Skip to main content

Kant’s Critical Legacy: Fichte’s Constructionism and Hegel’s Discursive Logic

  • Chapter
The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism

Part of the book series: The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism ((PHGI))

Abstract

This chapter is essentially about Hegel.1 If I bring Fichte conspicuously into the picture, this is for the sake of contrast. There is another reason as well. Common wisdom has it that Fichte was the one who remained the closest to the master in the reception of the Critique of Reason.2 No doubt, Kant’s legacy is broad enough, and in places even ambiguous, that a case can be made to that effect, especially if one concentrates on the legacy’s moral side. But I want to say that, in what counted most, it is Hegel who was Kant’s true inheritor. I shall presently say what I consider as “counting most.” I must first make clear that the Fichte I have in mind is post-Jena — notably the Fichte of 1804 onward, the time when Fichte dropped from his Science the idiom of the “I”; when Hegel, for his part, finally made it to the philosophical stage, and a conversation between the two, albeit always at a distance and perhaps not even ever deliberately intended, was in fact taking shape. The Fichte whom Hegel had in mind in his explicit criticisms was always the author of the early versions of the Wissenschaftslehre. As for Fichte, his primary confrontation was with Schelling3 — not Hegel, to whom he occasionally only alluded. A conversation was nonetheless taking shape between the two, for, whoever their immediate philosophical interlocutor (and Schelling was as much on Hegel’s mind as on Fichte’s), it was with respect to Spinoza’s metaphysics that both, in their contrasting ways, were taking position, and, in so doing, were also staking their respective claims to the Kantian legacy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ...which I have documented elsewhere. Cf. George di Giovanni, “The Unfinished Philosophy of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi,” introduction to The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel “Allwill” by Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, trans. and ed. George di Giovanni (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1994), sect. 2; and George di Giovanni, Freedom and Religion in Kant and His Immediate Successors: The Vocation of Humankind, 1774–1800 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), ch. 1.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. ...as I have documented elsewhere. Maimon’s critique is the philosophically more interesting one. Cf. di Giovanni, Freedom and Religion, 97–104; and George di Giovanni, “The Facts of Consciousness,” introduction to Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, trans. George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, rev. ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2000), 20–27, 32–36.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Thus Karl Rosenkranz, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Leben: Supplement zu Hegels Werke (Berlin: Dunder und Humblot, 1844), 132–44.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Wilfrid Seilars, “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1: The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, ed. Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1956), 298–99.

    Google Scholar 

  5. I am borrowing Gilbert Ryle’s analogy of philosophy as a cartography of mental space. See Gilbert Ryle, “Abstractions,” Dialogue 1, no. 1 (June 1962): 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. In Heinrich Heine’s words, “In the year 1804, the God of Schelling appeared at last in His completed form in a work entitled ‘Philosophy and Religion.’“ And Heine added, “Here philosophy ceases with Schelling, and poetry — I may say folly -commences” (Heinrich Heine, Religion and Philosophy in Germany: A Fragment, trans. John Snodgrass [Boston: Beacon Press, 1959], 151, 152).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2014 George di Giovanni

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

di Giovanni, G. (2014). Kant’s Critical Legacy: Fichte’s Constructionism and Hegel’s Discursive Logic. In: Altman, M.C. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism. The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-33475-6_33

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics