Skip to main content

Essence or Context?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Of Essence and Context

Part of the book series: Numanities - Arts and Humanities in Progress ((NAHP,volume 7))

Abstract

Cast in the form of a gloss on the passage on Hanslick from The Oxford History of Western Music, this essay considers such topics as musical beauty (versus the musical sublime), the relationship of musical form and content, the status of music as an artifact of culture rather than phenomenon of nature, the function of metaphor in the perception and description of music, and the ontological status of musical structure—in all cases framing its formulations as responses to the writing of Nick Zangwill (whose reply will be found in this volume).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Taruskin (2005: 511–513) (Chapter V ‘Music in the Late Twentieth Century’).

  2. 2.

    See Taruskin (2005: 441) (Chapter III ‘Music in the Nineteenth Century’).

  3. 3.

    First enunciated by Edmund Burke one hundred years before Hanslick: Edmund Burke. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful. London, 1757.

  4. 4.

    Quoted in Taruskin (1997: 253).

  5. 5.

    In his answer to me elsewhere in this volume, Nick reverts to his trademark nonchalance, rejecting the whole idea of the sublime as a musical category and adding: “I do not care if a number of famous dead people have said the opposite.” Does he expect me—or you, the reader—to be convinced by a show of bravado? I think it better to seek a formulation on which he and I and the dead people can agree. How about this: Just as he insists that the “musically-beautiful”, hyphen fastidiously in place, is something particular and distinct from other manifestations of the beautiful, why not admit that there is such a thing as the “musically-sublime”, as exemplified pre-eminently by Beethoven’s Schrekensfanfaren? That way one can regard the horror-fanfare as contrasting to, say, the scene by the brook in the Pastoral Symphony, rather than along a spectrum with it. That would seem to accord better with Beethoven’s intent. If the hyphenated term gets by the Zangwill censor, I won’t mind using it, even though I would never insist on it.

  6. 6.

    According to Immanuel Kant:

    If […] we estimate the worth of the fine arts by the culture they supply to the mind, and adopt for our standard the expansion of the faculties whose confluence, in judgement, is necessary for cognition, music, then, since it plays merely with sensations, has the lowest place among the fine arts—just as it has perhaps the highest among those valued at the same time for their agreeableness. (Kant 2007: 158).

  7. 7.

    It may have been the later economist Paul Samuelson, who, purportedly quoting Keynes, actually said it first. See Samuelson (1986: 275).

  8. 8.

    Until his reply to me in this volume, that is, where he dismisses counterexamples to his claims about beauty with a truly Kivian nonchalance: “Who cares about a few avant-garde outliers?”.

  9. 9.

    E.g. Zangwill (2015: 1, 11 (“music itself”), 155 (“music as music”)).

  10. 10.

    See Taruskin (1995b).

  11. 11.

    Quoted frequently in Zangwill (2015: 10). In his answer to me elsewhere in this volume, he says that “when citing Hanslick” he prefers this “pristine and clean” quote to “the musicologist’s favorite ‘tonally moving forms’, because he latter includes a crucial metaphor, of motion, and in the interpretation of that metaphor lie all the controversial issues”. But that metaphor is in my view the essential insight that makes Hanslick valuable, and it seems rather absent-minded not to notice that the phrase “artistic combination”, without which the definition is just a truism (is that what he means by “pristine and clean”?), harbors any number of controversial issues. What Nick seems to be revealing here is that his reading of Hanslick is in fact selective, and to that extent untrustworthy.

  12. 12.

    As translated by Gustav Cohen in 1891, see Hanslick (1957: 11).

  13. 13.

    Here I should have written “category distinction” rather than “categorical”, which suggest that there is no overlap or compatibility. Nick is therefore right to question the word in his reply and I gladly modify it.

  14. 14.

    At least one philosopher, Roger Scruton, insists on the distinction at least as adamantly as I do, writing recently that philosophy “should be intent on distinguishing the human world from the order of nature, and the concepts through which we understand appearances from those used in explaining them”, adding that “for this reason […] I believe aesthetics to be central to philosophy, being the branch of philosophy that deals directly with our most studied attempts to create and discern what is truly meaningful” (Roger Scruton & Timothy Williamson. But Is It Science? Times Literary Supplement, 3 November 2017: 16). To boil down the rest of Scruton’s long argument in terms relevant to the present discussion, natural science looks for essence, humanities (i.e., the study of human artifacts) looks for meaning.

  15. 15.

    And this, of course, is the nub and … well, essence of the difficulty between me and Nick on the matter of essence. In his answer to me elsewhere in this volume, Nick adduces biological organs as things that have mind-independent essence in the same way that music does. But I dispute that on grounds that I have learned from Nick himself. A heart has, as its purpose, the pumping of blood, and it had that purpose even before the purpose was discovered (that is, observed) by science. So its purpose is indeed mind-independent, and if you want to call that purpose its essence, you will get no argument from me. But the artistic combination of tones did not exist before we knew about it, for there was no music until we humans invented it. Hence, no mind-independence, and no essence. To smuggle essence into the description of music or other human artifacts and activities, moreover, by attaching it to other words (as in “essential function” or “essential motives”) fails so long as the words to which it is attached already suffice to describe or define. As far as I am concerned (that is, as far as my descriptive or explanatory needs require), the word “essential” adds nothing to the discussion of musical functions or human motives; it is just a placeholder, like “compositional” when describing what composers do, or “sincere” when describing one’s beliefs. As an experiment, the reader can bracket the word “essential” in Nick’s rebuttal and test whether the meaning is really affected by its removal. If the removal does not change anything substantive, then I believe “essence” to be shown, in effect, inessential to a discussion of music. But its superfluity does not therefore render it innocuous. Essentialist views are normative views. They not only delineate the way things are, but also define the way things must be. We have had quite enough of that in musical writings, whether on musical ontology, on performance practice, or on questions of value.

  16. 16.

    Barnhart 1950.

  17. 17.

    This was a careless error. Actually it was Hanslick who called his own teacher, Václav Tomášek (1774–1850), by this name. I was misremembering this sentence from Eric Sams’ article on Hanslick in the first (1980) edition of the New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians:

    His own phrase for Tomášek in Prague, “the dalai lama of music” might well describe his own eminence not only in Vienna but throughout the German-speaking world, and beyond.

  18. 18.

    See Karnes 2008, esp. Part I ‘Eduard Hanslick and the Challenge of Musikwissenschaft’.

  19. 19.

    See Small 1998; cf. Abbate 2004.

  20. 20.

    See Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. Laokoonoder Über die Grenzen der Malerei und Poesie, 1765.

References

  • Abbate, Carolyn. 2004. Music—Drastic or Gnostic? Critical Inquiry 30 (3): 505–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnhart, Clarence L. (ed.). 1950. American College Dictionary, 1200. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, Karol. 1999. A Theory of Art. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Edmund. 1981. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful (1757). In Music and Aesthetics in the Eighteenth and Early-Nineteenth Centuries, P. le Huray, and J. Day (eds.), 60–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felski, Rita. 2011. Context Stinks! New Literary History XLII: 573–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goehr, Lydia. 2007. The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of Music, revised ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanslick, Eduard. 1957. The Beautiful in Music. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanslick, Eduard. 1986. On the Beautiful in Music. Geoffrey Payzant (transl.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2007. Critique of Judgment. James Creed Meredith (transl.), Nicholas Walker (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karnes, Kevin. 2008. Music, Criticism, and the Challenge of History: Shaping Modern Musical Thought in Late Nineteenth Century Vienna. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kerman, Joseph. 1985. Contemplating Music: Challenges to Musicology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, Peter. 1980. The Corded Shell: Reflections on Musical Expression. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, Peter. 1989. Sound Sentiment: An Essay on the Musical Emotions, Including the Complete Text of the Corded Shell. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Jerrold. 1997. Music in the Moment. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClary, Susan. 1987. Comment: Getting Down off the Beanstalk, The Presence of a Woman’s Voice in Janika Vandervelde’s Genesis II. Minnesota Composers Forum Newsletter, January 1987, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClary, Susan. 1991. Feminine Endings: Music, Gender and Sexuality. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Leonard B. 1998. A Universe of Universals. Journal of Musicology XVI: 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, Paul. 1986. The Keynes Centenary: Sympathy from the Other Cambridge. In The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul Samuelson, Kate Crowley (ed.), 275–278. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumann, Robert. 1969. On Music and Musicians. Konrad Wolff (ed.), Paul Rosenfeld (transl.). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumann, Robert. 2007. Gesammelte Schriften, vol. I. Piero Weiss (transl.). In Music in the Western World: A History in Documents, 2nd ed., Piero Weiss, and Richard Taruskin (eds.). Belmont, CA: Thomson/Schirmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Small, Christopher. 1998. Musicking: The Meanings of Performing and Listening. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaeth, Sigmund. 1936. Great Symphonies: How to Recognize and Remember Them. Garden City, NY: Garden City Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stasov, Vladimir Vasilievich. 1859/1952. Ein Wort der Gegenwart gegen zwei Phrasen der Zukunftgilde. In Niederrheinische Musik-Zeitung, 1859. Reprinted in: V. V. Stasov, 1952. Izbrannïye sochineniya v tryokh tomakh, vol. I. Moscow: Iskusstvo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 1982. Review of the Corded Shell: Reflections on Musical Expression by Peter Kivy. The Musical Quarterly LXVIII: 287–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 1985. Review of Sound and Semblance: Reflections on Musical Representation by Peter Kivy. Journal of Music Theory XXIX: 347–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 1987. Beethoven Symphonies—The New Antiquity. Opus, October 1987, 31–41, 43, 63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 1995a. Text and Act: Essays on Music and Performance. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 1995b. A Myth of the Twentieth Century: The Rite of Spring, the Tradition of the New, and ‘The Music Itself’. Modernism/Modernity II: 1–26; rpt. idem, Defining Russia Musically 360–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 1997. Defining Russia Musically: Historical and Hermeneutical Essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taruskin, Richard. 2005. The Oxford History of Western Music. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, Nick. 2001. The Metaphysics of Beauty. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, Nick. 2015. Music and Aesthetic Reality: Formalism and the Limits of Description. New York, London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Taruskin .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Taruskin, R. (2019). Essence or Context?. In: Stanevičiūtė, R., Zangwill, N., Povilionienė, R. (eds) Of Essence and Context. Numanities - Arts and Humanities in Progress, vol 7. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14471-5_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics