Skip to main content

Husserl and Weyl on the Constitution of Space

The Role of Symbolic Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Weyl and the Problem of Space

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 49))

Abstract

I discuss in this paper Husserl and Weyl’s views on the role of intuition and symbolization in empirical science and their reactions to purely symbolic extensions of mathematical representations of empirical reality. Although both accept that physical space as considered in mathematical physics, for instance, is an intentional construct out of perceptual space that eliminates subjective content of perceptual experience in favor of objective form, thus transforming space as perceived in an empty mathematical manifold, they differ as to the freedom allowed to mathematics to further elaborate this and other mathematical representatives of perceptual reality. Husserl puts serious restrictions to non-eliminable, non-denoting symbolic extensions of representing manifolds, which Weyl, in his more holistic approach, is willing to accept.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the notion of material a priori see da Silva 2016.

  2. 2.

    Provided, of course, pointing happens in a context where it is interpreted as denoting.

  3. 3.

    “[…] this world does not exist in itself, but is merely encountered by us as an object in the correlative variance of subject and object. The world exists only as that met with by an ego, as an appearing to consciousness; the consciousness in this function does not belong to the world, but stands out against the being as the sphere of vision, of meaning, of image, or however else we may call it” (Weyl 1934, 83).

  4. 4.

    For Weyl, objective reality, as an intentional object, relates to experience in a manner that (1) there cannot be incoherent experiences of reality and (2) there cannot be anything in reality that cannot in principle correspond to something in experience (see Weyl 1963, 121–24).

  5. 5.

    “…this objective world, representable only in symbols…[my emphasis]” (Weyl 1963, 120).

  6. 6.

    “The datum of consciousness is the starting-point at which we must place ourselves if we are to understand the absolute meaning as well as the right to the supposition of reality” (Weyl 1952, 5).

  7. 7.

    “It cannot be denied that a theoretical desire, incomprehensible from the merely phenomenal point of view, is alive in us which urges toward totality. Mathematics shows that with particular clarity; but it also teaches us that that desire can be fulfilled on one condition only, namely, that we are satisfied with the symbol and renounce the mystical error of expecting the transcendent ever to fall within the lighted circle of our intuition” (Weyl 1963, 66).

  8. 8.

    See Weyl 1963, 75–78.

  9. 9.

    One can easily distinguish an hierarchy: (1) morphological, quality-filled perceptual space; (2) an abstract and idealized, properly mathematical physical space; and (3) an analytic surrogate of physical space, isomorphic to it and only remotely representing in ideal form the structure discernible in perceptual space.

  10. 10.

    Husserl was quite aware of this possibility: “The solution of problems raised within a theoretical discipline, or one of its theories, can at times derive the most effective methodological help from recourse to the categorial type or (what is the same) to the form of the theory, and perhaps also by going over to a more comprehensive form or class of forms and to its laws” (Husserl 1900, §70).

  11. 11.

    See Husserl 1936/1954.

  12. 12.

    For details see da Silva 2012a, b and 2013a, b.

  13. 13.

    See Weyl 1954, 200.

References

  • Bloch, F. 1976. Heisenberg and the early days of quantum mechanics. Physics Today 29 (12): 23–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • da Silva, J.J. 2012a. Husserl on geometry and spatial representation. Axiomathes 22: 5–30, reprinted in Hill & da Silva 2013, 31–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Away from the facts, symbolic knowledge in Husserl’s philosophy of mathematics. In Symbolic knowledge from Leibniz to Husserl, ed. A.L. Casanave, 115–135. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013a. Husserl and the principle of bivalence. In Hill & da Silva, 285–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. Mathematics and the crisis of science. In Hill & da Silva, 345–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. The analytic/synthetic dichotomy. In Husserl and analytic philosophy, ed. G.E. Rosado Haddock, 35–54. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1891. “Besprechung von E. Schröder, Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik I”, in Husserl 1890–1910, 3–43, published in English as “Review of Ernst Schröder’s Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik” in Husserl 1994, 52–91. Originally published in Göttinger Gelehrte Anzeigen, no 7, 243–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1970. Philosophie der Arithmetik, mit ergänzenden Texten (1890 – 1901), Hua XII, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Early writings in the philosophy of logic and mathematics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Philosophie der Arithmetik. Logische und psychologische Untersuchungen, Bd. I, Pfeffer, Halle a.d.S. 1891. English translation: Philosophy of arithmetic, psychological and logical investigations with supplementary texts from 1887 – 1901 (D. Willard, ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. 1932. The open world: Three lectures on the metaphysical implications of science. In Weyl 2009, 34–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934. Mind and nature. In Weyl 2009, 83–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. ca, 1949. Man and the foundations of science. In: Weyl 2009, 175–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1952. Space, time, matter. New York: Dover. (H. L. Brose, Trans.). from the 4th ed. of Raum, Zeit, Materie, 1921.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1953. Axiomatic versus constructive procedures in mathematics. In Weyl 2012, 191–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1954. The unity of knowledge. In Weyl 2009, 194–2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. New York: Atheneum. Revised and augmented English edition based on a trans. by Olaf Helmer. Parts of the book originally published in Handbuch der Philosophie as Philosophie der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft, 1927.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

da Silva, J.J. (2019). Husserl and Weyl on the Constitution of Space. In: Bernard, J., Lobo, C. (eds) Weyl and the Problem of Space. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 49. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-11527-2_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics