Skip to main content

Is “Autonomy Talk” Misleading?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Thick (Concepts of) Autonomy

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 146))

Abstract

Especially during the last three decades, there has been a fine-grained debate on the notion of personal autonomy. This article will suggest taking one important distinction within this debate more seriously: the differentiation between (a) “personal autonomy” designating a family of ideal, gradual, and hence at least moderately perfectionist conceptions about what an autonomous person is and (b) what is called “autonomy as right” (Feinberg. 1986. 47). These are not different dimensions of one concept, but independent concepts with disparate, even conflicting normative functions and should be kept clearly separate from each other. Treating these two concepts merely as different aspects of one and the same notion of personal autonomy, as done by most authors, is severely misleading. For clarity, we will ultimately need different words for divergent concepts. It will be suggested that “autonomy as (moral or legal) right” should no longer be called “autonomy”, but forthrightly the “right to self-determination” or, in accordance with Thomas Hobbes, “authority”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The metaphor of space was always crucial for the notion of autonomy rights, see e.g. Feinberg 1986, 28, speaking of the “sovereign authority to govern oneself, which is absolute within one’s own moral boundaries (one’s ‘territory’, ‘realm’, ‘sphere’, or ‘domain’)”; Wellmann 1985, 95 (“dominion”) and Steiner 1994, 90 (“domain”). The metaphor goes back at least to von Savigny 1867, 6, who (in this regard following) Immanuel Kant’s notion of right) defines “the right in a subjective sense” as “a territory in which his will rules and rules with our consent”. It was taken up in consequentialist accounts of (quasi-) rights to self-determination, see Mill 1992, Ch. I, IV (“Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign”).

  2. 2.

    Autonomy as right does not have to be exclusively a negative right. It may also generate reasons for others to assist or to promote the autonomy competence of others as well, cf. Beauchamp , Childress 2013, 101 et seq., and Mackenzie 2008. See for the needs of vulnerable persons who are attempting to reconstruct a sense of practical identity required for their autonomy, Christman 2014.

  3. 3.

    Quante , in order to avoid a utopian ideal of autonomy that is unattainable for mortals, convincingly introduces a capacity for critical self-evaluation which contains a counterfactual: “a person has personal autonomy with respect to a first-order-attitude if she would be able to exercise the capacities necessary for personal autonomy if she noticed this first-order-attitude (or if someone asked her to critically reflect her first-order attitude).” Thus, permanent critical reflection and identification is not required for personal autonomy. Cf. Quante 2017, 119, 131, and also Christman’s (2009, 155) hypothetical reflection condition for the authenticity element of autonomy.

  4. 4.

    Although, strictly speaking, some aspects of such a notion of “relational autonomy” (cf. Mackenzie and Stoljar 2000a) are no longer a concept of autonomy at all, but of aspects of human flourishing that should be clearly distinguished from personal autonomy.

  5. 5.

    We can also skip the question here of whether “the ideal of personal autonomy […] requires not merely the presence of options, but of acceptable ones” (Raz 1986, 205) or “calls for positive freedom”, “de facto power”, and the social, political, and economically means to realize one’s choices (Oshana 2006a, 101 et seq.; id. 2006b, 2; id. 1998; Mackenzie and Stoljar 2000a; Mackenzie 2014, 25).

  6. 6.

    In a wider sense, personal autonomy in this sense is also one of the elements of well-being (cf. Mill 1992, Ch. III).

  7. 7.

    Cf. Darwall’s (1977) notion of “recognition respect”, which is neither context dependent nor a matter of degree.

  8. 8.

    It may be “at best only a partial ideal “(Feinberg 1986, 45), “an actually unattainable ideal” (Quante 2017, 130) and “an ideal deeply rooted in the liberal tradition” (Benn 1988, 10), but it is an ideal.

  9. 9.

    Of course, some authors in the debate about autonomyi see this point clearly , e.g. Christman 2015, Sub 1.1., and Beauchamp. 2005, 319 (We need “a way to ensure that ordinary choices qualify as autonomous even when persons have not reflected on their preferences at a higher level and even when they are hesitant to identify with one type of desire rather than another”).

  10. 10.

    It is only through such a low threshold concept of autonomy that the fundamentally egalitarian, as well as the inclusive character of the concept (or regime) of autonomy can be ensured. It is not until this is accomplished that it makes sense to think about autonomy-enabling policies in order to address Joel Anderson’s critique that the focus on low threshold conditions fails to protect less-competent groups in society because “the central fact about individual autonomy is how limited the competence of many individuals is and how vulnerable groups are significantly disadvantaged by arrangements in which benefits are distributed in part on the basis of the autonomy-competence that individuals develop ‘naturally’” (Anderson 2004).

  11. 11.

    The very idea of rights involves a commitment to equality, cf. Waldron 2007, 752.

  12. 12.

    “Having rights enables us to ‘stand up like men’, to look others in the eye, and to feel in some fundamental way the equal of anyone [...] To respect a person then, or to think of him as possessed of human dignity , simply is to think of him as a potential maker of claims”. Self-respect (together with self-trust and self-esteem) serves as a necessary element of several thicker conceptions of autonomyi as well, cf. Honneth and Anderson 2005, 132–138; Mackenzie 2008, 525.

  13. 13.

    Mackenzie sees that herself, in part, cf. Mackenzie 2008, 523 (“In the case of citizens’ rights to de jure political autonomy, the threshold level of competence required ought to be minimal. Agents who meet this minimal level of competence ought to be treated as politically autonomous and entitled to enjoy the rights and liberties that it guarantees, including freedom from the unwarranted paternalistic intervention of the state. To characterize an agent as personally autonomous, however, involves attributing to her capacities that go well beyond this minimal threshold”). Mackenzie’s whole argument, however, seems to imply that in moral (as opposed to legal) theory, persons who are not autonomous in a ‘thick’ sense should not have “the capacity, the right and the responsibility to exercise […] the authority to make decisions of practical importance to one’s life, for one’s own reasons, whatever those reasons might be” (512).

  14. 14.

    In some contexts, the stability of a decision might function as a place-holder for its voluntariness—something which is much less than authenticity.

  15. 15.

    Although this is highly questionable. “It is one thing to publically criticize modes of social practice that denigrate their participants, but it is another to define autonomy in a way to claim that those participants are not fully functioning agents at all” (Christman 2004, 158).

  16. 16.

    See Meyers 2004, 3–12, though.

  17. 17.

    The justified claim that respect for agents whose autonomy is impaired would, as a matter of social justice, entail positive obligations of social institutions to promote the autonomy of these citizens by fostering the social conditions for autonomy (Mackenzie 2008; Honneth and Anderson 2005) would not change anything regarding the two class-system of persons that is created until full justice or recognition in this sense is achieved. Mackenzie’s approach does not overcome the correlation of protection and incapacitation that is typical of substantive notions of personal autonomy.

  18. 18.

    In the final analysis the difference between the mildly perfectionist authenticity criterion e.g. Christman (2004, 2009) suggests on the one hand, and the strong perfectionist view of human values (i.e, the view that values and moral principles can be valid for a person independent of her judgment of those values and principles) that is imported into the account of autonomy by some relational concepts of autonomy on the other hand (see Christman 2004, 146) is also not crucial in this regard. Both conceptions see autonomy as a matter of degree and do not clearly take into account the normative structure of rights that defines the concept of autonomyr as an ontic status.

  19. 19.

    “[T]he right of doing any action is called authority , Hobbes 1651, Ch. XVI.

References

  • Anderson, Joel. 2004. Regimes of Autonomy. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17: 355–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, Tom L. 2005. Who Deserves Autonomy, and Whose Autonomy Deserves Respect? In Personal Autonomy: New Essays on Personal Autonomy and Its Role in Contemporary Moal Philosophy, ed. James Stacey Taylor, 310–329. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2013. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benn, Stanley L. 1976. Freedom, Autonomy, and the Concept of a Person. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86: 109–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. A Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berofsky, Bernard. 1995. Liberation from Self: A Theory of Personal Autonomy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael E. 1987. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Planning Agency, Autonomous Agency. In Structures of Agency: Essays, id, 195–221. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2004. Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism and the Social Constitution of Selves. Philosophical Studies 117: 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-historical Selves. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Relational Autonomy and the Social Dynamics of Paternalism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17: 369–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015, Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/autonomy-moral/. Accessed 4 Apr 2020.

  • Darwall, Stephen. 1977. Two Kinds of Respect. Ethics 88: 36–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Gerald. 1988. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1983. Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1970. The Nature and Value of Rights. The Journal of Value Inquiry 4: 243–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Harm to Self The Moral Limits of The Criminal Law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1972a. Das Ich und das Es. [1923]. In Studienausgabe Band III, 273–330. Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1972b. Neue Folge der Vorlesungen zur Einführung in die Psychoanalyse [1932]. In Studienausgabe Band I, 448–608. Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A. 1982. Legal Rights. In Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory, 162–193. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1651. Leviathan or The Matter, Forme and Power of a Common Wealth Ecclesiasticall and Civil. London: Andrew Crooke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1996. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflict. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel, and Joel Anderson. 2005. Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition and Justice. In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays, ed. John Christman and Joel Anderson, 127–149. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, Frances M. 2004. Rights. In The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, ed. Jules L. Coleman and Scott J. Shapiro, 476–513. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona. 2000. Imagining Oneself Otherwise. In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, ed. Natalie Stoljar, 124–150. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism. Journal of Social Philosophy 39: 512–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Three Dimensions of Autonomy: A Relational Analysis. In Autonomy, Oppression and Gender, ed. Andrea Veltman and Mark Piper, 15–41. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar. 2000a. Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000b. Introduction: Autonomy Refigured. In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, 3–31. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyers, Diana Tietjens. 1989. Self, Society and Personal Choice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Intersectional Identity and the Authentic Self: Opposites Attract! In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, ed. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, 151–180. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization. In Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action and Social Life, ed. Diana Tietjens Meyers, 3–11. Lanham/Boulder: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1992. On Liberty [1859]. In On Liberty and Utilitarianism, with an introduction by Isaiah Berlin. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oshana, Marina. 1998. Personal Autonomy and Society. Journal of Social Philosophy 29: 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006a. How Much Should We Value Autonomy. Social Philosophy and Policy 20: 99–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. Personal Autonomy in Society. Hampshire: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quante, Michael. 2007. Autonomy for Real People. In Intentionality, Deliberation and Autonomy: The Action-Theoretic Basis of Practical Philosophy, ed. Christoph Lumer and Sandro Nannini, 209–226. Aldershot: Asgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. In Defence of Personal Autonomy. Journal of Medical Ethics 37: 597–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Personal Identity as a Principle of Biomedical Ethics. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good. Philosophy and Public Affairs 17: 251–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, Hillel. 1994. An Essay on Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, Natalie. 2000. Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition. In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self, ed. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar, 94–111. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, Leonard W. 2000. Rights. In The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, ed. Hugh LaFollette, 354–373. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985a. Self-interpreting Animals. In Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1, 45–76. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985b. What’s wrong with negative liberty. In Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2, 211–229. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1990. The Realm of Rights. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • VanDeVeer, Donald. 1986. Paternalistic Interventions: The Moral Bounds on Benevolence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Savigny, Friedrich Carl. 1867. System of the Modern Roman Law, Vol 1

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 1981. A Right to Do Wrong. Ethics 92: 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Rights. In A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, ed. Robert E. Goodi, Philip Pettit, and Thomas W. Pogge, 745–754. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellmann, Carl. 1985. A Theory of Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, Alan. 1987. Coercion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wikler, Daniel. 1983. Paternalism and the Mildly Retarded. In Paternalism, ed. Rolf Sartorius, 83–94. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1981. Persons, Character and Morality. In Moral Luck, 1–19. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Gutmann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gutmann, T. (2022). Is “Autonomy Talk” Misleading?. In: Childress, J.F., Quante, M. (eds) Thick (Concepts of) Autonomy. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 146. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-80991-1_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics