Skip to main content

Kant and Existentialism: Inescapable Freedom and Self-Deception

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism and Existentialism

Part of the book series: Palgrave Handbooks in German Idealism ((PHGI))

  • 726 Accesses

Abstract

Fremstedal offers an account of Kant as a predecessor of existentialism. More specifically, Kant is claimed to anticipate existentialism by emphasizing human finitude and holding human consciousness to be characterized by mineness or self-referentiality. In addition, Kant makes human freedom the central philosophical issue, arguing that freedom is inescapable for human agents. Kant not only introduces the influential concept of autonomy, but he also holds that awareness of freedom leads to anxiety, and that anxiety in turn precedes moral evil. Because of moral evil, human agents suffer from self-deception, something that necessitates a radical self-choice, or conversion, by which the agent takes responsibility for himself as a natural and moral being. Finally, Kant prepares the ground for existentialism by developing an existential interpretation of religion that criticizes theodicies and emphasizes the hiddenness of God.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The present text draws partially on Fremstedal 2014 (a book that deals with Kierkegaard’s relation to Kant). References to Critique of Pure Reason use the pagination in the A and B editions (e.g., Kant 2007, A445/B473). All other references to Kant use the volume and pagination in the German Academy edition of Kant’s works (e.g., Kant 1900ff., vol. 6, p. 24).

  2. 2.

    Yet Kant’s ethics anticipates Sartre’s idea of man as a “legislator deciding for the whole of mankind” as well as his view that “the act of lying implies the universal value which it denies” (1975, p. 351). Sartre (1975, p. 366) explicitly agrees to Kant’s view that “freedom is a will both to itself and to the freedom of others.” For Kant’s importance for Kierkegaard’s ethics, see Fremstedal (2014).

  3. 3.

    Although Kant did not develop a phenomenology, he is still one of the forerunners of twentieth-century phenomenology (cf. Engelland 2010).

  4. 4.

    Moreover, Kant argues that “Another can indeed coerce me to do something that is not my end (but only a means to another’s end) but not to make this my end; and yet I can have no end without making it an end for myself” (Kant 1900ff., vol. 6, p. 381).

  5. 5.

    My interpretation here is based on Fremstedal (2020), except that that the present text does not focus on Kierkegaard.

  6. 6.

    Kierkegaard represents an exception here since he tends towards moral realism (Fremstedal 2014, chapter 10).

  7. 7.

    To describe the fall into evil, some Kant scholars rely on the Kierkegaardian notion of a leap of volition developed in The Concept of Anxiety (Muchnik 2009, pp. 93–94; Morgan 2005, p. 77; Fremstedal 2014, p. 250n123).

  8. 8.

    See the chapters on Schelling, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, and Sartre in the present anthology.

  9. 9.

    Kant is concerned with self-deception that tries to ignore the demands of moral freedom. He is hardly concerned with forms of self-deception that exaggerate freedom and understate facticity. Nor does he give a taxonomy of self-deception, as Kierkegaard does (Fremstedal 2014, chapter 3).

  10. 10.

    Like many existentialists, Kant was also highly concerned with freedom of speech, although he struggled with censorship and religious orthodoxy (cf. Kuehn 2001).

  11. 11.

    Kant 1900ff., vol. 7, p. 285; vol. 25, pp. 1367–1368. Sinnesart or “empirical character” belongs to the phenomenal realm and is the sensual sign (sinnliche Zeichen) of man’s “intelligible character,” his noumenal Denkungsart (Wimmer 1990, pp. 101, 130, 151–152, 188).

  12. 12.

    Scheler (1928, p. 51); translated in Louden (2011, p. 67).

  13. 13.

    Both Kant and his commentators seem to describe the antinomy of practical reason in terms of (moral) despair (Kant 1900ff., vol. 28, p. 1076; Marina 2000, p. 354; Kuehn 2001, p. 313; Henrich 2008, p. 102; Wood 1970, p. 160; Wimmer 1990, pp. 68, 156–159, 206).

  14. 14.

    I am indebted to Andrew Chignell and Darrel Moellendorf here.

  15. 15.

    Transcendental arguments represent one of Kant’s most discussed contributions to philosophy. Pereboom (2009) explains, “In Kant’s conception, an argument of this kind begins with an uncontroversial premise about our thought, experience, or knowledge, and then reasons to a substantive and unobvious necessary condition of this premise. Typically, this reasoning from uncontroversial premise to substantive conclusion is intended to be a priori in some sense.” Transcendental arguments can be found in both Kierkegaard and twentieth-century existentialism. Some accounts even identify transcendental and phenomenological methodology (see Engelland 2010, Part III). For Kierkegaard, see Fremstedal (2014, pp. 229–230).

Bibliography

  • Adams, Robert. 1987. The Virtue of Faith and Other Essays in Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allison, Henry. 1995. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. On the Very Idea of a Propensity to Evil. The Journal of Value Inquiry 36: 337–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayer, Oswald. 2007. Theology the Lutheran Way. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beiser, Frederick. 2006. Moral Faith and the Highest Good. In The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy, ed. Paul Guyer, 588–629. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burnham, Douglas, and George Papandreopoulos. 2011. Existentialism. In Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. James Fieser and Bradley Dowden. http://www.iep.utm.edu/existent/. Accessed 1 February 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caswell, Matthew. 2006. Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good, the Gesinnung, and the Theory of Radical Evil. Kant-Studien 97: 184–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chignell, Andrew. 2007. Kant’s Concept of Justification. Noûs 41: 33–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, James. 1967. The Emergence of Philosophy of Religion. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2017. Existentialism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/existentialism. Accessed 8 January 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davenport, John. 2012. Narrative Identity, Autonomy, and Mortality: From Frankfurt and MacIntyre to Kierkegaard. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dorrien, Gary. 2012. Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit: The Idealistic Logic of Modern Theology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engelland, Chad. 2010. The Phenomenological Kant: Heidegger’s Interest in Transcendental Philosophy. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 41: 150–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Formosa, Paul. 2007. Kant on the Radical Evil of Human Nature. The Philosophical Forum 38: 221–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Is Kant a Moral Constructivist or a Moral Realist? European Journal of Philosophy 21: 170–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fremstedal, Roe. 2014. Kierkegaard and Kant on Radical Evil and the Highest Good: Virtue, Happiness, and the Kingdom of God. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Søren Kierkegaard’s Critique of Eudaimonism and Autonomy. In Perfektionismus der Autonomie, ed. Douglas Moggach, Nadine Mooren, and Michael Quante, 291–308. Munich: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, Dieter. 2008. Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1900ff. Gesammelte Schriften, vols. 1–29. Berlin: Reimer (later de Gruyter).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Practical Philosophy. Ed. and Trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001a. Religion and Rational Theology. Ed. and Trans. Allen Wood and George Di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Lectures on Ethics, ed. Peter Heath and Jerome Schneewind. Trans. Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Lectures on Logic. Ed. and Trans. Michael Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and Trans. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Anthropology, History, and Education. Ed. Günter Zöller and Robert Louden, Trans. Mary Gregor, Paul Guyer, Robert Louden, Holly Wilson, Allen Wood, Günter Zöller and Arnulf Zweig. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleingeld, Pauline. 1999. Kant, History, and the Idea of Moral Development. History of Philosophy Quarterly 16: 56–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosch, Michelle. 2006. Freedom and Reason in Kant, Schelling, and Kierkegaard. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuehn, Manfred. 2001. Kant: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Louden, Robert. 2011. Kant’s Human Being: Essays on His Theory of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madore, Joël. 2011. Difficult Freedom and Radical Evil in Kant: Deceiving Reason. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marina, Jacqueline. 2000. Making Sense of Kant’s Highest Good. Kant-Studien 91: 329–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Seiriol. 2005. The Missing Formal Proof of Humanity’s Radical Evil in Kant’s Religion. The Philosophical Review 114: 63–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muchnik, Pablo. 2009. Kant’s Theory of Evil: An Essay on the Dangers of Self-Love and the Aprioricity of History. Lanham, MD: Lexington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neiman, Susan. 1997. The Unity of Reason: Rereading Kant. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, Derek. 2009. Kant’s Transcendental Arguments. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/kant-transcendental. Accessed 4 April 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, Sami, and Sari Kivistö. 2016. Kantian Antitheodicy: Philosophical and Literary Varieties. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinkard, Terry. 2010. German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudd, Anthony. 2012. Self, Value, and Narrative: A Kierkegaardian Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1975. Existentialism is a Humanism. In Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre, ed. Walter Kaufman, 345–369. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, Max. 1928. Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos. Darmstadt: Otto Reichl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulte, Christoph. 1991. Radikal Böse. Die Karriere des Bösen von Kant bis Nietzsche. Munich: Fink.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, Robert. 2012. Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, Jon. 2010. Idealism and Existentialism: Hegel and Twentieth-Century European Philosophy. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Søren Kierkegaard: Subjectivity, Irony and the Crisis of Modernity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Timmermann, Jens. 2013. Divine Existence and Moral Motivation. In Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, ed. Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca, and Margit Ruffing, vols. 1–5, vol. 3, 669–678. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varga, Somogy, and Charles Guignon. 2017. Authenticity. In The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/authenticity. Accessed 25 January 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verstrynge, Karl. 2004. The Perfection of the Kierkegaardian Self in Regulative Perspective. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook, 473–495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welz, Claudia. 2008. Love’s Transcendence and the Problem of Theodicy. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, Reiner. 1990. Kants kritische Religionsphilosophie. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, Allen. 1970. Kant’s Moral Religion. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Kant and the Problem of Human Nature. In Essays on Kant’s Anthropology, ed. Brian Jacobs and Patrick Kain, 38–59. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, John. 2002. Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roe Fremstedal .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Fremstedal, R. (2020). Kant and Existentialism: Inescapable Freedom and Self-Deception. In: Stewart, J. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism and Existentialism. Palgrave Handbooks in German Idealism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-44571-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics