Skip to main content

Putting the Cart Before the Horse: Ernest Nagel and the Uncertainty Principle

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 53))

  • 348 Accesses

Abstract

In The Structure of Science, Ernest Nagel finds fault with Werner Heisenberg’s explication of the uncertainty principle. Nagel’s complaint is that this principle does not follow from the impossibility of measuring with precision both the position and the momentum of a particle, as Heisenberg intimates, rather it is the other way around. Recent developments in theoretical physics have shown that Nagel’s argument is more substantial than he could have envisaged. In particular it has become clear that there are in fact two uncertainty principles; as a result, there are four pairs of quantities to examine, whereas Heisenberg considers only one. These findings throw new light on Nagel’s criticism. They enable us to see that his intuition was surprisingly apposite, but also make clear where his argument misses the mark.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Of course the domain has to be specified, e.g. certain singular situations have to be excluded, but this is to be understood.

  2. 2.

    It is important not to confuse Nagel’s criticism with that of Niels Bohr. In 1927, both at the Volta conference in Como, Italy, and at the Solvay conference in Brussels, Bohr objected to Heisenberg’s claim that the uncertainty relations follow from the gamma ray thought experiment; according to Bohr, that thought experiment is defective (see Sect. 7.3). Bohr was right, but the objection is not the same as Nagel’s, which is that the uncertainty relations do not follow from uncontrollability.

  3. 3.

    The actual formula in Heisenberg’s seminal paper is p1q1 h, where p1 is “die Genauigkeit, mit der der Wert p bestimmbar ist” and q1 is “etwa der mittlere Fehler von q” (Heisenberg, 1927, p. 175).

  4. 4.

    Camilleri (2009, p. 93) has argued that for Heisenberg the matter is actually not epistemic but semantic: an accurate measurement of the position of an electron renders the concept of its momentum meaningless, rather than meaningful but unknowable. This distinction is interesting, but for our argument not relevant.

  5. 5.

    See Kennard (1927). Heisenberg was formally Privatdozent in Göttingen from 1924 to 1927; but from May 1926 to the end of 1927 he was actually employed in Copenhagen as lecturer and assistant to Niels Bohr.

  6. 6.

    Our translation from the German: “Dieses ist das etwas verallgemeinerte Unbestimmtheitsgesetz von Heisenberg. Es setzt eine untere Grenze für das Produkt der Unbestimmtheitsmaße für jedes Paar kanonischer Variabeln fest.” The inequality that Kennard is talking about is inequality (27) in his text.

  7. 7.

    Another example is the textbook by L.E. Ballentine (1990, p. 166), who first derives in a very elegant way what is actually the preparation uncertainty principle and then ascribes it to Heisenberg. On a personal note, one of us remembers from his time as student a feeling of unease when confronted first with one version and then with another as if they were equivalent. At the time he did not worry too much about the matter but now finds it rather satisfying to learn that his unease was justified after all.

  8. 8.

    This goes not only for an electron, but for all objects and processes in both the micro- and the macroworld.

  9. 9.

    Because of the structure of quantum mechanics, it is possible in special cases for the noise to be zero (a so-called noiseless measurement). According to Heisenberg’s 1927 version of the measurement uncertainty principle, this would mean that the disturbance in the momentum is infinite; but Ozawa’s correction gives merely a finite, and not necessarily large lower bound for this disturbance.

  10. 10.

    Hilgevoord and Uffink (2001/2016), and (1990). In a somewhat similar vein, Uffink and Hilgevoord (1985) earlier criticized the Kennard measure, explaining that for some exceptional probability distributions it gives too ample an estimate of the real spreading of position or momentum. One is more interested in where, say, 95% of the distribution is located than in what the least-squares measure would give. For normal, or near normal distributions with Gaussian tails, the criticism would be of little consequence; but one can think of other cases in which the Kennard measure would give a gross overestimate of the real uncertainty. This is not to say that the measure is wrong; rather for some abnormal distributions it is too crude.

References

  • Ballentine, L. E. (1990). Quantum mechanics. Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busch, P., Lahti, P., & Werner, R. F. (2013). Proof of Heisenberg’s error-disturbance relation. Physical Review Letters, 111, 160405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camilleri, K. (2009). Heisenberg and the interpretation of quantum mechanics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erhart, J., Sponar, S., Sulyok, G., Badurek, G., Ozawa, M., & Hasegawa, J. (2012). Experimental demonstration of a universally valid error-disturbance uncertainty relation in spin measurements. Nature Physics, 8, 185–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1927). Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik and Mechanik. Zeitschrift Für Physik, 43, 172–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1930). Die Physikalischen Prinzipien der Quantentheorie. Leipzig: Hirzel. English translation: The physical principles of quantum theory. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilgevoord, J., & Uffink, J. (1990). A new view on the uncertainty principle. In Miller, A. I. (Ed.), Sixty-two years of uncertainty. Historical, philosophical, and physical inquiries into the foundations of quantum mechanics, pp. 121–137. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilgevoord, J., & Uffink, J. (2001/2016). The uncertainty principle. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/qt-uncertainty/.

  • Kennard, E. H. (1927). Zur Quantenmechanik einfacher Bewegungstypen. Zeitschrift Für Physik, 44, 326–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Y., et al. (2019). Experimental test of error-tradeoff uncertainty relation using a continuous-variable entangled state. Quantum Information, 5, 68–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozawa, M. (2003). Universally valid reformulation of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle on noise and disturbance in measurement. The Physical Review, A67, 042105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozawa, M. (2019). Soundness and completeness of quantum root-mean-square errors. Quantum Information, 5, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiff, L. I. (1955). Quantum mechanics (2nd ed.). McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uffink, J., & Hilgevoord, J. (1985). Uncertainty principle and uncertainty relations. Foundations of Physics, 15, 925–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J. (1955). Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Matthias Neuber and Adam Tamas Tuboly for organizing the conference “Ernest Nagel and the Making of Philosophy of Science a Profession”, and the participants for posing interesting questions. We are also grateful to Jan Hilgevoord, John Norton, Jos Uffink and an anonymous referee for having commented on earlier versions of this paper. Hanoch Ben-Yami we thank for showing us the heights and depths of Budapest’s old and recent history.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeanne Peijnenburg .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendices

figure a
figure b

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Atkinson, D., Peijnenburg, J. (2022). Putting the Cart Before the Horse: Ernest Nagel and the Uncertainty Principle. In: Neuber, M., Tuboly, A.T. (eds) Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 53. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-81010-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics