Skip to main content

Limited Review in Balancing Constitutional Rights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Proportionality, Balancing, and Rights

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 136))

Abstract

In liberal democracies constitutional courts or ‘Supreme Courts’ are typically empowered to undertake constitutional review of parliamentary statutes. This often involves balancing constitutional rights against other constitutional rights and/or collective goods. To be sure, the court empowered to undertake constitutional review has to pay deference towards balancing decisions taken by the democratically legitimated parliament, which are reflected in the statute. The argument from democracy does not render parliamentary statutes completely immune to review, it justifies, however, a limitation of review. ‘Limited review’ represents a compromise between ‘strict review’ and ‘no review at all’. This chapter illustrates prominent instances of such limited review and explores its characteristics as a legal phenomenon. Limited review will then be reconstructed in the weight formula as brought about by means of a formal principle. The insights into the structure and the properties of this formal principle will yield a more comprehensive and thorough understanding of the constitutional courts’ deference towards parliamentary statutes or the ‘margin of appreciation’ that the Member States of the ECHR enjoy before the European Court of Human Rights—to mention only two prominent instances of limited review.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    On proportionality in the assessment of rights claims, see generally Alexy (2002a), pp. 66–69. On the proliferation of proportionality see Beatty (2004); Stone Sweet and Matthews (2008), pp. 112–160; Barak (2012), pp. 181–210; Bernal Pulido (2013). On the German origins of proportionality, see, for example, Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), pp. 271–275; Arai-Takahashi (2013), p. 447.

  2. 2.

    See, for example, Greer (2004); Crawford (2012), p. 665; Peters (2012) marginal number 106; Arai-Takahashi (2013), pp. 448–464; Harris et al. (2014), pp. 13–14; Newton and May (2014); Kolb (2016), pp. 401–412.

  3. 3.

    See, for example, Craig and de Burca (2015), pp. 551–558; Weatherill (2016), pp. 48–54; see also Peers and Prechal (2014), marginal numbers 52.65 to 52.86.

  4. 4.

    See, for example, Alexy (2002a), pp. 66–69; Craig and de Burca (2015), p. 526; Cohen-Eliya and Porat (2010), p. 267.

  5. 5.

    See, for example, Alexy (2002a), pp. 67–68.

  6. 6.

    There are cases in which balancing leads to a stalemate—one cannot say either that the interference with the right outweighs the promotion of the end pursued by public authority or vice versa. On such cases, see Alexy (2002b), pp. 408–414. The question of which side enjoys the benefit of the doubt is a normative rather than a structural issue.

  7. 7.

    Borowski (2018), pp. 191, 336 et passim.

  8. 8.

    On the ‘margin of appreciation’, see Sect. 1.3.

  9. 9.

    See, for example, Alexy (2002b), p. 416; Alexy (2014), p. 516. See also Rivers (2006), p. 204, referring to Law L.J.: ‘greater deference should be paid to Parliament than to subordinate legislative or executive acts’.

  10. 10.

    This deference assuages the concern that constitutional review of parliamentary statutes by means of proportionality deprives the democratic process of the central role it deserves. On this concern, see, in particular, Böckenförde (2017), p. 258.

  11. 11.

    BVerfGE 50, 290 (333).

  12. 12.

    Dworkin (1977), p. 38.

  13. 13.

    See, for example, Nettesheim (2005), p. 1091.

  14. 14.

    Nettesheim (2005), pp. 1093–1094. See also Bauer (2015), marginal number 13 with further references.

  15. 15.

    See, for example, Brenner (2018), marginal number 29 with further references.

  16. 16.

    The phrase ‘ordinary courts’ (Fachgerichte) refers to all courts of the five jurisdictions just mentioned in the text, as opposed to the GFCC and the sixteen constitutional courts of the German states (Länder).

  17. 17.

    ‘The following basic rights shall bind the legislature, the executive and the judiciary as directly applicable law.’

  18. 18.

    See, for example, BVerfGE 18, 85 (93); 102, 347 (362); 111, 366 (373).

  19. 19.

    Named after the seminal decision of the GFCC, BVerfGE 6, 32 – Elfes, in which the fundamental structure of assessing claims stemming from liberty rights was introduced.

  20. 20.

    This is a generally accepted conclusion, see only Schlaich and Korioth (2018), marginal number 284; see also Hillgruber and Goos (2015), p. 81.

  21. 21.

    Alexy (2002a), pp. 210–217; Borowski (2018), pp. 327–333.

  22. 22.

    See, for example, Schlaich and Korioth (2018), marginal number 285, with further references. See also BVerfGE 22, 93 (98); 51, 130 (139); 96, 27 (40).

  23. 23.

    These phrases were introduced in BVerfGE 7, 198 (207) and have been repeated in numerous decisions ever since.

  24. 24.

    See Schlaich and Korioth (2018), marginal numbers 301-304 with further references.

  25. 25.

    See, for example, BVerfGE 43, 130 (138); 59, 231 (270-271); 71, 162 (178-179); 77, 346 (359); 95, 28 (37); 97, 391 (406).

  26. 26.

    See Sect. 2.1.

  27. 27.

    See, for example, Schlaich and Korioth (2018), marginal numbers 295-297 with further references.

  28. 28.

    See the references in Schlaich and Korioth (2018), marginal numbers 307-309.

  29. 29.

    BVerfGE 50, 290 (333).

  30. 30.

    Borowski (2016), p. 127.

  31. 31.

    See, for example, European Court of Human Rights (2006), marginal number 140.

  32. 32.

    Article 1 of this Protocol reads: ‘At the end of the preamble to the Convention, a new recital shall be added, which shall read as follows: “Affirming that the High Contracting Parties, in accordance with the principle of subsidiarity, have the primary responsibility to secure the rights and freedoms defined in this Convention and the Protocols thereto, and that in doing so they enjoy a margin of appreciation, subject to the supervisory jurisdiction of the European Court of Human Rights established by this Convention”. This Protocol will enter into force once all 47 Member States will have ratified. Currently 46 member states have ratified, except Italy.

  33. 33.

    European Court of Human Rights (1976), marginal number 48.

  34. 34.

    Jurisconsult of the ECHR (2010,) marginal number 45.

  35. 35.

    See Schabas (2015), pp. 81–82 with further references.

  36. 36.

    Jurisconsult of the ECHR (2010), marginal number 9. In the same direction, for example, European Court of Human Rights (2012b), marginal number 58: ‘[W]here a particularly important facet of an individual’s existence or identity is at stake, the margin allowed to the State is correspondingly narrowed’.

  37. 37.

    Jurisconsult of the ECHR (2010), marginal numbers 27-39 with further references.

  38. 38.

    See note 33 and the accompanying text.

  39. 39.

    Borowski (2018), pp. 166–167.

  40. 40.

    It has proven impossible to establish a hierarchy, let alone a strict hierarchy, between and among the different canons of interpretation. This and the practice of legal interpretation suggests that the canons exhibit the dimension of weight and can be balanced against each other in subsumption judgments, see Borowski (1998), p. 315; Borowski (2009), 103; Borowski (2018), pp. 166–167, footnote 389; see also Sieckmann (2009), pp. 164–166.

  41. 41.

    Borowski (2013a), pp. 192–193; Borowski (2017), pp. 452, 461.

  42. 42.

    European Court of Human Rights (2012a), marginal number 88.

  43. 43.

    See Borowski (2014), p. 779.

  44. 44.

    See Sect. 1.1.1.

  45. 45.

    Of course, one can also distinguish more than three levels of intensity of review. The number of levels depends on how many levels of intensity of review can be meaningfully distinguished in the relevant context.

  46. 46.

    Alexy (2002b), p. 419; Alexy (2007), p. 25.

  47. 47.

    Alexy (2002b), p. 422.

  48. 48.

    Epistemic uncertainty is a necessary condition of limited review and the degree of uncertainty is key for the extent of the limitation of review, see Sect. 4.

  49. 49.

    Alexy (2002a), p. 54.

  50. 50.

    A legal system that contains principles necessarily contains rules dependent on balancing principles. This is not to say that it necessarily contains any rule independent from balancing principles. What is more, the rule that is created according to the law of competing principles has definitive legal validity only in the respective legal system, (1) if all relevant principles in this legal system are considered in the balancing, and (2) if all relevant factual circumstances (which are expressed by ‘C’ in the law of collision) are considered. Only under these circumstances the rule established in the balancing is fully concretized. If not all relevant principles or not all relevant facts are taken into consideration, a merely partially concretized norm is created.

  51. 51.

    Alexy (2002b), p. 418: ‘The more heavily an interference in a constitutional right weighs, the greater must be the certainty of its underlying premisses’. See also Alexy (2007), p. 25.

  52. 52.

    Borowski (2018), p. 127: ‘materielles Abwägungsgesetz’.

  53. 53.

    Alexy (2002a), p. 102.

  54. 54.

    Alexy (2002b).

  55. 55.

    Alexy (1985).

  56. 56.

    Alexy (2002c).

  57. 57.

    Alexy (2003a). Translation into English: Alexy (2007).

  58. 58.

    Alexy (2003b).

  59. 59.

    Alexy (2007), p. 25; Alexy (2003b), p. 446. See, for the same formula in the long notation, Alexy (2007), 25, footnote 37.

  60. 60.

    On this modification in the corresponding German version of the weight formula, see Borowski (2013a), p. 168.

  61. 61.

    Alexy (2002b), pp. 396–414; Alexy (2016), p. 15. See Sect. 3.2.7.1.

  62. 62.

    See Alexy (2003b), p. 446. See also Alexy (2007), p. 23: ‘extended version of the weight formula’—not to be confused with the ‘Extended Weight Formula’ on p. 27, see Sect. 3.2.5.

  63. 63.

    While Alexy was initially hesitant to extend ‘R’ to the reliability of the normative premisses (see Alexy [2002b], p. 419, footnote 97), he later endorsed this explicitly (Alexy 2012, p. 331); Alexy (2014), p. 514.

  64. 64.

    For an explanation of ‘classification propositions’, see Sect. 3.2.6.

  65. 65.

    In the context of balancing individual rights and collective goods, this is a plausible reading. There are other contexts in law, in which it might be useful or required, however, to set a threshold value for reliability in the sense of an all-or-nothing fashion, see Borowski (2013a), pp. 172–173.

  66. 66.

    See, in particular, Borowski (2013b), pp. 410–412; Borowski (2018), pp. 354–356; see also Alexy (2015), p. 511.

  67. 67.

    See Alexy (2002b), pp. 405–414; Alexy (2002c), p. 21; Alexy (2003b), 440–443; Alexy (2007), pp. 14–20.

  68. 68.

    On the double-triadic scale, see Alexy (2002b), pp. 412–413; Alexy (2007), pp. 22–23.

  69. 69.

    Borowski (2013a), pp. 176–177.

  70. 70.

    Alexy (2002b), p. 419, footnote 97; Alexy (2007), p. 25. That would be for the double triadic scale 2-0, 2-1, 2-2, 2-3, 2-4, 2-5, 2-6, 2-7, 2-8.

  71. 71.

    Alexy (2007), p. 27.

  72. 72.

    Ibid.

  73. 73.

    See, on the distinction between internal and external justification, Wróblewski (1971), pp. 411–412; Wróblewski (1974), p. 39. See furthermore Alexy (1989), pp. 221–231; MacCormick (1978), p. 101; Moreso (1996), p. 73 et seq.

  74. 74.

    See, in particular, Dworkin (1977), pp. 22–45.

  75. 75.

    See, in particular, Dworkin (1985), p. 119 et seq.

  76. 76.

    Alexy (2002b), pp. 396–414; Alexy (2007), p. 19. This phrase is rather pale, for also the other forms of structural discretion and even epistemic discretion emerge ‘in balancing’.

  77. 77.

    On this distinction, see Alexy (2002a), pp. 80–82; Borowski (2018), p. 165, with further references.

  78. 78.

    For an alternative reconstruction, see Borowski (2010), pp. 31–32.

  79. 79.

    See Alexy (2002a), pp. 308–314; Alexy (2009), p. 5; Borowski (2018), pp. 254–281.

  80. 80.

    Alexy (2002c), p. 17; Alexy (2009), p. 16; Borowski (2018), pp. 177 and 277–281.

  81. 81.

    So far, I completely agree with Robert Alexy: ‘[F]ormal principles play no role with respect to substantial discretion’, Alexy (2014), p. 519—he uses ‘substantial discretion’ as a synonym for ‘structural discretion’, ibid.

  82. 82.

    See Sect. 3.2.5. This formal principle is considered only in the ‘review decision’, not in the ‘decision to be reviewed’.

  83. 83.

    The formal principle is the ‘third principle’ in cases in which two substantive principles compete. If there is a competition between and among three substantive principles for the ‘balancing decision to be reviewed’, the formal principle is the ‘fourth principle’, and so on.

  84. 84.

    See, in particular, the analysis in Borowski (2013a), pp. 165–181.

  85. 85.

    On this ‘model of competing formal principles’ (Modell der konkurrierenden Rechtskonzeptionen) see Sieckmann (1990), pp. 162–164; Sieckmann (2002), pp. 398–403; Sieckmann (2009), pp. 200–204; Sieckmann (2018), pp. 200–211.

  86. 86.

    Sieckmann (2009), p. 204; Sieckmann (2018), pp. 210–211.

  87. 87.

    Alexy (2014), p. 520 et passim.

  88. 88.

    See Borowski (2018), p. 183, footnote 482.

  89. 89.

    Borowski (2013a), p. 180.

  90. 90.

    Alexy (2014), pp. 520–521.

  91. 91.

    Alexy (2002b), p. 419. See also Alexy (2007), p. 25; Alexy (2003b), pp. 447–448.

  92. 92.

    See, supra, Sect. 3.2.2.

  93. 93.

    Borowski (2013a), pp. 175–177, Borowski (2017), pp. 459–460.

  94. 94.

    Alexy (2014), p. 523.

  95. 95.

    See Sect. 3.2.7.1.

  96. 96.

    Alexy (2014), p. 519.

  97. 97.

    See above, Sect. 3.2.7.1.

  98. 98.

    See, in particular, Borowski (2013a), pp. 195–199.

  99. 99.

    Borowski (2013a), pp. 197–198; Borowski (2017), p. 461. In this direction also Alexy (2002b), p. 424: ‘The moment uncertainty disappears they [formal principles] go out of action’. See also Alexy (2012), p. 331.

References

  • Alexy R (1985) Theorie der Grundrechte. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1989) A theory of legal argumentation (trans: MacCormick ND). Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2002a) A theory of constitutional rights (trans: Rivers J). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2002b) Postscript. In: Alexy R (ed) A theory of constitutional rights (trans: Rivers J). Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 388–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2002c) Verfassungsrecht und einfaches Recht – Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit und Fachgerichtsbarkeit. Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 61:7–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003a) Die Gewichtsformel. In: Jickeli J, Kreutz P, Reuter D (eds) Gedächtnisschrift für Jürgen Sonnenschein. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 771–792. Translation into English: Alexy R, The weight formula (Alexy R 2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003b) On balancing and subsumption. A structural comparison. Ratio Juris 16:433–449

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2007) The weight formula (trans: Brożek B, Paulson S L). In: Stelmach J, Brożek B, Zaluski W (eds) Frontiers of economic analysis of law – studies in the philosophy of law, vol 3. Jagellonian University Press, Cracow, pp 9–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2009) On constitutional rights to protection. Legisprudence 3:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2012) Comments and responses. In: Klatt M (ed) Institutionalized reason. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 319–356

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2014) Formal principles: some replies to critics. Int J Const Law 12:511–524

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2015) Menschenwürde und Verhältnismäßigkeit. Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 140:497–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2016) The absolute and the relative dimension of constitutional rights. Oxf J Legal Stud 36:1–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Arai-Takahashi Y (2013) Proportionality. In: Shelton D (ed) Oxford handbook of international human rights law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 446–468

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2012) Proportionality, constitutional rights, and their limitations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bauer H (2015) Artikel 82. In: Dreier H (ed) Grundgesetz Kommentar, vol 2, 3rd edn. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 2128–2149

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty DM (2004) The ultimate rule of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernal Pulido C (2013) The migration of proportionality across Europe. New Zealand J Public Int Law 11:483–515

    Google Scholar 

  • Böckenförde E-W (2017) Fundamental rights as constitutional principles (trans: Dunlap T, Zimmerling R). In: Künkler M, Stein T (eds) Böckenförde, E-W Constitutional and political theory, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 235–265

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (1998) Prinzipien als Grundrechtsnormen. Zeitschrift für Öffentliches Recht 53:307–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2009) Die Bindung an Festsetzungen des Gesetzgebers in der grundrechtlichen Abwägung. In: Clérico L, Sieckmann J-R (eds) Grundrechte, Prinzipien und Argumentation. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 99–128

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2010) The structure of formal principles. Robert Alexy’s ‘law of combination’. In: Borowski M (ed) On the nature of legal principles. Steiner, Stuttgart, pp 19–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2013a) Formelle Prinzipien und Gewichtsformel. In: Klatt M (ed) Prinzipientheorie und Theorie der Abwägung. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 151–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2013b) Absolute rights and proportionality. German Yearb Int Law 56:385–423

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2014) Subjekte der Verfassungsinterpretation. In: Isensee J, Kirchhof P (eds) Handbuch des Staatsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, vol 12, 3rd edn. C.F. Müller, Heidelberg, pp 761–782

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2016) Die verfassungsgerichtliche Rechtfertigung des Grundrechtseingriffs – Teil II. Studentische Zeitschrift für Rechtswissenschaft Heidelberg:115–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2017) Alexys drittes Modell formeller Prinzipien. In: Borowski M, Sieckmann J-R, Paulson SL (eds) Rechtsphilosophie und Grundrechtstheorie – Robert Alexys System. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 449–476

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2018) Grundrechte als Prinzipien, 3rd edn. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner M (2018) Artikel 82. In: von Mangoldt H, Klein F, Starck C (eds) Grundgesetz Kommentar, vol 2, 7th edn. CH Beck, Munich, pp 2401–2422

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Eliya M, Porat I (2010) American balancing and german proportionality: the historical origins. Int J Const Law 8:263–286

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig P, de Burca G (2015) EU Law, 6th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford J (2012) Brownlie’s principles of public international law, 8th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1977) Taking rights seriously. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1985) A matter of principle. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • European Court of Human Rights (1976) Plenary, 7 December 1976, Handyside v. United Kingdom, Appl. No. 5493/72

    Google Scholar 

  • European Court of Human Rights (2006) Judgment of the Grand Chamber, 26 March 2006, Scordino v. Italy I, Appl. No. 36813/97, ECHR 2006-V

    Google Scholar 

  • European Court of Human Rights (2012a) Judgment of the Grand Chamber, 7 February 2012, Axel Springer AG v. Germany, Appl. No. 39954

    Google Scholar 

  • European Court of Human Rights (2012b) Jugdment of the Fifth Section, 21 June 2012, E.S. v. Sweden, Appl. No. 5786/08

    Google Scholar 

  • Greer S (2004) Balancing and the European Court of Human Rights: a contribution to the Habermas-Alexy debate. Camb Law J 63:412–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris D, O’Boyle M, Bates E, Buckley C (2014) Law of the European Convention on Human Rights, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillgruber C, Goos C (2015) Verfassungsprozessrecht, 4th edn. CF Müller, Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • Jurisconsult of the ECHR (2010) Interlaken follow-up on the principle of subsidiarity, 8 July 2010; https://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/2010_Interlaken_Follow-up_ENG.pdf. Accessed at 10 Nov 2020

  • Kolb R (2016) Theory of International law. Hart, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick ND (1978) Legal reasoning and legal theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (1996) On relevance and justification of judicial decisions. Erkenntnis 44:73–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nettesheim M (2005) Die Aufgaben des Bundespräsidenten. In: Isensee J, Kirchhof P (eds) Handbuch des Staatsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, vol 3, 3rd edn. CF Müller, Heidelberg, pp 1073–1103

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton M, May L (2014) Proportionality in international law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Peers S, Prechal S (2014) Article 52. In: Peers S, Hervey T, Kenner J, Ward A (eds) The EU charter of fundamental rights – a commentary. Hart, Oxford, pp 1455–1521

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peters A (2012) Article 25. In: Simma B, Khan D-E, Nolte G, Paulus A (eds) The Charter of the United Nations – a commentary, vol 1, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 787–854

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2006) Proportionality and variable intensity of review. Camb Law J 65:147–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schabas WA (2015) The European Convention of Human Rights – a commentary. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlaich K, Korioth S (2018) Das Bundesverfassungsgericht, 11th edn. CH Beck, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J-R (1990) Regelmodelle und Prinzipienmodelle des Rechtssystems. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J-R (2002) Grundrechtliche Abwägung als Rechtsanwendung. Das Problem der Begrenzung der Besteuerung. Der Staat 41:385–405

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J-R (2009) Recht als normatives System. Nomos, Baden-Baden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J-R (2018) Rechtsphilosophie. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stone Sweet A, Matthews J (2008) Proportionality balancing and global constitutionalism. Columb J Transnational Law 47:73–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherill S (2016) EU Law, 12th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1971) Legal decision and its justification. In: Hubien H (ed) Le raisonnement juridique – actes du congrès mondial de philosophie du droit et de philosophie sociale. Bruylant, Brussels, pp 409–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1974) Legal syllogism and rationality of judicial decision. Rechtstheorie 5:33–46

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Borowski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Borowski, M. (2021). Limited Review in Balancing Constitutional Rights. In: Sieckmann, JR. (eds) Proportionality, Balancing, and Rights . Law and Philosophy Library, vol 136. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77321-2_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77321-2_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-77320-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-77321-2

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics