) The emergence of a universal international society. In: Bull H, Watson A (eds) The expansion of international society. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 117–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Carro V (1947) Los Fundamentos Teológicos-jurídicos de las Doctrinas de Vitoria. Ciencia Tomista 223:95–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Dandelet TJ (2014) The Renaissance of Empire in Early Modern Europe. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández Santamaría JA (1977) The State, War and Peace: Spanish political thought in the Renaissance, 1516-1559. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández Santamaría JA (1980) Reason of State and Staecraft in Spain (1595-1640). J Hist Ideas 41(3):355–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Folgado A (1959) Los Tratados De Legibus y De Iustitia et Iure en los Autores Epañoles del Siglo XVI y Primera Mitad del XVII. La Ciudad de Dios CLXXII(3):275-302

    Google Scholar 

  • Guicciardini F (1857) Discorsi Politici: Opere Inedite di Francesco Guicciardini. Barbara, Bianchi e comp, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslam J (2002) No virtue like necessity: realist thought in international relations since Machiavelli. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinsley FH (1966) Sovereignty. New York, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson R (2005) Classical and modern thought on international relations: from Anarchy to Cosmopolis. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson R (2007) Sovereignty: evolution of an idea. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucena M (1984) Crisis de la Conciencia Nacional: Las Dudas de Carlos V. In: Pereña Vicente L (ed) La Ética en la Conquista de América: Francisco de Vitoria y la Escuela de Salamanca. Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Munro DC (1931) The Western attitude toward islam during the crusades. Speculum 6(3):329–343

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naszalyi E (1948) El Estado según Francisco de Vitoria. Ediciones Cultura Hispánica, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Nys E (ed) (1917) Francisci de Victoria: De Indis et De iure belli relectiones. Carnegie Institution of Washington, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Osiander A (2001) Sovereignty, international relations, and the Westphalian Myth. Int Organ 55(2):251–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagden AR (1995) Lords of all the worlds: ideologies of empire in Spain, Britain and France c. 1500-c. 1850. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagden AR, Lawrence J (eds) (1991) Francisco de Vitoria. Political writings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Parry JH, Keith RG (1984) New Iberian World: a documentary history of the discovery and settlement of Latin America to the Early 17th Century. Times Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereña L (ed) (1967) Francisco de Vitoria. Relectio de Indis o Libertad de los Indios. Consejo Suprerior de Investigaciones Científicas, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereña Vicente L (ed) (1984) La Ética en la Conquista de América: Francisco de Vitoria y la Escuela de Salamanca. Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez Agesta L (1959) El Concepto del Estado en el Pensamiento Español del Siglo XVI. Instituto de Estudios Políticos, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott JB (1934) The Spanish origin of international law. The Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepúlveda JGd (1544) Democrates Alter: Or, on the Just Causes for War against the Indians. http://www.columbia.edu/acis/ets/CCREAD/sepulved.htm. Accessed 27 Mar 2019

  • Skinner Q (1980) The foundations of modern political thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 1978

    Google Scholar 

  • Truyol y Serra A (1993) El Derecho de Gentes como Orden Universal. In: Mangas Martín A (ed) La Escuela de Salamanca y el Derecho Internacional en América: del Pasado al Futuro. Asociación Española de Profesores de Derecho Internacional y Relaciones Internacionales, Salamanca, pp 17–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuck R (1999) The rights of war and peace: political thought and international order from Grotius to Kant. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Urdánoz T (1967) Síntesis Teológico-Jurídica de la Doctrina de Vitoria. In: Pereña L (ed) Francisco de Vitoria. Relectio de Indis o Libertad de los Indios. Consejo Suprerior de Investigaciones Científicas, Madrid, pp 234–285

    Google Scholar 

  • Valenzuela-Vermehren L (2013) Vitoria, humanism and the School of Salamanca in Early Sixteenth Century Spain: a heuristic overview. Logos J Cathol Thought Cult 16(2):99–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wight M (1966) Western values in international relations. In: Butterfield H, Wight M (eds) Diplomatic investigations: essays in the theory of international politics. George Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wight M (1992) International theory: the three traditions. Holmes & Meyer for The Royal Institute of International Affairs, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luis Valenzuela-Vermehren .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Valenzuela-Vermehren, L. (2022). The Elements of Sovereignty in Francisco de Vitoria’s Political Thought. In: Beneyto, J.M. (eds) Empire, Humanism and Rights. Studies in the History of Law and Justice, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-82487-7_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-82487-7_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-82486-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-82487-7

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics